Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T04:50:30.410Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rumors and Health Care Reform: Experiments in Political Misinformation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 June 2015

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article explores belief in political rumors surrounding the health care reforms enacted by Congress in 2010. Refuting rumors with statements from unlikely sources can, under certain circumstances, increase the willingness of citizens to reject rumors regardless of their own political predilections. Such source credibility effects, while well known in the political persuasion literature, have not been applied to the study of rumor. Though source credibility appears to be an effective tool for debunking political rumors, risks remain. Drawing upon research from psychology on ‘fluency’ – the ease of information recall – this article argues that rumors acquire power through familiarity. Attempting to quash rumors through direct refutation may facilitate their diffusion by increasing fluency. The empirical results find that merely repeating a rumor increases its power.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2015 

In the summer of 2009, stories swirled alleging that President Obama’s health care reforms would include procedures to withhold care from certain citizens. The elderly, these rumors suggested, would have to meet with government officials to discuss ‘end of life’ options like euthanasia. On 7 August 2009 former Alaska governor and US vice presidential candidate Sarah Palin wrote on her Facebook page, ‘The America I know and love is not one in which my parents or my baby with Down Syndrome will have to stand in front of Obama’s “death panel” so his bureaucrats can decide, based on a subjective judgment of their “level of productivity in society”, whether they are worthy of health care. Such a system is downright evil.’Footnote 1 Within a week, 86 per cent of the American public was aware of Palin’s accusation.Footnote 2 Though these objectively false rumors were widely discredited, the controversy surrounding death panels would not die – even long after the 2010 Affordable Care Act (ACA) was passed by the US Congress and signed into law by Obama.Footnote 3

Rumors and innuendo have long influenced the conduct of politics in destructive ways. Though not always false, rumors are regularly used in contemporary politics as a tool to spread falsehoods and misinformation. This is true not only in the United States, but in other countries throughout the world.Footnote 4 Rumors in political discourse are common and easy to identify, yet it remains difficult to find ways to undo the false information they spread. As the motivating example above illustrates, political rumors are often durable and highly resistant to correction, sometimes with dangerous consequences.

In this article, I engage the broad challenge of finding ways to correct rumors. I study how ordinary citizens responded to actual rumors surrounding the health care reforms enacted by the US Congress in 2010. There are, it appears, some effective strategies for countering rumors. Refuting a rumor with statements from an unlikely source – a person who makes proclamations that run contrary to their personal and political interests – can increase citizens’ willingness to reject rumors, regardless of their own political predilections. While such source credibility results are well known in the political persuasion literature, these insights have not yet been brought to bear on the study of rumor. In the present context, pairing death panel rumors with statements from Republicans flatly debunking the rumor can lead citizens – Republicans and Democrats alike – to reject the veracity of the rumor.

Though source credibility appears to be an effective tool for debunking political rumors, risks remain. Drawing upon research from psychology on ‘fluency’ – a state of mind that characterizes the ease of information processing – I argue that rumors acquire their power through familiarity. Attempting to quash rumors through direct refutation may instead facilitate their diffusion by increasing their fluency. Empirically, I find that merely repeating a rumor increases its strength. In fact, simply asking subjects to repeat the rumor to themselves – without any indication that it is true – increases its power. Evidence from a panel of subjects demonstrates that these effects persist even weeks after subjects read the initial story. This pattern holds even when rumors are repeated in the context of debunking that misinformation with a strong correction.

This article proceeds as follows: in the next section, I describe the nature of political rumors with a focus on the health care rumor. I then discuss how we can limit their power by bolstering the credibility of the source debunking the rumor. In today’s politically polarized world, non-partisan sources sometimes lack credibility; far more credible are partisan political actors who make statements that run counter to their apparent interests. I next discuss how the repetition of rumors can augment their ‘fluency’, thereby increasing the likelihood that individuals will accept misinformation as truth. To test these theoretical claims, I present the results of two experiments in which I vary the presentation of information concerning the 2010 ACA. Together, these experiments demonstrate both the power of partisan corrections to counter false information and the dominance of fluency in facilitating the acceptance of rumors.

Rumors in the Political Realm

While the conceptual murkiness surrounding the term ‘rumor’ has led to longstanding definitional debates among social scientists, a consensus regarding its meaning has emerged.Footnote 5 Sunstein defines the term to refer to ‘claims of fact – about people, groups, events and institutions – that have not been shown to be true, but that move from one person to another and hence have credibility not because direct evidence is known to support them, but because other people seem to believe them’.Footnote 6

From these points of view, rumors are a particular form of misinformation – an acceptance of information that is factually unsubstantiated – characterized by two features. First, rumors are statements that lack specific standards of evidence.Footnote 7 Political rumors, then, are not ‘warranted beliefs’.Footnote 8 Secondly, rumors are more than fringe beliefs. They acquire their power through widespread social transmission.

While rumors have been a topic of social science research for over 100 years, by some readings, they have become a more insidious political force in recent times.Footnote 9 In the World War II era, Allport and Postman noted that the main medium of rumor transmission was word of mouth.Footnote 10 The internet has expanded the scope of rumor dissemination. Today, anyone can publish on the web, instantly acquiring a degree of credibility and more easily reaching a larger audience. As a result, rumors may materialize suddenly and never disappear.Footnote 11 This is true not just in the United States, but in other countries as well.Footnote 12 Rumors are therefore a powerful tool in the spread of unsubstantiated information, and even falsehoods (as in the case of death panels).

The persistence of these rumors is troubling for the prospects of democracy. As Kuklinski et al. note, while much of the handwringing in the field of political behavior concerns the implications of citizens’ ignorance of basic political facts, a more serious problem for the possibility of establishing effective mass participation in a democratic system is the prevalence of misinformation.Footnote 13 A democracy in which falsehoods are rampant can lead to dysfunction. Rumors are an insidious form of misinformation – one that is particularly damaging for the functioning of democracy – but they are misinformation nonetheless. The key, from this perspective, is making sure that the public definitively rejects false information. Seen in this light, political rumors provide a new and interesting venue for the study of political misinformation.Footnote 14 By focusing on patently false rumors that can be debunked with uncontested facts, we can learn about the more general processes of political misperception.

Health Reform and ‘Death Panels’

While recent history bears out the power and reach of political rumors from across the ideological spectrum, in this article I consider one specific political rumor. As noted above, in the summer of 2009 rumors circulated that Obama’s proposed health care reform plan would allow government officials to decide whether individual citizens should receive health care based on a calculation of their level of productivity in society. One element of these rumors was the suggestion that elderly people would have to consult ‘death panels’ to discuss end-of-life options like euthanasia. These rumors started with statements made by former New York Lieutenant Governor Betsy McCaughey, but quickly spread to the conservative media.Footnote 15 A number of prominent Republican politicians added to the chorus, including Sarah Palin and Senator Charles Grassley, the ranking Republican member of the US Senate Finance Committee.

These rumors are patently false and have been publicly discredited in many fora. Yet they have taken seed among the American public. A poll conducted by the Pew Center in August 2009 found that 30 per cent of the public thought the ‘death panel’ rumor was true, with another 20 per cent unsure of the veracity of the statement.Footnote 16 Following various attempts to debunk the rumor, and even after the passage of the ACA in March 2010, the death panel rumors continued to persist. A July 2010 YouGov poll found that 33 per cent of the public thought the rumor was true, with another 22 per cent unsure. In a separate question, the same poll also found that 26 per cent of the public thought that changes to the health care system would require elderly patients to meet with government officials to discuss end-of-life options, including euthanasia. Another 28 per cent were unsure. These responses are consistent with other polling on health care rumors.Footnote 17

The power of this rumor extends beyond shaping the beliefs of the mass public; it also has serious policy consequences. In early 2011, the Obama administration announced that it would revise Medicare fee policies to remove provisions that provided funding for end-of-life counseling. The vast reach of the death panel rumors hung heavily over this decision. Thus the spread of death panel rumors may have, at least indirectly, contributed to the end of an important Medicare service.

