Article contents
‘God Hath Ordained to Man a Helper’: Hobbes, Patriarchy and Conjugal Right
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 27 January 2009
Extract
There are two conflicting and equally misleading interpretations of Hobbes: either he is a patri-archalist like Filmer – but the premise of Hobbes's theory is that political right originates in maternal not paternal lordship; or he is an anti-patriarchalist – but he endorses the subjection of wives to husbands in civil society. To appreciate how Hobbes turns mother right into a specifically modern, non-paternal form of patriarchy, an understanding is required of his peculiar view of the family as a protective association of master and servants that originates in conquest (contract). Secondly, a conjectural history of the defeat of women by men in the natural condition and their incorporation into ‘families’ has to be provided. The overthrow of mother right enables men to enter the original contract, to create Leviathan in their own image, and to secure the fruits of their conquest by establishing patriarchal political right, exercised in large part as conjugal right.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1989
References
1 The arguments are those, respectively, of Chapman, Richard A., ‘Leviathan Writ Small: Thomas Hobbes on the Family’, American Political Science Review, 69 (1975), 76–90, at p. 77CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Zvesper, John, ‘Hobbes' Individualistic Analysis of the Family’, Politics (UK), 5 (1985), 28–33 at p. 33CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For references to other discussions of Hobbes and patriarchy see Chapman, , ‘Leviathan Writ Small’, p. 76, fns 2–14.Google Scholar
2 Hampton, Jean, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986).Google Scholar
3 Contemporary feminist arguments about patriarchy are discussed in Pateman, Carole, The Sexual Contract (Cambridge: Polity Press; Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988), chap. 2.Google Scholar
4 Hobbes, Thomas, Philosophical Rudiments Concerning Government and Society [the English version of De Cive], in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury [hereafter EW] (London: John Bohn, 1841), vol. II, chap. VIII, p. 109.Google Scholar
5 di Stephane, Christine, ‘Masculinity as Ideology in Political Theory: Hobbesian Man Considered’, Women's Studies International Forum, 6 (1983), 633–44, at p. 638.Google Scholar
6 Leslie Stephen in 1904; cited by Schochet, Gordon, Patriarchalism in Political Thought (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975), p. 234.Google Scholar
7 Hinton, R. W. K., ‘Husbands, Fathers and Conquerors’, Political Studies, 16 (1968), 55–67, at p. 57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
8 This section draws on Pateman, , The Sexual Contract, chap. 4.Google Scholar
9 Schochet, , Patriarchalism in Political Thought, p. 193.Google Scholar
10 Schochet, , Patriarchalism in Political Thouyht, p. 16.Google Scholar
11 SirFilmer, Robert, Patriarcha, or the Natural Powers of the Kings of England Asserted and Other Political Works, ed. Laslett, Peter (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1949), p. 241; p. 283Google Scholar. Genesis, too, can be interpreted in more than one way, and equality of men and women in the sight of God is not incompatible with male supremacy in human affairs; e.g. Calvin argued from both the perspective of cognitio dei (the eternal, Divine perspective in which all things are equal) and the perspective of cognitio hominis (the worldly perspective in which humans are hierarchically ordered). See Potter, Mary, ‘Gender Equality and Gender Hierarchy in Calvin's Theology’, Signs, 11 (1986), 725–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
12 Locke, John, Two Treatises of Government, 2nd edn, Laslett, Peter, ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967), Bk II, 2.Google Scholar
13 Filmer, , Patriarcha, p. 245.Google Scholar
14 Hobbes, , Leviathan, in EW, vol. III, chap. XX, p. 187.Google Scholar
15 Hobbes, , Leviathan, pp. 186–7.Google Scholar
16 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XIV, pp. 124–5.Google Scholar
17 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XX, p. 186.Google Scholar
18 Hobbes, , Philosophical Rudiments, chap. IX, p. 116.Google Scholar
19 Hobbes, , Leviathan, p. 188.Google Scholar
20 For an account of the controversy, see Coward, Rosalind, Patriarchal Precedents (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983), chap. 2Google Scholar. See also Pateman, , The Sexual Contract, chap. 2.Google Scholar
21 King, Preston, The Ideology of Order (London: Allen & Unwin, 1974), p. 203.Google Scholar
22 King, , The Ideology of Order, p. 206; p. 205Google Scholar. Hobbes's most recent biographer suggests that his argument about mother-right derives from his own experience as a child. Hobbes's views perhaps ‘owed much to that occasion during those years when the curate [Hobbes's father], possibly long before his disappearance, was forced by his character and circumstances to yield the government to Hobbes’ mother' (Rogow, Arnold A., Thomas Hobbes: Radical in the Service of Reaction (New York and London: W.W. Norton and Co., 1986), p. 132Google Scholar). Hobbes's father, rather fond of drink and neglectful of his parish, fled after being accused of assaulting a rector of a neighbouring parish. Ironically Rogow was unable to find any new information about Hobbes's mother. Even her maiden name remains uncertain.
