Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-wbk2r Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-01T04:12:53.495Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Taking an engineer's view: Implications of network analysis for computational psychiatry

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

A. David Redish
Affiliation:
Department of Neuroscience, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, MN 55455. redish@umn.edu
Rebecca Kazinka
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, MN 55455. kazin003@umn.edu
Alexander B. Herman
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, MN 55455. herma686@umn.edu

Abstract

An engineer's viewpoint on psychiatry asks: What are the failure modes that underlie psychiatric dysfunction? And: How can we modify the system? Psychiatry has made great strides in understanding and treating disorders using biology; however, failure modes and modification access points can also exist extrinsically in environmental interactions. The network analysis suggested by Borsboom et al. in the target article provides a new viewpoint that should be incorporated into current theoretical constructs, not placed in opposition to them.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Borsboom et al. challenge the notion that the brain should occupy a privileged position in mental health nosology and science, contending instead that symptom networks reflect the best units of analysis. However, psychiatry has made great strides in understanding and treating disorders using biology, and it is naïve to assume that because the model does not completely account for the full complexity, it is therefore useless.

Because all behavior arises from brain function, neurobiology is obviously critical for understanding psychiatric phenomena and not simply an example of “local reduction” of symptom networks. However, we think that the authors do have an important point that has not been incorporated well into current psychiatric reasoning: namely, that the trajectory of interactions with the external environment contains consequence chains that provide additional access points for treatment.

It is important to remember that psychiatric problems are not simply social constructs, but lead to real devastating consequences. For example, a patient with obsessive-compulsive disorder (OCD) unable to stop compulsive hand-washing is damaging their skin, leading to an increased risk of infection (Swedo et al. Reference Swedo, Rapoport, Leonard, Lenane and Cheslow1989) – certainly not something one would want anywhere, especially in a plague situation.

To help patients overcome their difficulties, we take an engineer's point of view, which asks two questions: (1) What are the failure modes that underlie psychiatric dysfunction? and (2) How can we modify the system?

The concept of a failure mode comes from reliability engineering – it recognizes that the structure of a process has specific ways in which it can fail. If we understood how environmental and neurobiological effects lead to behavior, then we could identify how this interaction can fail (MacDonald et al. Reference MacDonald, Zick, Netoff, Chafee, Redish and Gordon2016; Redish Reference Redish2013; Redish et al. Reference Redish, Jensen and Johnson2008). We agree that it is unrealistic to think that only the brain impacts disease – these failure modes may also be occurring outside of the individual's brain, that is, in the extended world.

Neurobiological effects on behavior have to be understood computationally, as information processing (Redish Reference Redish2013). While these definitely have environmental interactions, the way to understand this is through quantitative theory. We believe that the network analysis that the authors propose here can provide an important contribution to quantifying the brain-environment interaction in computational models. Once you go to these theoretical models, the problem of reductionism falls away. The question is not whether an emergent phenomenon exists at a lower level, but rather how lower-level effects combine to produce the emergent phenomenon. This more-nuanced scientific discussion can be seen in the emergent phenomenon of traffic: Traffic on city streets is something that emerges only from structure. However, we can derive very accurate models of traffic patterns from understanding the underlying phenomena (physical structures of cars, timing of traffic lights, reaction times of typical drivers, etc.) (Seibold Reference Seibold2015). The fact that traffic is an emergent network phenomenon does not mean that we can't reduce it to a complex interaction of other parts. It just means that we need to understand both the parts and their interaction.

The target article provides an important insight that has not been included in current theoretical conceptualizations: that some of these failure modes arise not from neurobiological failures, but from environmental failures that neurobiological systems are unable to cope with. Thus, for example, sleeplessness causes anxiety (Ohayon & Roth Reference Ohayon and Roth2003), but anxiety can cause sleeplessness (Marcks et al. Reference Marcks, Weisberg, Edelen and Keller2010), which could lead to a spiraling dysfunction. Intrusive memories in posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD) are episodic, not semantic (Shay Reference Shay1994; Talarico & Rubin Reference Talarico and Rubin2003), and may arise from insufficient neural memory consolidation during sleep (McClelland et al. Reference McClelland, McNaughton and O'Reilly1995; Payne & Nadel Reference Payne and Nadel2004; Rasch & Born Reference Rasch and Born2013; Redish Reference Redish2013). Even if normal consolidation processing were intact, a patient with PTSD unable to sleep might be unable to consolidate memory due to the lack of sleep and would remain subject to episodic flashbacks. If this scenario were true, it would mean that concentrating research looking for dysfunction in the neural system's underlying consolidation may be less fruitful (practically) than finding ways to facilitate an intact consolidation process.

Similarly, one could imagine scenarios in which treatment can use intact neural systems to bypass dysfunctional failure modes through modification of environmental components. For example, we have proposed that contingency management (a behavioral treatment in which addicts are rewarded monetarily for not taking drugs [Petry Reference Petry2011]) works, in part, by shifting the decision process from a dysfunctional habit-based system into a non-dysfunctional deliberative system (Regier & Redish Reference Regier and Redish2015). If this hypothesis is correct, then this treatment is bypassing, not curing, the brain dysfunction. Thinking about the interaction of brain and world provides alternative controls for treatment. Importantly, however, this proposal requires understanding the neuroscience underlying the information processing because it implies that we need to test for the intactness of the deliberative neural system before assigning someone to contingency management.