How do People Respond to Rumors?

Correcting rumors is no easy task, but it may be even more difficult to correct rumors in the minds of certain types of citizens. Recent research has shown that some individuals are more predisposed than others to accept conspiracy theories and related rumors even when the theories are self-contradictory.Footnote 18

But even given these inter-individual differences in the tendency to accept fanciful beliefs, the specific presentation of information – and misinformation – should help shape many citizens’ ideas about political rumors. Obama attempted one such strategy by directly contradicting the health care rumors at town hall meetings in New Hampshire in August 2009. But, as the polls discussed above demonstrate, these strategies did not shift the tides of public opinion. This is not surprising. Consistent with Obama’s failures, political science research on misinformation paints a grim picture. Kuklinski et al. had some success in correcting false beliefs about welfare spending in the United States, but they also presented evidence that such learning is short-lived.Footnote 19 More recently, Nyhan and Reifler conducted experiments in which they corrected false statements about, among other topics, the Iraq war and Obama’s religion.Footnote 20 They find that confronting citizens with the truth can sometimes backfire and reinforce existing misperceptions. For instance, conservatives who received information that Iraq did not possess weapons of mass destruction were more likely to believe Iraq had those weapons than were respondents who did not receive the correct information.Footnote 21

These results are both disturbing and counterintuitive; they suggest that, with regard to political issues, attempts to correct the misperceptions of ordinary citizens may exacerbate the stickiness of mistaken beliefs. Moreover, these findings contradict much of the advice in psychology on how best to address rumors. In a comprehensive review of rumor-quelling literatures in both psychology and business, spanning twenty-two different studies, DiFonzo and Bordia find that the most frequent recommendation on how to reduce belief in a rumor is the use of rebuttal, the same strategy the Obama administration attempted in 2009.Footnote 22

Political Rumors and the Power of Partisanship

To correct misperceptions and misinformation about political controversies, a new approach seems necessary. The introduction of partisan concerns changes how people deal with new information. Surveys show that Democrats and Republicans (and liberals and conservatives) approach the same rumor in very different ways. More generally, research has found that people are more likely to accept rumors that are consistent with their pre-existing attitudes.Footnote 23 A compelling explanation of this pattern is citizens’ tendency to engage in motivated reasoning:Footnote 24 ordinary citizens are goal-directed information processers, and they perceive new information in light of their pre-existing views.Footnote 25 Put another way, some citizens may be more likely to believe particular rumors because they are motivated to cling to beliefs that are compatible with their partisan or political outlook.

Because partisans tend to evaluate new information with respect to their existing views,Footnote 26 encountering a rumor may have different effects for citizens of different political stripes. Still, while partisanship may color the processing of new information, it does not always control it, and even the strongest partisans can change their beliefs in response to new information. In this case, turning the power of partisanship on its head could be the key to developing effective corrective measures. Politicians who attempt to debunk rumors often appeal to non-partisan authorities as neutral referees of the truth. But in a time when people’s partisanship colors how they perceive new information, these ‘neutral’ non-partisan figures may speak with less credibility than is often presumed. More convincing are partisan politicians who speak against their own apparent political interests. Such unlikely statements may make rumor rebuttals more credible.

This notion of source credibility effects is novel in the study of rumors, but is a familiar result in persuasion research.Footnote 27 Moreover, it is consistent with the formal model proposed by Calvert.Footnote 28 Calvert concludes that ‘biased’ advisors – those with strong priors toward a particular policy – are especially informative sources of information for decision makers. If such an advisor rejects a policy that the decision maker presumed he would support, this unexpected advice could be ‘enough to reverse prior preferences’.Footnote 29 In the present context, a Republican who debunks a rumor about a Democratic politician or policy could change the beliefs of both Democrats and Republicans (as well as Independents).

The Fluency of Information

If turning partisanship on its head seems a plausible corrective measure for rumors, what concerns remain? One is that we have few explanations for the seemingly counter-intuitive results of Nyhan and Reifler – why do some correctives actually increase the power of rumors?Footnote 30 While there is much we do not know about the dynamics of rumors, we can draw on basic mechanisms studied by social psychologists outside of the context of rumors to explain these results. After all, psychologists have long known that retractions often fail to eliminate the influence of misinformation through a ‘continued influence effect’.Footnote 31 The key is to consider what Schwarz et al. call the ‘processing fluency’ of information.Footnote 32

Fluency is ‘the subjective experience of ease or difficulty associated with completing a mental task’.Footnote 33 This line of research grows out of Tversky and Kahneman’s availability heuristic.Footnote 34 Cognitive tasks, as Alter and Oppenheimer note, can be described as ranging from effortless to highly effortful.Footnote 35 These tasks, in turn, produce an internal state of awareness whereby people are aware of how hard they need to think to complete a task, and that awareness influences their everyday judgements.Footnote 36

What is important here is that a number of psychologists have found that the difficulty with which information is processed affects individuals’ assessment of its accuracy. Specifically, they find that people use their feelings regarding how easy it is to recall or process new information as a signal of the veracity of that information.Footnote 37 This is a powerful effect that goes beyond merely identifying or comprehending frequently presented information, a phenomenon that was recognized beginning in the 1980s.Footnote 38 The psychological state of high fluency instead shapes the perceived authenticity of information. For instance, information that has been presented frequently will be more familiar to citizens and, as a result, is more likely to be accepted as the truth, regardless of the actual content.Footnote 39 Repetition is but one path to fluency, but these findings may explain the Nyhan and Reifler results. Any attempt to explicitly discredit falsehoods may make things worse because directly countering a rumor involves repeating it. This mere mention of the rumor can increase its fluency, thereby heightening its perceived accuracy.Footnote 40

Schwarz et al. demonstrate the importance of these processes using an informational flyer created by the Center for Disease Control (CDC) to educate patients about the flu vaccine.Footnote 41 This flyer confronts ‘myths’ about the vaccination – erroneous beliefs about the vaccine – with the proper ‘facts’. Schwarz et al. conducted an experiment in which some subjects were shown the CDC flyer. Half of these subjects were immediately given a test that repeated the ‘facts and myths’ information. These participants were asked to mark which statements were true. The other half of the subjects was given the test after a thirty-minute delay.Footnote 42

Immediately after reading the flyer, participants were able to recall the information from the flyer almost perfectly – they misclassified ‘myths’ as ‘facts’ at very low rates (and vice versa). However, after the thirty-minute delay – once the memory of the substantive details of the information presented in the poster faded, but the ‘gist’ of those statements remained – the subjects’ judgements began to show a systematic error pattern. Consistent with a psychological state of increased fluency, these respondents were significantly more likely to misidentify the ‘myths’ as ‘truth’ than vice versa, and were less likely to say they would get a shot than the participants who were asked their opinions immediately. In essence, the attempt to debunk myths about the flu shot instead had the effect of further spreading mistruths by subconsciously increasing the respondents’ recognition of those myths.Footnote 43 We can draw upon the same dynamics uncovered by Schwarz to understand the power of rumors.

Summary and Synthesis

Together these seemingly disparate bodies of work explain the enduring power of political rumors and provide some clues about potential correctives. Political rumors are powerful because partisans are motivated to believe falsehoods about politicians and policies of the other party. Moreover, the strategy most often employed to counter rumors – directly confronting the rumor by repeating it, then debunking it – may serve to augment the processing fluency of the rumor for individuals, thereby decreasing the likelihood that citizens will reject that rumor out of hand. To discredit these rumors and correct misinformation, it is necessary to adopt a new strategy – in particular by varying the partisanship of the authoritative source. It may be that Republicans who debunk Democratic rumors (and Democrats who debunk Republican rumors) will have more credibility than non-partisan actors. These politicized voices may have the power to overwhelm the fluency effect and correct misinformed beliefs. In my experiments, I try to break the vicious cycle of rumors with different presentational strategies.

