Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T21:55:21.442Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Africa and the Imperative of philosophy: A Skeptical Consideration

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 May 2014

Extract

The African Studies Association in 1984 gave Paulin Hountondji a share in the Melville Herskovits award for the most significant Africanist publication for the previous year. The selection of Hountondji's book, African Philosophy: Myth and Reality (1983), suggests, logically, that the Association believes the book to be a significant contribution to African Studies. One might go even a step further and conclude that it indicates the Association's concurrence with the main premises and the general philosophical orientation of the author's arguments. This paper outlines some serious questions Hountondji and his fellow philosophers raise about what one's attitude to the African past should be and what criteria should dictate the course of development on the African continent.

Hountondji is perhaps the best known of the “professional philosophers.” As one would expect, each of the philosophers perceives the issues that will be raised in this discussion from a different perspective, even when they agree broadly on the critique of ethnophilosophy; Hountondji has nevertheless emerged as the most articulate and representative in this regard, to the extent that his book has earned the title, “the ‘bible’ of anti—ethnophilosophers” (Mudimbe, 1985: 199). The focus of this essay will accordingly be on this important work, with occasional references, of course, to those of others, in particular the Ghanaian Kwasi Wiredu. This strategy has the attraction of straddling the divide between Anglophone and Francophone manifestations of the new philosophical attitudes.

To best understand what grounds there might be for objections to certain of the philosophers' positions, it is expedient that one isolate the several targets of their disparagement. Chief of these is ethnophilosophy, which Hountondji (1983: 34) defines as “an ethnological work with philosophical pretensions.” This includes the works of all those who like Placide Tempels, Alexis Kagame, John Mbiti, and other ethnologists have attempted to articulate African philosophies or systems of thought. Another target is African cultures or traditions themselves, as distinct from whatever the ethnophilosophers or ethnologists might correctly or mistakenly have made of them.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © African Studies Association 1987

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Achebe, Chinua. 1960. No Longer At Ease. Conn.: Fawcett.Google Scholar
Apostel, Leo. 1981. African Philosophy: Myth or Reality? Gent, Belgium: Scientific Publishers, E Story-Scientia.Google Scholar
Ayoade, John A. A. 1984. “Time in Yoruba Thought,” pp. 93112 in Wright, Richard A. (ed.) African Philosophy: An Introduction. Lanham: University Press of America.Google Scholar
Ayres, C. E. 1927. Science: The False Messiah. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company.Google Scholar
Baran, Paul A. 1957. The Political Economy of Growth. New York: Monthly Review Press.Google Scholar
Bauer, P. T. 1976. Dissent on Development: Studies and Debates in Development. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bochenski, I. M. 1961. Contemporary European Philosophy. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Bodunrin, P. O. 1984. “The Question of African Philosophy,” pp. 124 in Wright, Richard A. (ed. ) African Philosophy: An Introduction. Lanham: University Press of America.Google Scholar
Cornford, Francis Macdonald. 1957. From Religion to Philosophy. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Cornford, Francis Macdonald. 1978. Before and After Socrates. Cambridge: The University Press.Google Scholar
Finnegan, Ruth. 1970. Oral Literature in Africa. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Frankfort, Henri, et al 1946. The Intellectual Adventure of Ancient Man: An Essay on Speculative Thought in the Ancient Near East. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Frankfort, Henri, et al 1956. The Birth of Civilization in the Near East. Garden City: Doubleday Anchor.Google Scholar
Freeman, Kathleen. 1966. The Pre-Socratic Philosophers. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Griaule, M. 1965. Conversations with Ogotemmeli: An Introduction to Dogon Religious Ideas. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hallen, Barry and Sodipo, J. O.. 1986. Knowledge, Belief & Witchcraft: Analytic Experiments in African Philosophy. London: Ethnographica.Google Scholar
Horton, Robin. 1970. “African Traditional Thought and Western Science,” pp. 131–71 in Wilson, Bryan R. (ed. ) Rationality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Horton, Robin. 1980. “Distances,” Recherche, Pédagogie et Culture 49, IX: 2733.Google Scholar
Horton, Robin. 1981. “Que peut la Philosophie?Présence Africaine 119: 4771.Google Scholar
Hountondji, Paulin. 1983. African Philosophy: Myth and Reality. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Idowu, E. Bolaji. 1963. Olodumare: God in Yoruba Belief. New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
Irele, Abiola. 1983. “Introduction,” in Hountondji, Paulin. African Philosophy: Myth and Reality. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Jahn, Janheinz. 1961. Muntu: An Outline of Neo-African Culture. New York: Grove Press.Google Scholar
Kagame, Alexis. 1956. La Philosophie Bantou- Rwandaise de l'Etre. Brussels: Arsom.Google Scholar
Karp, Ivan. 1980. “Beer Drinking and Social Experience in an African Society: An Essay in Formal Sociology,” pp. 83119 in Karp, Ivan and Bird, Charles S. (eds.) Explorations in African Systems of Thought. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Keita, Lancinay. 1984. “The African Philosophical Tradition,” pp. 5776 in Wright, Richard A. (ed. ) African Philosophy: An Introduction. Lanham: University Press of America.Google Scholar
Malinowski, Bronislaw. 1954. Magic, Science and Religion and Other Essays. Garden City: Doubleday Anchor.Google Scholar
Mbiti, John S. 1969. African Religion and Philosophy. New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
Messenger, John C Jr. 1965. “The Role of Proverbs in a Nigerian Judicial System,” pp. 299307 in Dundes, Alan (ed.) The Study of Folklore. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, Inc. Google Scholar
Mudimbe, V. Y. 1985. “African Gnosis,” The African Studies Review 28, 2/3: 149233.Google Scholar
Owomoyela, Oyekan. 1985. “Proverbs: Exploration of an African Philosophy of Social Communication,” Ba Shiru: A Journal of African Language and Literature 12/1: 316.Google Scholar
Tempels, Placide. 1969. Bantu Philosophy. Paris: Présence Africaine.Google Scholar
Turner, Victor. 1984. “Liminality and the Performative Genres,” pp. 1941 in MacAloon, John J. (ed.) Rite, Drama, Festival, Spectacle: Rehearsals Toward a Theory of Cultural Performance. Philadelphia: ISHI.Google Scholar
Wilbur, J. B. and Allen, H. J. (eds.). 1979. The World of the Early Greek Philosophers. Buffalo: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Wiredu, Kwasi. 1980. Philosophy and an African Culture. Cambridge: The University Press.Google Scholar
Wiredu, J. E. 1984. “How Not to Compare African Thought with Western Thought,” pp. 149–62 in Wright, Richard A. (ed.) African Philosophy: An Introduction. Lanham: University Press of America.Google Scholar