While extrinsic causal chains are discussed in the psychiatric literature, as in the widely taught “biopsychosocial model” (Frances Reference Frances2014), they remain non-computational word-theories, which make them difficult to implement practically. Network analysis provides a mathematical toolbox to study these brain-behavior interactions, whether the causal chains arise from brain or environmental dysfunction. Importantly, network analysis is not atheoretical, and the network analysis requires hypothesized constructs. Network analysis applied to a taxonomy of DSM-based symptoms will produce one answer (American Psychiatric Association 2013; Borsboom et al. Reference Borsboom, Cramer, Schmittmann, Epskamp and Waldorp2011), while a network analysis run over the Research Domain Criteria (RDoC; Flagel et al. Reference Flagel, Pine, Ahmari, First, Friston, Mathys, Redish, Schmack, Smoller, Thapar, Redish and Gordon2016; Insel Reference Insel2014; National Institute of Mental Health 2018) or decision-making constructs (Rangel et al. Reference Rangel, Camerer and Montague2008; Redish Reference Redish2013; Redish et al. Reference Redish, Jensen and Johnson2008) will produce another. It will require collaborations with experimental and clinical psychiatrists to determine which of these taxonomies provide better explanation of the data and whether these tools can aid in practical psychiatric treatment.

Psychiatry has made tremendous progress over the last century, and computational psychiatry has opened up new ways of understanding the interactions of brain and behavior over the last decade (Huys et al. Reference Huys, Maia and Frank2016; Redish & Gordon Reference Redish and Gordon2016). We think that network analysis has a part to play, but it needs to be incorporated into the current theoretical constructs, not placed in opposition to them.

References

American Psychiatric Association (2013) Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders, 5th edition (DSM-5). American Psychiatric Association.Google Scholar
Borsboom, D., Cramer, A. O., Schmittmann, V. D., Epskamp, S. & Waldorp, L. J. (2011) The small world of psychopathology. PLoS One 6(11):e27407. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0027407.Google Scholar
Flagel, S. B., Pine, D. S., Ahmari, S. E., First, M. B., Friston, K. J., Mathys, C., Redish, A. D., Schmack, K., Smoller, J. W. & Thapar, A. (2016) A novel framework for improving psychiatric diagnostic nosology. In: Computational psychiatry: New perspectives on mental illness, ed. Redish, A. D. & Gordon, J. A., Ch. 10, pp. 167–99. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Frances, A. (2014) Resuscitating the biopsychosocial model. The Lancet Psychiatry 1:496–97.Google Scholar
Huys, Q. J., Maia, T. V. & Frank, M. J. (2016) Computational psychiatry as a bridge from neuroscience to clinical applications. Nature Neuroscience 19(3):404–13. doi: 10.1038/nn.4238.Google Scholar
Insel, T. R. (2014) The NIMH Research Domain Criteria (RDoC) project: Precision medicine for psychiatry. American Journal of Psychiatry 171(4):395–97.Google Scholar
MacDonald, A. W. III, Zick, J. L., Netoff, T. I. & Chafee, M. V. (2016) The computation of collapse: Can reliability engineering shed light on mental illness? In: Computational psychiatry: New perspectives on mental illness, ed. Redish, A. D. & Gordon, J. A., Ch. 9, pp. 153–66. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Marcks, B. A., Weisberg, R. B., Edelen, M. O. & Keller, M. B. (2010) The relationship between sleep disturbance and the course of anxiety disorders in primary care patients. Psychiatry Research 178(3):487–92.Google Scholar
McClelland, J. L., McNaughton, B. L. & O'Reilly, R. C. (1995) Why there are complementary learning systems in the hippocampus and neocortex: Insights from the successes and failures of connectionist models of learning and memory. Psychological Review 102(3):419–57.Google Scholar
National Institute of Mental Health. (2018) Research Domain Criteria (RDoC). Available at: https://www.nimh.nih.gov/research-priorities/rdoc.Google Scholar
Ohayon, M. M. & Roth, T. (2003) Place of chronic insomnia in the course of depressive and anxiety disorders. Journal of Psychiatric Research 37(1):915.Google Scholar
Payne, J. D. & Nadel, L. (2004) Sleep, dreams, and memory consolidation: The role of the stress hormone cortisol. Learning and Memory 11(6):671–78.Google Scholar
Petry, N. M. (2011) Contingency management for substance abuse treatment. Routledge.Google Scholar
Rangel, A., Camerer, C. & Montague, P. R. (2008) A framework for studying the neurobiology of value-based decision making. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 9(7):545–56. Available at: https://www.nature.com/articles/nrn2357.Google Scholar
Rasch, B. & Born, J. (2013) About sleep's role in memory. Physiological Reviews 93(2):681766.Google Scholar
Redish, A. D. (2013) The mind within the brain: How we make decisions and how those decisions go wrong. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Redish, A. D. & Gordon, J. A. (2016) Computational psychiatry: New perspectives on mental illness. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Redish, A. D., Jensen, S. & Johnson, A. (2008) A unified framework for addiction: vulnerabilities in the decision process. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31:415–87.Google Scholar
Regier, P. S. & Redish, A. D. (2015) Contingency management and deliberative decision-making processes. Frontiers in Psychiatry 6: article 76. (Online publication). doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2015.00076. Available at: https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyt.2015.00076/full.Google Scholar
Seibold, B. (2015) A mathematical introduction to traffic flow theory. IPAM Tutorials. Available at: http://helper.ipam.ucla.edu/publications/tratut/tratut_12985.pdf.Google Scholar
Shay, J. (1994) Achilles in Vietnam: Combat trauma and the undoing of character. Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
Swedo, S. E., Rapoport, J. L., Leonard, H., Lenane, M. & Cheslow, D. (1989) Obsessive–compulsive disorder in children and adolescents: Clinical phenomenology of 70 consecutive cases. Archives of General Psychiatry 46:335–41.Google Scholar
Talarico, J. M. & Rubin, D. C. (2003) Confidence, not consistency, characterizes flashbulb memories. Psychological Science 14(5):455–61.Google Scholar