Experiments

In 2010, I conducted two studies to test the effects of different corrections on the beliefs regarding rumors concerning the 2010 ACA. These studies varied the presentation of the rumor-related information across three dimensions: (1) the pairing of rumor and correction, (2) the partisanship of the source of the correction of the rumor and (3) the degree to which the respondent was induced to rehearse the rumor. These experiments also explored the effect of time on the power of the treatments, recording responses not only immediately following the treatment, but also many days later. In all the experiments I was concerned with patterns of rumor rejection – the rate at which subjects would definitively reject false information. The psychological literature often takes the opposite approach, focusing on patterns of rumor acceptance.Footnote 44 I focus on rumor rejection because of the ambiguous nature of the ‘not sure’ response. From a political science perspective, any position short of outright rejecting a rumor – even an expression of uncertainty about its veracity through a ‘don’t know’ or ‘not sure’ response – enhances the credibility of rumors and is normatively undesirable. The importance of the ‘not sure’ responses can be seen in media reports of polls asking rumor questions. Such responses are often reported to be as damning as acceptance of the rumors.Footnote 45

The experiments described in this article are especially difficult tests of the power of rumors because they exploit real-world (rather than constructed) rumors. Both of these experiments were conducted in the immediate wake of the passage of the controversial 2010 ACA and used quotes and facts drawn from the debate surrounding the act. In doing so, I traded off the ability to fully manipulate the information presented to respondents in order to maintain a realistic set of treatments. In addition, given that these experiments were conducted during an ongoing controversy, the effect sizes of my treatments will be smaller than if the information presented in the stories was completely novel to the subjects. Thus, the experimental effects that I find from exposure to my treatments are, by design, more muted than they would have been if I had been able to control the full scope of the information presented.

Study 1

In May 2010, two months after the passage of the ACA, I ran a between-subjects design experiment on an internet panel to test the efficacy of various corrective strategies.Footnote 46 The primary purpose of this experiment was to examine the impact of the partisan identity of the provider of the rumor correction. I then used a delayed follow-up questionnaire to assess some of Schwarz’s expectations regarding fluency.Footnote 47

I randomized the presentation of different news stories that I constructed about health care reform to subjects in four different experimental conditions (along with a control condition, in which the subjects received no news story, but were merely asked if they believed the rumor). The stories all dealt with the 2010 ACA, but presented different details about the debate surrounding that plan (the full text of the treatments is presented in Appendix A).

In the first ‘rumor’ condition, subjects were presented with the rumor in the form of quotes by opponents of the act, who warned of the possibility of death panels. In the second ‘rumor and non-partisan correction’ condition, respondents were presented both the rumor information from the first condition and a non-partisan correction of that rumor, in the form of a description of the end-of-life provisions of the ACA and supporting quotes from the American Medical Association (AMA) and the American Association of Retired Persons (AARP). The third and fourth conditions introduced explicitly partisan information in addition to the non-partisan correction. In the third ‘rumor and Republican correction’ condition, the text from the ‘rumor and non-partisan correction’ condition text was reproduced, and a quote debunking the rumor from Senator John Isakson (a Republican who helped draft the end-of-life provisions) was added to the end of the story. In the fourth ‘rumor and Democratic correction’ condition, the ‘rumor and non-partisan correction’ was also reproduced and a separate quote containing the correction was added to the end of the story. This quote was instead from Representative Earl Blumenauer (a Democrat who helped draft the provision).Footnote 48 The specific text of the quotes from Isakson and Blumenauer differed (because they were drawn from actual quotes) but the spirit of the corrections was the same.Footnote 49 More generally, it should be noted that while the treatments differ in a number of ways, these differences are intentionally drawn to mirror the political rhetoric surrounding the discussion of rumors concerning health care reform in the media.

Respondents were randomly assigned to one of five conditions (the four experimental treatments and the control). They were then asked a series of questions concerning the veracity of the death panel rumors and whether they support the health care plan. In the tables that follow, I present the results of the analysis of the euthanasia rumor item, which most directly taps the controversy surrounding the ACA provisions. It asks, ‘Do you think the changes to the health care system have that have been enacted by Congress and the Obama administration require elderly patients to meet with government officials to discuss “end of life” options including euthanasia’?Footnote 50 The results are very similar for the other rumor question, which asks about death panels. To minimize the number of tables in the body of the article, I do not include the analysis of this question below, but present the full results in Appendix B.Footnote 51

In addition, I asked two questions that were designed to measure, in a general sense, how closely the respondents followed the instructions on the survey. Specifically, I designed items that serve as what Oppenheimer, Meyvis and Davidenko term an instructional manipulation check (IMC).Footnote 52 IMCs (or ‘screeners’) indirectly capture whether respondents are satisficingFootnote 53 – simply hurrying through the questionnaire as fast as possible (the full text of these questions is presented in Appendix C). Approximately two-thirds of respondents passed each of the two screener questions, and 55 per cent of the sample passed both of the questions. In the analyses that follow, I present the results for the full sample, but focus on the ‘attentive sample’ – those respondents who passed both screener questions. I focus on this subsample because the news story treatments contain subtle differences in presentation that are likely to have their strongest effect on respondents who pay closest attention to the survey.Footnote 54 Berinsky, Margolis and Sances show that the passage of screener questions leads to an increased power of textual treatments because people who pass screeners read the text more closely.Footnote 55 That said, because Berinsky, Margolis and Sances also show that people who pass screener questions are different from those who fail them, it is certainly possible that there is a heterogenous treatment effect between the attentive and inattentive subgroups. That is, even if the inattentive subgroup read the material more closely, the effect of the treatment might not be the same for the two groups. The estimates presented here for the attentive sample should therefore be best thought of as the average treatment effect for this sample.

A second reason I focus on this subsample is that approximately one week after the initial survey I conducted a second wave of the experiment. I recontacted only those respondents who passed both of the screener questions. Of those contacted, about 60 per cent agreed to participate in the second wave. Ultimately, I reinterviewed 699 subjects – 41 per cent of the initial full sample. This reinterview sample was essentially identical to the initial attentive sample on measures of gender, education, party identification and political information. During the second wave, I again asked the rumor questions and support for the health care plan.

In Table 1, I present the answers to the euthanasia rumors question, broken down by experimental condition. I present two sets of significance tests. The first is a χ2 test of overall significance, which tests if there are any significant differences among any of the conditions. The second set is a series of paired comparisons testing for significant differences between conditions. Because there are five conditions, there are a total of ten comparisons. I present full significance results for all the pairwise comparisons in a note at the bottom of the table.

Table 1 Effect of Treatments on Euthanasia Rumor Belief, May 2010

N=1,596; χ2(8)=19.24; Pr=0.01.

Note: the top three rows present the percentage of respondents that rejects, accepts or is unsure about each rumor. This is presented for each condition (represented by the column). The significance tests are calculated across all response categories.

aControl is not statistically significantly different from Rumor Only (p=0.306), or from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.142).

bControl is marginally statistically significantly different from Rumor+Non-partisan Correction (p=0.093).

cControl is statistically significantly different from Rumor+Republican Correction (p=0.029).

dRumor Only is statistically significantly different from Rumor+Non-partisan Correction (p=0.010), from Rumor+Republican Correction (p=0.002) and from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.039).

eRumor+Non-partisan Correction is not statistically significantly different from Rumor+Republican Correction (p=0.895), or from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.810).

fRumor+Republican Correction is not statistically significantly different from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.599).

N=876; χ2(8)=23.95; Pr=0.002.

Note: the top three rows present the percentage of respondents that rejects, accepts or is unsure about each rumor. This is presented for each condition (represented by the column). The significance tests are calculated across all response categories.

aControl is not statistically significantly different from Rumor Only (p=0.145), or from Rumor+Non-partisan Correction (p=0.581) or from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.216).

bControl is statistically significantly different from Rumor+Republican Correction (p=0.004).

cRumor Only is not statistically significantly different from Rumor+Non-partisan Correction (p=0.147).

dRumor Only is statistically significantly different from Rumor+Republican Correction (p=0.000), and from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.029).

eRumor+Non-partisan Correction is marginally statistically distinguishable from Rumor+Republican Correction (p=0.068).

fRumor+Non-partisan Correction is not statistically significantly different from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.836).

gRumor+Republican Correction is not statistically significantly different from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.147).

