Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T20:55:42.657Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Massive redeployment or distributed modularity?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 October 2010

Alexia Toskos Dils
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305. atoskos@stanford.edusflus@stanford.edu
Stephen J. Flusberg
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305. atoskos@stanford.edusflus@stanford.edu

Abstract

In distinguishing itself from other distributed approaches to cognition, Anderson's theory of neural reuse is susceptible to some of the same criticisms that have been leveled at modular approaches. Specifically, neural reuse theories state that: (1) the “working” of a given brain circuit is fixed, rather than shaped by its input, and (2) that high-level cognitive behaviors can be cleanly mapped onto a specific set of brain circuits in a non-contextualized manner.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Chao, L. L. & Martin, A. (2000) Representation of manipulable man-made objects in the dorsal stream. NeuroImage 12:478–84.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1983) The modularity of mind. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinker, S. (1997) How the mind works. Norton.Google Scholar
Rumelhart, D. E. & McClelland, J. L (1986) Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, G. (1949) The concept of mind. Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Sharma, J., Angelucci, A. & Sur, M. (2000) Induction of visual orientation modules in auditory cortex. Nature 404:841–47.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thelen, E. & Smith, L. B. (1994) A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Toskos Dils, A., & Boroditsky, L. (forthcoming) A motion aftereffect from literal and metaphorical motion language: Individual differences. To appear in: Proceedings of the 32nd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Austin, TX, ed. Ohlsson, S. & Catrambone, R.. Cognitive Science Society.Google Scholar
Tucker, M. & Ellis, R. (1998) On the relations between seen objects and components of potential actions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 24:830–46.Google ScholarPubMed
Uttal, W. R. (2001) The new phrenology: The limits of localizing cognitive processes in the brain. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E. & Rosch, E. (1991) The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press.Google Scholar
von Melchner, L., Pallas, L. L. & Sur, M. (2000) Visual behavior mediated by retinal projections directed to the auditory pathway. Nature (London) 404:871–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar