Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-788cddb947-nxk7g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-18T01:08:50.625Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

7 - Personhood and the Ethics of Life

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 April 2013

Justin Buckley Dyer
Affiliation:
University of Missouri, Columbia
Get access

Summary

The central question in the abortion debates, as Richard John Neuhaus long contended, is simply, “Who belongs to the community for which we accept common responsibility?” For many of the most influential voices in the academic debate about the ethics and legality of abortion, the answer to this question hinges on some conception of personhood. “Beginning in the ancient world,” John Rawls noted, “the concept of the person has been understood, in both philosophy and law, as the concept of someone who can take part in, or who can play a role in, social life, and hence exercise and respect its various rights and duties.” A person is a member of the political and social community, whereas a non-person stands outside of that community and can neither claim its rights nor be subject to its obligations.

In his Dred Scott opinion, Roger Taney made such a conception of personhood central to the question of whether African slaves and their descendants could ever claim American citizenship, and Taney’s suggestion that African slaves formed no part of “the people” for whom the Constitution was written was a historical claim about conventional rights and duties. For “more than a century,” Taney maintained, slaves were “regarded as beings of an inferior order . . . and so far inferior that they had no rights which the white man was bound to respect.” Having no legal rights, the slave was “bought and sold, and treated as an ordinary article of merchandise and traffic whenever a profit could be made by it.” Although Taney’s simplistic reading of history was challenged by the dissenting opinions of Benjamin Curtis and John McLean, it was of course true that slaves were treated as property, and therefore something less than full persons, throughout much of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Neuhaus, Richard John, “The End of Abortion and the Meaning of ‘Christian America,’First Things (June/July 2001), 67Google Scholar
Rawls, John, Political Liberalism, expanded edition (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005 [1993]), 18Google Scholar
Blassingame, John W., ed., The Frederick Douglass Papers Series One: Speeches, Debates, and Interviews, 5 vols. (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985), Vol. 3, 169
Forsythe, Clarke D., Politics for the Greatest Good: The Case for Prudence in the Public Square (Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 2009)Google Scholar
Casey, Robert’s speech on the steps of the courthouse in St. Louis (a deliberate allusion to Dred Scott), reprinted as “Law Without Honor,” Human Life Review 19, no. 2 (Spring 1993), 54–64Google ScholarPubMed
Giubilini, Alberto and Minerva, Fransesca, “After-Birth Abortion: Why Should the Baby Live?”Journal of Medical Ethics (2012) , 2Google Scholar
Rawls, , Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 2005), 1§3 (pp. 15–22) and 1§5 (pp. 29–35)Google Scholar
Thomson, Judith Jarvis, “Abortion,” Boston Review (Summer 1995),
Finnis, John, “The Rights and Wrongs of Abortion: A Reply to Judith Thomson,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 2, no. 2 (1973), 132.
Wertheimer, Roger, “Understanding the Abortion Argument,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 1, no. 1 (1971), 78Google Scholar
Tooley, Michael, “Abortion and Infanticide,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 2, no. 1 (1972), 37–38Google Scholar
Singer, Peter, Practical Ethics, 3rd ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 160–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, Jeff, “Challenges to Human Equality,” The Journal of Ethics 12, no. 1 (2008), 104Google Scholar
Kaczor, Christopher, The Ethics of Abortion: Women’s Rights, Human Life, and the Question of Justice (New York: Routledge, 2011), 93Google Scholar
Kavanaugh, John F., S.J., Who Counts as Persons? Human Identity and the Ethics of Killing (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2001), 67Google Scholar
George, Robert P. and Lee, Patrick, Body-Self Dualism in Contemporary Ethics and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008)Google Scholar