Several conclusions are apparent. First, the differences among the conditions are highly significant in a statistical sense, indicating that, taken together, the different presentations of the information altered rumor rejection levels. Moving to the pairwise comparisons between the different conditions, I find that presenting the rumor by itself decreases rumor rejection rates by 5 per cent relative to the control condition, though this difference is not statistically significant. The correction conditions all seem to be effective, and increase the rates of rumor rejection by ten points over the rumor-only condition, largely by reducing the levels of ‘not sure’ responses.

The pairwise differences between each of the three correction conditions and the ‘rumor only’ condition are all statistically significant at the 0.05 level. However, the differences among the three correction conditions are not statistically significant.Footnote 56 In addition, the ‘rumor and Republican correction’ condition – which should be the strongest correction – increases rumor rejection rates by 8 per cent relative to the control condition (58 vs. 50 per cent), a difference that is statistically significant at the 0.05 level. Thus, the corrections seem to work by increasing rumor rejection rates by reducing the level of uncertainty surrounding the rumor.

The magnitude of the differences among the conditions is magnified in the attentive sample. As the bottom panel of Table 1 demonstrates, the baseline rumor rejection rates are somewhat higher in the attentive sample, but the differences between conditions apparent in the full sample emerge more sharply in the attentive sample. Among those respondents who paid close attention to question wordings, the Republican correction – information from an unexpected source – is the most effective treatment in increasing rates of rumor rejection. The size of the differences between the ‘rumor and Republican correction’ condition and the other conditions is larger in both a substantive and a statistical sense than in the full sample. The difference in results between the full and attentive samples makes sense, because the key difference between the Democratic and Republican correction conditions is the provider of the quote at the end of the article. People who merely skim through the treatment and do not read the stimulus are likely to miss this critical difference. This result holds when we break up the sample into partisan groups. Though the relatively small size of the subgroup samples precludes the detection of statistically significant differences, there are strong patterns in the substantive size of the effects (and sometimes these differences reach conventional levels of significance). Most importantly, the Republican correction is the most powerful treatment for both Republican and Democratic identifiers (see Appendix B for full results). Thus, a simple elite cueing story alone cannot explain these results; after all, Democratic identifiers are more influenced by the Republican correction than by the Democratic correction. Rather, it is the informational content of the identity of the politician making the correction that matters.

These effects extend from rejection of the rumor to support for health care in the attentive sample, as shown in Table 2.Footnote 57 While the euthanasia rumor question presented in Table 1 measures belief in the rumor, the policy item in Table 2 measures whether the respondent supports the policies enacted by Obama’s health care reforms. Though the effects are modest in size, both statistically and substantively, presenting the rumor by itself decreases support for the plan relative to the control condition (51 per cent compared to 42 per cent). This nine-point difference barely misses significance at the 0.10 level in the attentive sample. Presenting the rumor in combination with a non-partisan correction or the Republican correction causes support to rebound, albeit modestly. However, neither of these correction conditions is statistically distinct from the ‘rumor only’ condition. But interestingly, introducing the Democratic correction creates a backlash, reducing support for the plan to its lowest level across any condition.Footnote 58

Table 2 Effect of Treatments on Health Care Policy Opinion, May 2010 (Attentive Sample)

N=876; χ2(4)=9.00; Pr=0.06.

Note: the top two rows present the percentages of respondents that supports or opposes each condition (represented by the columns).

aControl is not statistically significantly different from Rumor Only (p=0.102), from Rumor+Non-partisan Correction (p=0.337), from Rumor+Republican Correction (p=0.600), or from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.216).

bRumor Only is not statistically significantly different from Rumor+Non-partisan Correction (p=0.483), or from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.312).

cRumor Only is statistically significantly different from Rumor+Republican Correction (p=0.000).

dRumor+Non-partisan Correction is not statistically significantly different from Rumor+Republican Correction (p=0.662).

eRumor+Non-partisan Correction is marginally statistically distinguishable from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.077).

fRumor+Republican Correction is statistically distinguishable from Rumor+Democratic Correction (p=0.027).

As Table 3 shows, there is some evidence of a subsiding effect over time. The effects of the different experimental conditions are clear, but these effects were all produced on items asked immediately post-treatment. Based on Schwarz’s work, we would expect that fluency-based backfire effects would occur after a delay.Footnote 59 Specifically, respondents who were presented both the rumor and the correction should be less likely to reject the rumor outright than people who were given no information.

Table 3 Effect of Treatments on Euthanasia Rumor Belief Over Time for Respondents Interviewed in Both Waves, May 2010

N=696; χ2(8)=23.2; Pr=0.03.

Note: full pairwise tests of statistical significance are presented in Appendix C (C8).

N=696; χ2(8)=12.2; Pr=0.14.

Note: full pairwise tests of statistical significance are presented in Appendix C (C9).

Here, I compare the responses on the euthanasia rumor question across the two waves for the subset of respondents that was interviewed in both waves. As expected, the respondents in the ‘rumor only’ condition held steady in their beliefs. However, the effectiveness of the corrections faded across the board during the week between the waves of the survey, largely because the rates of ‘not sure’ responses increased for respondents in those conditions. As the χ2 test of overall significance demonstrates, the differences among the experimental conditions were no longer significant. Not surprisingly, given this result, the statistically significant differences found in the pairwise comparison of conditions from the first wave disappear.Footnote 60 The Republican correction remained the most effective treatment, but the rates of rumor rejection decreased by about 10 per cent relative to the first wave. Furthermore, the rates of rumor rejection for both the ‘rumor and non-partisan correction’ and ‘rumor and Democratic correction’ conditions were now lower than the control condition (though this difference is not statistically significant). Thus, over time, providing people with correct information in conjunction with the rumor may be no better than no information at all. These effects extended beyond rumor rejection to support for health care. Respondents who were exposed to the rumor, either alone or in combination with the non-partisan correction, remained less supportive than people who received no information (see Appendix B for these results).

Study 2

Study 1 demonstrated that corrections from an unlikely source – Republicans debunking health care rumors – are the most effective way to counter rumors. But the danger in debunking rumors is that by reminding citizens of the rumor, the effectiveness of correcting that rumor could fade over time. In order to build on the first study and more directly test the fluency hypothesis, I fielded a second experiment as a module in the October/November 2010 Cooperative Congressional Election Study (CCES), a panel study fielded by YouGov.Footnote 61

The subject of these experiments was again rumors concerning Obama’s health plan. As in Study 1, I randomized the presentation of treatments that consisted of (constructed) news stories about health care reform. In this second study, I used a new design. The stories in these treatments were modeled on the stories used in the May 2010 experiment and are presented in Appendix E. I had three different experimental conditions. The first ‘rumor’ condition was identical to the rumor condition in the May study. The second ‘correction only’ condition was a new treatment that did not mention the rumors concerning the death panel, but only described the actual provisions in the 2010 ACA.Footnote 62 I chose to hold the partisan content of the rumor correction at its most effective level, using the Republican correction in the form of the Isakson quote from the May study. The third ‘rumor and correction’ was identical to the ‘rumor and Republican correction’ condition from the May study and presented both the rumor information from the first condition and the correction from the second condition. Unlike Study 1, I did not employ the screener IMC items.Footnote 63

There was no control group in this experiment. Based on the results of Study 1, we have a good sense of the power of the treatments relative to the baseline.Footnote 64 I therefore compare the effects of the different conditions to each other. This is an appropriate analytic strategy because the purpose of the experiment is to explore the effects of differences in the presentation of information, not the differences between the treatments and ‘no information’.

