Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-m42fx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-23T22:21:58.646Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

5 - Recognition

Duncan Ivison
Affiliation:
University of Sydney
Get access

Summary

I was in bondage in Missouri, too. I can't say that my treatment was bad. In one respect I say it was not bad, but in another I consider it as bad as could be. I was a slave. That covers it all. I had not the rights of man.

(Benjamin Miller, former slave, quoted in Darby 2006: 430)

Introduction

So far we have been concentrating on theories of rights that are closely aligned to the notion of law, which is not unsurprising. Right and law are indeed closely related. But there are different modes of juridical thought. We have been exploring some of these differences in our discussion of Grotius, Hobbes, Pufendorf, Locke and Kant. The differences between these philosophers are as significant, I think, as their shared commitment to the centrality of law to the language of rights, and to politics more generally. I also noted that civic humanism and republicanism (especially the neo-Roman conceptions of freedom) offered an alternative set of frameworks within which to make sense of rights, or even to displace them in favour of an emphasis on civic virtue. In this chapter we turn to yet another approach to rights, this time embodied in the philosophy of Hegel. Why read Hegel on rights? Well, for one thing, he is an important source for an influential set of critiques of modern liberalism that take aim at the centrality of individual rights (and the social contract) in their accounts of state, society and the self.

Type
Chapter
Information
Rights , pp. 128 - 153
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Recognition
  • Duncan Ivison, University of Sydney
  • Book: Rights
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844653867.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Recognition
  • Duncan Ivison, University of Sydney
  • Book: Rights
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844653867.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Recognition
  • Duncan Ivison, University of Sydney
  • Book: Rights
  • Online publication: 05 February 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/UPO9781844653867.006
Available formats
×