Lewis, C. S., The Complete C. S. Lewis Signature Classics (New York: HarperCollins, 2002), 265Google Scholar
Channing, Walter, “Effects of Criminal Abortion,” Boston Medical and Surgical Journal LX, no. 7 (March 17, 1859), 135; 139CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hale, Edwin, Treatise on Criminal Abortion (Chicago: C. S. Halsey, 1866), 313Google Scholar
Storer, Horatio Robinson, Why Not? A Book for Every Woman (Boston: Lee and Shepard, 1866), 15Google Scholar
Hitchcock, Homer, “Report on Criminal Abortion,” Fourth Annual Report of the Secretary of the State Board of Health of the State of Michigan (Lansing, MI: W. S. George & Co., 1876), 58Google Scholar
Nebinger, Andrew, “Criminal Abortion: Its Extent and Prevention,” Transactions of the Medical Society of the State of Pennsylvania at its Twenty-Seventh Annual Session, XI, Part I (Philadelphia, 1876), 119Google Scholar
Eaton, M. M., “Four and A-Half Inches of Whalebone in the Uterus. – Abortion – Narrow Escape from Death,” Chicago Medical Examiner IX, no. 4 (April 1868), 218Google Scholar
Dixon-Jones, Mary A., “Criminal Abortion. Its Evils and Its Sad Consequences,” Medical Record XLVI, no. 1 (July 7, 1894), 10Google Scholar
Harris, C. H., “Special Operation for Abortion,” New York Gynecological Journal (September, 1892), 842Google Scholar
McMahan, Jeff, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life (New York: Oxford University Press, 2008), 22Google Scholar
Singer, Peter, Rethinking Life and Death: The Collapse of Our Traditional Ethics (New York: St. Martin’s, 1995), 1Google Scholar
Planned Parenthood v. Casey 505 U.S. 833, 851 (1992) (O’Connor, Kennedy, and Souter, JJ.).
Lawrence v. Texas 539 U.S. 538, 588 (2003) (Scalia, J., dissenting).
Thomson, Judith Jarvis, “In Defense of Abortion,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 1, no. 1 (1971), 47–66Google Scholar
McDonagh, Eileen, “The Case of the Missing Frame: Abortion as Self-Defense,” Historical Methods 40, no. 4 (2007), 190Google Scholar
McDonagh, ’s Breaking the Abortion Deadlock: From Choice to Consent (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996)Google Scholar
Reader, Soran, “Abortion, Killing, and Maternal Moral Authority,” Hypatia 23, no. 1 (2008), 134CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomson, , “Abortion,” Boston Review (1995).
Hegeman, Roxana, “Abortion Doctor’s Killer Says He Has No Regrets,” Associated Press (10 February 2010).
Hinton, Richard J., John Brown and His Men (New York: Funk and Wagnalls Co., 1894), 398Google Scholar
Jefferis, Jennifer, Armed for Life: The Army of God and Anti-Abortion Terror in the United States (Santa Barbara, CA: ABC-CLIO, 2011)Google Scholar
Risen, James and Thomas, Judy L., Wrath of Angels: The American Abortion War (New York: Basic Books, 1998), 78–100Google Scholar
Shields, Jon A., “What Abortionist Killers Believe,” The Weekly Standard 14, no. 38 (June 22, 2009)Google Scholar
Bray, Michael, A Time to Kill: A Study Concerning the Use of Force and Abortion (Portland, OR: Advocates for Life Publications, 1994), 67.Google Scholar
Thoreau, Henry David, “A Plea for Captain Brown,” in Redpath, James, Echoes of Harper’s Ferry (Boston: Thayer and Eldridge, 1860), 17–43Google Scholar
Garrison, William Lloyd, “Speech of William Lloyd Garrison,” Liberator (December 16, 1859), 198Google Scholar
McAleer, G. J., To Kill Another: Homicide and Natural Law (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 2010)Google Scholar
“Killing Abortionists: A Symposium,” First Things (December 1994).
Green, Clifford J., “Pacifism and Tyrannicide: Bonhoeffer’s Christian Peace Ethic,” Studies in Christian Ethics 18, no. 31 (2005), 32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dietrich Bonhoeffer Works, Volume 6: Ethics, Green, Clifford J., trans. and ed. (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press, 2005), 25 n. 98Google Scholar
Schama, Simon, The American Future: A History (New York: HarperCollins, 2010), 183Google Scholar
Shields, Jon A., “Almost Human: Ambivalence in the Pro-Choice and Pro-Life Movements,” Critical Review 23, no. 4 (2011), 512CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Eric, “The Tragedy of Equality,” The New Atlantis (Fall 2004/Winter 2005), 106Google ScholarPubMed
Kass, Leon, foreword to Human Cloning and Human Dignity: The Report of the President’s Council on Bioethics (New York: Perseus Books, 2002), xv–xviGoogle Scholar
Schaub, Diana, “Slavery plus Abortion,” The Public Interest (Winter 2003), 46Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×