In addition to the corrective strategy treatment, I designed a two-condition ‘rehearsal treatment’ to directly test the expectations regarding fluency from the Schwarz work.Footnote 65 Respondents who received the rumor information – either alone or in combination with the correction – were asked one of two types of recall questions after the story. The stated purpose of the task was to test what they could recall from the story, but the true purpose was to see whether rehearsing the rumors would increase their power. Half of the respondents were assigned to an ‘irrelevant recall’ condition, in which they were asked a single recall question – a multiple choice question asking what office was held by Betsy McCaughey (who was quoted in the story) – while the other half was placed in a ‘long recall’ condition and received two additional questions that asked them to identify the speaker of a particular quote that repeated the content of the rumor. For instance, respondents were asked who said, ‘You have every right to fear […] [You] should not have a government-run plan to decide when to pull the plug on Grandma’ (exact text of these questions is presented in Appendix F).

I was not interested in the answers they gave to these questions per se; the simple task of answering the recall questions ensured that they would again read the incorrect information. This ‘rehearsal’ of the rumor immediately following the presentation of the study should increase the fluency with which people process the information contained in the rumor.Footnote 66 Based on the psychological work on fluency, I expected this increased level of fluency to lower rumor rejection levels, regardless of whether the rumor was paired with the correction.

CCES respondents were interviewed first in October, and then again in November. I asked the rumor belief questions in both waves. I also asked about support for health care reform in the first wave.Footnote 67

In Table 4, I present the effects of the rumor information treatment on rumor rejection levels (setting aside the recall treatments for the moment). The correction conditions – whether in combination with the rumor or alone – led respondents to reject the euthanasia rumor at higher rates than in the rumor-only condition, though only the rumor and correction condition is statistically distinct from the rumor-only condition at the 0.05 level. Thus, at least in the moment, the pairing of the rumor with the correction was a more effective strategy than simply presenting the correct information on its own (though the differences between these two conditions are not statistically significant).

Table 4 Effect of Treatments on Euthanasia Rumor Belief, October 2010

N=1,000; χ2(4)=12.23; Pr=0.02.

Note: full pairwise tests of statistical significance are presented in Appendix G (G7).

But Schwarz’s work suggests that the effectiveness of corrections fades over time.Footnote 68 Table 5 presents the distribution of responses for those individuals who completed both waves of the study (837 of the initial 1,000 subjects). Subjects who completed only the first wave of the survey are excluded from the analysis. This table demonstrates that on a substantive level, by the second wave, the gap between the ‘rumor only’ and ‘rumor and correction’ conditions had diminished (see Appendix G for a more formal difference-in-difference test). As in Study 1, the passage of time reduced the effectiveness of the correction relative to the rumor on the euthanasia question. Neither of the correction conditions is statistically distinct from the rumor-only condition in a pairwise comparison test. It should be noted that this effect is not merely the result of the fading effectiveness of information over time; one month later, the distribution of responses to the euthanasia question for respondents in the ‘rumor only’ condition is unchanged. This differential pattern of information decay across conditions contrasts with the typical pattern of treatment decay found in similar studies.Footnote 69 Again, the effect of the treatments extended from rejection of rumors to general support for health care (see Appendix G for details).

Table 5 Effect of Treatments on Euthanasia Rumor Belief Over Time, October–November 2010

N=837; χ2(4)=14.22; Pr=0.01.

Note: full pairwise tests of statistical significance are presented in Appendix G (G8).

N=834; χ2(4)=5.03 Pr=0.28.

Note: full pairwise tests of statistical significance are presented in Appendix G (G9).

To this point, Study 2 largely replicates the findings from Study 1. I next sought to see if the rehearsal treatment had the intended effect. Findings about the effect of rumor rehearsal on rumor acceptance are given in Table 6. The table presents four columns of data. The first two columns pertain to the results among respondents assigned to the ‘rumor only’ story treatment. The first column presents the distribution of responses to the euthanasia question among subjects who were assigned to the ‘irrelevant recall’ version of the rehearsal treatment. These respondents were only presented the McCaughey office identification question. The second column presents the distribution of the rumor question among those who were assigned to the ‘long recall’ version of the rehearsal treatment. In addition to the McCaughey question, these respondents were given the two death panel quote identification questions.

Table 6 Effect of Rumor Rehearsal on Euthanasia Rumor Belief, October 2010

Rumor Only: N=350; χ2(2)=5.49; Rumor+Correction: Pr=0.06; N=342; χ2(2)=0.67; Pr=0.72.

My expectation was that respondents in this condition would be less likely to reject the rumor because they have rehearsed its content, thus increasing its fluency. The next two columns of the table repeat this presentation for respondents in the ‘rumor and correction’ story condition. Since respondents in the ‘correction only’ condition all received a single recall question unrelated to the rumor, the data from those respondents are omitted from the table.

Table 6 demonstrates that, as expected, increasing fluency by simply rehearsing the rumor by answering the recall questions increased the power of the treatment across both questions. The increased rehearsal of the rumor – in the absence of any information about its veracity – was sufficient to decrease rumor rejection rates, even when the rumor was initially presented in combination with a powerful correction. Admittedly, this effect is not extremely large, but it was larger in the long-recall condition than the irrelevant recall condition for both respondents in the rumor-only and the rumor and correction condition (though the differences are statistically significant at the 0.10 level only in the ‘rumor only’ condition).Footnote 70 Further, in line with the ‘fluency’ hypothesis, Table 6 shows increases in rumor belief as well as uncertainty. Respondents are not simply becoming more uncertain, but are actually more ready to believe the rumor after repeated exposure.Footnote 71

Because the rumor questions are asked in short succession to the treatment, it could be argued that these results are as much evidence of priming as they are of fluency.Footnote 72 Specifically, the recall question might serve to ‘prime’ the consideration of the veracity of the rumor.

Table 7 provides suggestive evidence that this rehearsal effect persists over time, and is not merely the influence of ephemeral priming. This table presents the Wave 1 and Wave 2 results for respondents interviewed in both waves of the CCES. The differences on the euthanasia question, which are substantively large (though, admittedly, not statistically significant), remain nearly identical a month later.Footnote 73 This table also provides some evidence that, over time, the power of the correction diminishes. Though not statistically significant, the rumor rejection rates drop for those respondents in the rumor and correction condition, especially for those in the long-recall condition. The pattern of responses for those in the rumor only condition, however, remains stable. This is suggestive evidence that, in line with the expectations from Schwarz’s work, merely increasing the fluency of a rumor increases its effectiveness.Footnote 74 This result is important because the long-recall condition more accurately represents the volume with which rumors are repeated and magnified in today’s media environment.

Table 7 Effect of Rumor Rehearsal on Euthanasia Rumor Belief Over Time, October–November 2010

Rumor Only: N=289; χ2(2)=4.82; Pr=0.09; Rumor+Correction: N=285; χ2(2)=0.52; Pr=0.77.

Rumor Only: N=289; χ2(2)=4.07; Rumor+Correction: Pr=0.13; N=285; χ2(2)=2.45; Pr=0.29.

Discussion and Conclusion

By understanding how and why people come to reject false beliefs, we can learn how to loosen their hold on destructive pieces of misinformation. In two different studies using two separate samples (one in which I measured general attentiveness to the survey, and one in which I did not), I come to a similar conclusion. Though partisanship colors how citizens process information about public policy, my studies show that under the right circumstances – with the right arguments made by the right people – corrections can increase rumor rejection rates among the mass public, regardless of their partisan predilections. In particular, corrections acquire credibility when politicians make statements that run counter to their personal and political interests.

These experiments present especially difficult tests of the power of corrections. In order to most directly address the question of how best to dislodge rumors, I used real-world rumors. However, as a result, my treatments competed against the rhetoric surrounding health reform in the political world. As I discuss below, media coverage of death panels increased rumor fluency by often repeating the rumor without an effective correction. That sustained media environment may, therefore, make it difficult for a single experimental correction to significantly increase rumor rejection rates. In addition, when constructing my treatments I limited myself to actual statements made by politicians in the heat of the health care debate. Altogether, these factors curb the power of any experimental effects; my results emerge despite – and not because of – the political environment at the time.

