Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-gvh9x Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T12:50:25.766Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Freedom of Expression, Political Fraud, and the Dilemma of Anonymity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 August 2010

Austin Sarat
Affiliation:
Amherst College, Massachusetts
Get access

Summary

Introduction: The Right Not to Speak as the Right of Expression

One of the long-accepted paradoxes of both the doctrine and theory of free expression is that the constitutional right to speak subsumes the constitutional right not to speak. A closer look at the underpinnings of the right not to speak, however, makes clear why it is properly thought to fall within the bounds of the First Amendment's guarantee of free expression. Governmentally compelled expression breaches the wall between government and individual that is essential to the viability of a liberal democracy. It therefore undermines the values fostered by free expression in a variety of important ways.

A traditionally recognized subcategory of the constitutional guarantee of silence is the right of anonymity – in other words, the right not to reveal one's identity when exercising one's affirmative right to express oneself. In one important sense, of course, the right of anonymity qualitatively differs from the right not to speak. While the latter could be construed to apply to a generic right to keep silent, the right of anonymity represents an expressive hybrid. It applies when and only when one first chooses to speak, write, or associate for political purposes. The right of anonymity, then, is a selective form of expressive silence: it is only when the speaker first affirmatively chooses to speak that this form of silence comes into play.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Redish, Martin H., Money Talks: Speech, Economic Power and the Values of Democracy (New York: New York University Press, 2001), 174–8.Google Scholar
Meiklejohn, Alexander, Political Freedom: The Constitutional Powers of the People (New York: Harper, 1960).Google Scholar
Redish, Martin H., Money Talks: Speech, Economic Power and the Values of Democracy (New York: New York University Press, 2001), 175.Google Scholar
Meiklejohn, Alexander, “The First Amendment Is an Absolute,” Supreme Court Review (1962): 245.Google Scholar
Baker, C. Edwin, Human Liberty and Freedom of Speech (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989).Google Scholar
Baker, C. Edwin, “Realizing Self-Realization: Corporate Political Expenditures and Redish's The Value of Free Speech,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 130 (1982): 646.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redish, Martin H., “Self-Realization, Democracy, and Freedom of Expression: A Reply to Professor Baker,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 130 (1982): 678CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redish, Martin H., “Commercial Speech, First Amendment Intuitionism and the Twilight Zone of Viewpoint Discrimination,” Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review 41 (2007): 67.Google Scholar
Barron, Jerome A., “Access to the Press – A New First Amendment Right,” Harvard Law Review 80 (1967): 1641.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calabresi, Guido and Bobbitt, Philip, Tragic Choices (New York: Norton, 1978).Google Scholar
Redish, Martin H. and Mollen, Abby Marie, “Understanding Post's and Meiklejohn's Mistakes: Adversary Democracy and the Theory of Free Expression,” Northwestern University Law Review 103, (2009): 1303.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart (1859), On Liberty (London: J. W. Parker).Google Scholar
Redish, Martin H. (1984), Freedom of Expression: A Critical Analysis (Charlottesville: Michie Co.,), 46.Google Scholar
Wellington, Harry, “On Freedom of Expression,” Yale Law Journal 88 (1979): 1105, 1130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redish, Martin H., “The Adversary System, Democratic Theory, and the Constitutional Role of Self-Interest: The Tobacco Wars, 1953–1971,” DePaul Law Review 51 (2001): 359.Google Scholar
Redish, Martin H., The Logic of Persecution: Free Expression and the McCarthy Era (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×