23 The other classic contract theorists are discussed in Pateman, , The Sexual Contract, chaps 3 and 4.Google Scholar
24 Hobbes, , Philosophical Rudiments, chap. IX, p. 116.Google Scholar
25 Hobbes, Thomas, A Dialogue between a Philosopher and a Student of the Common Laws of England, EW, vol. VI, p. 147.Google Scholar
26 Hobbes, Thomas, De Corpore Politico, or The Elements of Law, EW, vol. IV, chap. IV, pp. 158–9.Google Scholar
27 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XVII, p. 154.Google Scholar
28 Hobbes, , Philosophical Rudiments, chap. VIII, p. 108.Google Scholar
29 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. X, p. 82.Google Scholar
30 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XX, p. 191.Google Scholar
31 Hobbes, , Philosophical Rudiments, chap. IX, p. 121.Google Scholar
32 Hobbes, , De Corpore Politico, chap. IV, p. 158.Google Scholar
33 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XV, p. 133.Google Scholar
34 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XX, p. 189.Google Scholar
35 Hobbes, , De Corpore Politico, chap. III, pp. 149–50.Google Scholar
36 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XX, p. 190.Google Scholar
37 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XVII, p. 159.Google Scholar
38 I am grateful to Peter Morriss for raising the question of generations and for other helpful criticisms.
39 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XV, p. 187.Google Scholar
40 Hobbes, , Philosophical Rudiments, chap. IX, p. 118.Google Scholar
41 On the implications of coverture, see Pateman, , The Sexual Contract, chaps 5 and 6.Google Scholar
42 Chapman, , ‘Leviathan Writ Small’, p. 84, fn. 90.Google Scholar
43 Hampton, , Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition, pp. 197–207Google Scholar, argues that his deduction of absolute sovereignty fails precisely because Hobbes makes self-protection an absolute right. But because she takes no account of Hobbes's patriarchalism, she fails to mention that, if the argument about sovereignty in the state is correct, then conjugal sovereignty fails too.
44 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XVII, p. 158.Google Scholar
45 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XVI, p. 151.Google Scholar
46 Hobbes, , Leviathan, chap. XXII, pp. 221–2.Google Scholar
47 Hinton, R. W. K., ‘Husbands, Fathers and Conquerors’, Political Studies, 15 (1967), 291–300 at pp. 294, 299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
48 For an argument that absolutist conclusions are ultimately unavoidable, see Pateman, Carole, The Problem of Political Obligation, 2nd edn (Cambridge: Polity Press; Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1985), chap. 3Google Scholar. Hampton, , Hobbes and the Social Contract TraditionGoogle Scholar, interprets Hobbes's commonwealth as a union of slaves within the will of a master.
49 Hobbes, , Leviathan, Part IV, p. 706.Google Scholar
50 Astell, Mary, Some Reflections Upon Marriage, 4th edn (New York: Source Book Press, 1970; originally published 1730), p. 107.Google Scholar
- 34
- Cited by