As a result, though the substantive size of the effects in this article is admittedly modest, there are important lessons to take from these results. To correct rumors, we must account for the power of partisanship – and try to neutralize it. As noted above, politicians who attempt to counter rumors often appeal to non-partisan authorities. For instance, to fight the death panel rumors, experts from the AMA and the AARP were called in to ‘speak the truth’. But, ironically, in a politically polarized time, those non-partisan ‘authoritative’ voices often lack authority because they are easily drowned out by more politicized ones. In the modern political environment, ‘independent’ sources that are credible to both Democrats and Republicans are hard to find. Consider, for example, the AMA and the AARP. A September 2009 NPR/KFF/Harvard telephone survey assessed the level of confidence that the public had in various groups to ‘recommend the right thing for the country when it comes to health care’.Footnote 75 Democrats and Republicans indeed held similar views of the AMA. Among Democrats, 23 per cent of respondents said they had a great deal of confidence in the AMA and 45 per cent had a fair amount of confidence – not a ringing endorsement, but a reasonable level of trust. Republicans expressed similar levels of trust – 20 per cent had a great deal of confidence and 45 per cent had a fair amount of confidence. However, there were large partisan gaps in the assessment of the AARP. Among Democrats, 29 per cent had a great deal of confidence and 40 per cent had a fair amount of confidence. But among Republicans, only 16 per cent had a great deal of confidence and 27 per cent had a fair amount of confidence – overall, a 26 percentage-point gap across the two categories.

That said, under the right circumstances, partisanship can be harnessed as a force for truth. In particular, politicized voices can help debunk false statements circulating in society. When I paired the death panel story with a quote debunking the rumor from a Republican who helped draft the end-of-life provisions, respondents – Republicans and Democrats alike – were far more likely to reject the euthanasia rumor. In the real world, these types of corrections from unexpected partisan sources exist, but they are admittedly rare. I performed a content analysis of all evening news stories broadcast from January 2009 to December 2012 that mentioned ‘death panels’ on ABC, CBS, NBC, CNN and FOX. While the rumor was presented without a correction only 7 per cent of the time, corrections from unlikely sources were rare as well; only 10 per cent of the stories paired the rumor with a correction from a Republican source.Footnote 76 Put simply, the media created an environment that fostered the continued spread of death panel rumors. However, this does not have to be the case. There are always partisans – like Senator Isakson on health care – who are interested in disseminating the truth. Perhaps amplifying those voices could be effective. After all, though I find that the power of corrections fade and rumors regain their strength over time, both studies demonstrated that the Republican correction remained strong, even after weeks in the midst of a heated real-world debate about the future of health care reform.

It may be hard to find such silver linings to other troubling results regarding the effects of fluency. Fluency is a powerful force – one that may provide a mechanism for understanding how rumors take hold and persist. Simply asking subjects to repeat the rumor to themselves – without any indication that it is true – increases their willingness to believe the existence of death panels, even weeks after they read the initial story. In the real world, rumors are repeated and cemented in the echo chamber of the internet. This is true not simply in the United States, but also in other countries.Footnote 77 Thus, the effects found here may play out on a larger scale in a variety of societies. But even given these findings, there may be hope. Perhaps the power of fluency could be harnessed to increase the effectiveness of corrections. Just as rumors can multiply their power through repetition, perhaps corrections can as well. Future work should explore such possibilities.Footnote 78 Until we know how to correct false information, rumors and innuendo will remain powerful forces in politics around the world.

Footnotes

*

Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Department of Political Science (email: berinsky@mit.edu). For valuable discussions regarding this article, I would like to thank seminar participants at The California Institute of Technology, Florida State University, MIT, University of Michigan, The West Coast Experiments Conference and Yale University. Special thanks go to Jamie Druckman, Gabe Lenz, Michael Tesler and Nick Valentino for detailed comments. I thank Justin de Benedictis-Kessner, Daniel de Kadt, Seth Dickinson, Daniel Guenther, Krista Loose, Michele Margolis and Mike Sances for research assistance. Financial support was provided by the National Science Foundation (SES-1015335), the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences and MIT. Data replication sets and online appendices are available at http://dx.doi.org/doi:10.1017/S0007123415000186.

2 http://people-press.org/, accessed 2 April 2015; http://people-press.org/files/legacy-pdf/537.pdf, accessed 2 April 2015.

3 In actuality, the plan included provisions to pay doctors to counsel patients about end-of-life options.

5 DiFonzo and Bordia Reference DiFonzo and Bordia2007.

6 Sunstein Reference Sunstein2009, 6; see also Fine and Ellis Reference Fine and Ellis2010.

7 Fine and Ellis Reference Fine and Ellis2010; see also Allport and Postman Reference Allport and Postman1947.

10 Allport and Postman Reference Allport and Postman1947.

16 Some scholars claim that respondents use surveys instrumentally as a vehicle to express more basic political judgements about politicians and the policies they oppose. In other work I examine this claim and conclude that the vast majority of expressions of rumor acceptance in fact represent the true beliefs of respondents.

17 See Nyhan Reference Nyhan2010.

21 See also Prasad et al. (Reference Prasad, Perrin, Bezila, Hoffman, Kindleberger, Manturuk and Powers2009) on Iraq and Nyhan, Reifler, and Ubel (Reference Nyhan, Reifler and Ubel2013) on death panels.

22 DiFonzo and Bordia Reference DiFonzo and Bordia2007.

23 DiFonzo and Bordia Reference DiFonzo and Bordia2007.

25 Taber and Lodge Reference Taber and Lodge2006.

26 Bartels Reference Bartels2002.

27 Petty and Cacioppo Reference Petty and Cacioppo1986. For a political science application, see Lupia and McCubbins (Reference Lupia and McCubbins1998).

28 Calvert Reference Calvert1985.

29 Calvert Reference Calvert1985, 546.

32 Schwarz, Skurnick, and Yoon Reference Schwarz, Sanna, Skurnik and Yoon2007.

33 Oppenheimer Reference Oppenheimer2008, 237. Fluency is therefore a mental state arising between the interaction of an individual person and information in the environment.

34 Tversky and Kahneman Reference Tversky and Kahneman1981.

35 Alter and Oppenheimer Reference Alter and Oppenheimer2009.

36 Schwarz Reference Schwarz2004.

37 Schwarz Reference Schwarz2004; for a review, see Alter and Oppenheimer Reference Alter and Oppenheimer2009. Fluency can be induced by any process that makes it easier to process new information, including the color and font of the text. But the end result is the same. As Alter and Oppenheimer aptly note in their review of research on fluency, ‘fluency is a general mechanism that influences truth judgments independently of how it is instantiated’ (228).

38 Jacoby and Dallas Reference Jacoby and Dallas1981.

39 Begg, Anas, and Farinacci Reference Begg, Anas and Farinacci1992; Gilbert, Tafarodi, and Malone Reference Gilbert, Tafarodi and Malone1993. In the realm of rumor, see Difonzo and Bordia (Reference DiFonzo and Bordia2007).

41 Schwarz, Skurnick, and Yoon Reference Schwarz, Sanna, Skurnik and Yoon2007.

42 Schwarz, Skurnick, and Yoon Reference Schwarz, Sanna, Skurnik and Yoon2007.

43 As the researchers note, with a delay, the subjects retained an incomplete recollection of the statements on the poster. When faced with such incomplete memories, people tend to think of recalled information as true, regardless of the initial presentational context.

46 The survey was administered online to a large national sample of 1,701 American adults from 17–19 May 2010. The second wave of the survey was administered to 699 of the initial respondents from 25–29 May 2010. The study was conducted by Survey Sampling International (SSI) of Shelton, CT. I did not employ quotas, but asked SSI to construct a target population that matched the (eighteen and over) census population on education, gender, age, geography and income. The resulting sample is not a probability sample, but is a diverse national sample. The description of the sample characteristics is presented in Appendix B.

47 Schwarz Reference Schwarz2004.

48 The treatment contained a typo, identifying Blumenauer’s home state as Georgia. Follow-up studies indicate that this typo did not change the basic pattern of the results of the experiment.

49 I ran a study of 1,354 respondents on Mechanical Turk from 17–25 November 2014 to see if people perceive the text of the Isakson and Blumenauer quotes as functionally the same – that is, if people view them as equally strong denouncements of the rumor. I presented the full version of the ‘rumor + correction’ condition but experimentally varied the final quote. Specifically I used a 3×2 design with one dimension as the relevant quotes denouncing the rumor (‘Blatant Lie’ vs. ‘Nuts’) and the other dimension as the speaker of the quote (the Republican Isakson vs. the Democrat Blumenauer vs. a third non-partisan speaker Ben Johnson, who was identified as ‘the chairman of the Bipartisan Advisory Committee on Healthcare Reform’). I then asked respondents to rate how strongly they thought that [Politician X] accepts or rejects the idea of ‘death panels’ being in the health care bill. I found that there were no statistically or substantively significant differences in the perceived strength of the two corrections, regardless of the source of the quote.

50 Respondents were also asked: (1) ‘Do you think the changes to the health care system have that have been enacted by Congress and the Obama administration create “death panels” which have the authority to determine whether or not a gravely ill or injured person should receive health care based on their “level of productivity in society?”’ (2) ‘Overall, given what you know about them, would you say you support or oppose the changes to the health care system that have been enacted by Congress and the Obama administration’?

51 Simmons, Nelson, and Simonsohn Reference Simmons, Nelson and Simonsohn2011.

52 Oppenheimer, Meyvis, and Davidenko Reference Oppenheimer, Meyvis and Davidenko2009.

53 Krosnick Reference Krosnick1991.

54 The IMCs function much the same way as a ‘manipulation check’ in this regard (see Berinsky, Margolis, and Sances Reference Berinsky, Margolis and Sances2014). There were no significant differences across the experimental conditions in levels of attentiveness. The sample characteristics of this ‘attentive’ sample are presented in Appendix B.

55 Berinsky, Margolis, and Sances Reference Berinsky, Margolis and Sances2014. For example, people who pass screener questions are more likely to demonstrate the framing effects uncovered by Tversky and Kahneman (1981). Those authors report that, when a potential policy was framed in terms of ‘lives saved’, respondents were more likely to pick the certain choice. When it was framed in terms of lives lost, respondents were more likely to pick the risky choice. However Berinsky, Margolis, and Sances find that this effect only occurs among people who pass a screener question asked immediately before the framing experiment. Subjects who fail the screener show no difference.

56 In this study, I used a three-category dependent variable. In other studies, I followed up this initial question with a probe of belief strength to create a seven-point scale of rumor acceptance. The results in those studies are essentially the same using the seven-point scale and the three-point scale.

57 The full sample results are presented in Appendix B.

58 Interestingly, this backlash effect does not occur among Republicans – probably because support for the reform plan is so low across all conditions. It should also be noted that while rumor acceptance levels could mediate the effect of rumor exposure on policy choice, I do not have the data necessary to test such a hypothesis.

59 Schwarz Reference Schwarz2004.

60 To test for declining effects more formally, I estimated difference-in-differences OLS regressions for the pairwise comparisons (the results were essentially the same using multinomial logits). Interaction terms are, of course, difficult to infer much from, as they are often very imprecisely estimated. In this regression, all p-values are greater than 0.1, but five are only slightly greater than 0.1. The tests are still somewhat suggestive of a declining treatment effect. The full results are presented in Appendix B.

61 In July 2010, I ran an additional study with YouGov to directly test the expectations regarding the effectiveness of different corrective strategies. The results of this experiment are consistent with the studies in this article and are presented in Appendix D.

62 This treatment could also be thought of as the ‘correct information’ treatment.

63 It should be noted that I tried to develop IMC items for this survey, but they were not effectively deployed. As a result, the IMCs did not effectively discriminate attentiveness according to the standards described in Berinsky, Margolis, and Sances (Reference Berinsky, Margolis and Sances2014).

64 I reran a limited version of this study with a control group from May to July 2011. The effects of the treatment were similar to those found here, while the difference between the control and treatment groups was in line with those found in earlier experiments.

65 Schwarz Reference Schwarz2004.

66 Admittedly, this second exposure to the rumor might have also triggered other cognitive mechanisms besides fluency that would increase the treatment effect. However, the results presented here are consistent with the mechanism of fluency.

67 The sample characteristics of the CCES study are presented in Appendix G.

68 Schwarz Reference Schwarz2004.

69 Druckman and Nelson 2003.

70 The difference in the differences across the two conditions between the irrelevant-recall and long-recall conditions is non-significant.

71 Results presented in Appendix G show that the substantive effect of the rehearsal treatment carries over from beliefs about rumor to health care reform opinion, though these differences are not statistically significant.

73 A parametric difference-in-differences test for change in the difference over time shows that the differences are stable (the results of this analysis are presented in Appendix G).

74 Schwarz Reference Schwarz2004.

75 The survey was conducted from 27 August through 13 September 2009. A nationally representative sample of 1,278 adults was interviewed by landline and cell phone.

76 There were fifty-two stories. In these stories, 30 per cent paired the rumor with a correction from a Democratic source, 43 per cent paired the rumor with a correction from a journalist and 4 per cent of the mentions paired the rumor with a non-partisan correction. The content analysis protocol and a detailed description of the coding procedure are presented in Appendix H.

78 However, this might not be enough. Ecker et al. (Reference Ecker, Lewandowsky, Swire and Chang2011) explore such a strategy and find that even multiple retractions were insufficient to eliminate the continued influence misinformation completely.

References

Allport, Gordon W., and Postman, Leo. 1947. The Psychology of Rumor. New York: Henry Holt & Co.Google Scholar
Alter, Adam L., and Oppenheimer, Daniel. 2009. Uniting the Tribes of Fluency to Form a Metacognitive Nation. Personality and Social Psychology Review 13 (3):219235.Google Scholar
Bargh, John A., Bond, Ronald N., Lombardi, Wendy J., and Tota, Mary E.. 1986. The Additive Nature of Chronic and Temporary Sources of Construct Accessibility. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 50:869878.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartels, Larry M. 2002. Beyond the Running Tally: Partisan Bias in Political Perceptions. Political Behavior 24 (2):117150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Begg, Ian Maynard, Anas, Ann, and Farinacci, Suzanne. 1992. Dissociation of Processes in Belief: Source Recollection, Statement Familiarity, and the Illusion of Truth. Journal of Experimental Psychology 121 (4):446458.Google Scholar
Berinsky, Adam J., Margolis, Michele F., and Sances, Michael W.. 2014. Separating the Shirkers from the Workers? Making Sure Respondents Pay Attention on Self-Administered Surveys. American Journal of Political Science 58 (3):739753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhavnani, Ravi, Findley, Michael G., and Kuklinski, James H.. 2009. Rumor Dynamics in Ethnic Violence. The Journal of Politics 71 (3):876892.Google Scholar
Bolten, Catherine. 2014. Sobel Truths and Tribal Truths: Narrative and Politics in Sierra Leone, 1994. Comparative Studies in Society and History 56:187214.Google Scholar
Brotherton, Robert, French, Christopher C., and Pickering, Alan D.. 2013. Measuring Belief in Conspiracy Theories: The Generic Conspiracist Beliefs Scale. Frontiers in Psychology 4 (279):115.Google Scholar
Bruder, Martin, Haffke, Peter, Neave, Nick, Nouripanah, Nina, and Imhoff, Roland. 2013. Measuring Individual Differences in Generic Beliefs in Conspiracy Theories Across Cultures: The Conspiracy Mentality Questionnaire. Frontiers in Psychology 4 (225):115.Google Scholar
Calvert, Randall L. 1985. The Value of Biased Information: A Rational Choice Model of Political Advice. The Journal of Politics 47 (2):530555.Google Scholar
DiFonzo, Nicholas, and Bordia, Prashant. 2007. Rumor Psychology: Social and Organizational Approaches. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.Google Scholar
Donovan, Pamela. 2007. How Idle is Idle Talk? One Hundred Years of Rumor Research. Diogenes 54 (1):5982.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Druckman, James N., and Nelson, Kjersten R.. 2003. Framing and Deliberation: How Citizens’ Conversations Limit Elite Influence. American Journal of Political Science 47 (4):729745.Google Scholar
Ecker, Ullrich K.H., Lewandowsky, Stephan, Swire, Briony, and Chang, Darren. 2011. Correcting False Information in Memory: Manipulating the Strength of Misinformation Encoding and its Retraction. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 18 (3):570578.Google Scholar
Fine, Gary Allen, and Ellis, Bill. 2010. The Global Grapevine: Why Rumors of Terrorism, Immigration, and Trade Matter. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Finnström, Sverker. 2009. Gendered War and Rumors of Saddam Hussein in Uganda. Anthropology and Humanism 34 (1):6170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, Daniel T., Tafarodi, Romin W., and Malone, Patrick S.. 1993. You Can’t Not Believe Everything You Read. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65:221233.Google Scholar
Gilens, Martin. 2001. Political Ignorance and Collective Policy Preferences. The American Political Science Review 95 (2):379396.Google Scholar
Huang, Haifeng. 2014. A War of (Mis)Information: The Political Effects of Rumors and Rumor Rebuttals in an Authoritarian Country, working paper. University of California, Merced. Available from http://ssrn.com/abstract=2131538, accessed 6 April 2015.Google Scholar
Jacoby, Larry L., and Dallas, Mark. 1981. On the Relationship Between Autobiographical Memory and Perceptual Learning. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 110 (3):306340.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jo, Dong-Gi. 2002. Diffusion of Rumors on the Internet. The Information Society Review 2002:7795.Google Scholar
Johnson, Hollyn M., and Seifert, Colleen. 1994. Sources of the Continued Influence Effect: When Misinformation in Memory Affects Later Inferences. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 20 (6):14201436.Google Scholar
Keeley, Brian L. 1999. Of Conspiracy Theories. The Journal of Philosophy 96 (3):109126.Google Scholar
Krosnick, Jon A. 1991. Response Strategies for Coping with the Cognitive Demands of Attitude Measures in Surveys. Applied Cognitive Psychology 5:213236.Google Scholar
Kuklinski, James H., Quirk, Paul J., Jerit, Jennifer, Schwieder, David, and Rich, Robert F.. 2000. Misinformation and the Currency of Democratic Citizenship. The Journal of Politics 62 (3):790816.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kunda, Ziva. 1990. The Case for Motivated Reasoning. Psychological Bulletin 8 (3):480498.Google Scholar
Lewandowsky, Stephan, Ecker, Ullrich K.H., Seifert, Colleen M., Schwarz, Norbert, and Cook, John. 2012. Misinformation and its Correction Continued Influence and Successful Debiasing. Psychological Science in the Public Interest 13 (3):106131.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lupia, Arthur, and McCubbins, Matthew. 1998. The Democratic Dilemma: Can Citizens Learn What They Need to Know? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ma, Ringo. 2008. Spread of SARS and War-Related Rumors Through New Media in China. Communication Quarterly 56 (4):376391.Google Scholar
Nyhan, Brendan. 2010. Why the ‘Death Panel’ Myth Wouldn’t Die: Misinformation in the Health Care Reform Debate. The Forum 8 (1):124.Google Scholar
Nyhan, Brendan, and Reifler, Jason. 2009. The Effects of Semantics and Social Desirability in Correcting the Obama Muslim Myth, working paper. Dartmouth University.Google Scholar
Nyhan, Brendan, and Reifler, Jason. 2010. When Corrections Fail: The Persistence of Political Misperceptions. Political Behavior 32 (2):303330.Google Scholar
Nyhan, Brendan, Reifler, Jason, and Ubel, Peter A.. 2013. The Hazards of Correcting Myths About Health Care Reform. Medical Care 51 (2):127132.Google Scholar
Oliver, J. Eric, and Wood, Thomas J.. 2014. Conspiracy Theories, Magical Thinking, and the Paranoid Style(s) of Mass Opinion. American Journal of Political Science 58 (4):952966.Google Scholar
Oppenheimer, Daniel. 2008. The Secret Life of Fluency. Trends in Cognitive Science 12 (6):237241.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Oppenheimer, Daniel, Meyvis, Tom, and Davidenko, Nicolas. 2009. Instructional Manipulation Checks: Detecting Satisficing to Increase Statistical Power. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 45:867872.Google Scholar
Palin, Sarah. 2009. Statement on the Current Health Care Debate. Facebook post. Available from https://www.facebook.com/note.php?note_id=113851103434, accessed 6 April 2015.Google Scholar
Petty, Richard E., and Cacioppo, John T.. 1986. The Elaboration Likelihood Model of Persuasion. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 19:123205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pipes, Daniel. 1998. The Hidden Hand: Middle East Fears of Conspiracy. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Prasad, Monica, Perrin, Andrew J., Bezila, Kieran, Hoffman, Steve G., Kindleberger, Kate, Manturuk, Kim, and Powers, Ashleigh Smith. 2009. ‘There Must be a Reason’: Osama, Saddam, and Inferred Justification. Sociological Inquiry 79 (2):142162.Google Scholar
Schwarz, Norbert. 2004. Metacognitive Experiences in Consumer Judgment and Decision Making. Journal of Consumer Psychology 14:332348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwarz, Norbert, Sanna, Lawrence J., Skurnik, Ian, and Yoon, Carolyn. 2007. Metacognitive Experiences and the Intricacies of Setting People Straight: Implications for Debiasing and Public Information Campaigns. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 39:127161.Google Scholar
Simmons, Joseph, Nelson, Leif D., and Simonsohn, Uri. 2011. False-Positive Psychology: Undisclosed Flexibility in Data Collection and Analysis Allows Presenting Anything as Significant. Psychological Science 22:13591366.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R.. 2009. On Rumors: How Falsehoods Spread, Why We Believe Them, What Can Be Done. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Taber, Charles S., and Lodge, Milton. 2006. Motivated Skepticism in the Evaluation of Political Beliefs. American Journal of Political Science 50 (3):755769.Google Scholar
Tversky, Amos, and Kahneman, Daniel. 1981. The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice. Science 211 (4481):453458.Google Scholar
Wood, Michael J., Douglas, Karen M., and Sutton, Robbie M.. 2012. Dead and Alive Beliefs in Contradictory Conspiracy Theories. Social Psychological and Personality Science 3 (6):767773.Google Scholar
Zonis, Marvin, and Joseph, Craig M.. 1994. Conspiracy Thinking in the Middle East. Political Psychology 15 (3):443459.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1 Effect of Treatments on Euthanasia Rumor Belief, May 2010

Figure 1

Table 2 Effect of Treatments on Health Care Policy Opinion, May 2010 (Attentive Sample)

Figure 2

Table 3 Effect of Treatments on Euthanasia Rumor Belief Over Time for Respondents Interviewed in Both Waves, May 2010

Figure 3

Table 4 Effect of Treatments on Euthanasia Rumor Belief, October 2010

Figure 4

Table 5 Effect of Treatments on Euthanasia Rumor Belief Over Time, October–November 2010

Figure 5

Table 6 Effect of Rumor Rehearsal on Euthanasia Rumor Belief, October 2010

Figure 6

Table 7 Effect of Rumor Rehearsal on Euthanasia Rumor Belief Over Time, October–November 2010

Supplementary material: File

Berinsky supplemetary material

Supplementary data sets

Download Berinsky supplemetary material(File)
File 44.4 KB
Supplementary material: PDF

Berinsky supplemenray material

Supplementary Appendices

Download Berinsky supplemenray material(PDF)
PDF 365.4 KB