Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gvvz8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-22T05:42:37.517Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theories or No Theories—Is Anything Evolving?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 October 2023

Matti Häyry*
Affiliation:
School of Business, Aalto University, Espoo, Finland
Tuija Takala
Affiliation:
School of Business, Aalto University, Espoo, Finland
*
Corresponding author: Matti Häyry; Email: matti.hayry@aalto.fi
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Editorial
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

R. M. Hare suggested half a century ago: “If philosophers are going to apply ethical theory successfully to practical issues, they must first have a theory.”Footnote 1 Apart from the obvious literal interpretation—if you want to apply something, you must have that something—he may have been right or wrong. Many bioethicists do well without explicit theories and even those who rely on theories develop them all the time.Footnote 2 , Footnote 3 , Footnote 4 , Footnote 5 , Footnote 6 , Footnote 7 This special section contains eight contributions pertaining to the topic.

The Role of Theories and Arguments

The first four entries discuss the role of theories and extant arguments in bioethics. Can good bioethical work be done without involving grand theories? What was the vision of the field’s pioneers on its workings? Apart from the discipline’s obvious pragmatic aim, does it have room for pragmatism as an ethical theory? Does the nature and use of bioethical arguments evolve as the real-life phenomena studied become more familiar and mundane?

Søren Holm opens the proceedings by addressing the first question. According to him, purely critical and empirical contributions to bioethics can easily survive without involving major theoretical frameworks. As long as the aim is to show flaws in existing views and policy suggestions, authors can simply point out inconsistencies in the argumentation or discrepancies in the presentation of the facts of the case in hand. When it comes to constructive efforts, however, the situation is different. If the aim is to provide a new argument or a new approach, reliance on a wider moral or political view is often required. And even analyses that do not initially seem to lean on substantive ethical doctrines have to seek support from theory fragments or formal principles such as analogies and reflective equilibria.Footnote 8

Mathias Schutz examines the early programmatic declaration in Daniel Callahan’s 1973 essay “Bioethics as a Discipline.”Footnote 9 Callahan made a plea for a comprehensive approach embracing all the academic fields that are involved in solving the biological, medical, psychological, social, political, and cultural issues in biomedical research, clinical work, and healthcare arrangements. His ideal was systematic knowledge and understanding. Instead, bioethics soon became a project concentrating on particular issues—abortion, euthanasia, the ethics of genetics, to name a few—and dominated by philosophy, clinical medicine, and law, at the expense of theology, history, and the social sciences. The advent of principlism a few years later was an attempt to reconcile belief systems and faith traditions, but it also turned bioethics into a problem-solving machine with no time for wider connections.Footnote 10 , Footnote 11 , Footnote 12

The way bioethical inquiries should be conducted has, of course, been vividly discussed ever since. Suggestions, in addition to principlism, have included theory-driven consequentialismFootnote 13 , Footnote 14 , Footnote 15 , Footnote 16 , Footnote 17 , Footnote 18 , Footnote 19 , Footnote 20 and deontology;Footnote 21 , Footnote 22 , Footnote 23 , Footnote 24 practice-based casuistry and virtue ethics;Footnote 25 , Footnote 26 , Footnote 27 , Footnote 28 , Footnote 29 , Footnote 30 justice-oriented political philosophy;Footnote 31 , Footnote 32 , Footnote 33 feminist approaches;Footnote 34 , Footnote 35 post-colonial perspectives;Footnote 36 , Footnote 37 , Footnote 38 and pleas to delimit the normative force of conceptual analyses.Footnote 39 , Footnote 40 , Footnote 41 , Footnote 42 , Footnote 43 , Footnote 44 , Footnote 45 A focal topic debated is often the practical usefulness of academic considerations.

Henrik Rydenfelt addresses this issue in light of Charles S. Peirce and John Dewey’s idea of experimental inquiry solving ethical problems. Moral views and public policies can be supported by using a method familiar from the natural sciences, the confirmation and disconfirmation of hypotheses through experimentation. The hypotheses are the views and policy suggestions; and the evidence that can be used to verify or falsify them, according to Peirce, is provided by feelings as “emotional interpretants.” Dewey also argued that moderate democratic development is to be preferred to unrestrained social and political change.Footnote 46 , Footnote 47 , Footnote 48 , Footnote 49 , Footnote 50

Jonathan Glover echoed Peirce’s idea in his 1977 book Causing Death and Saving Lives. Matti Häyry in 1994 summarized his position as follows:

Glover argued in his book that contemporary moral, social, and political issues can be studied systematically by methods which are not unlike those used in scientific research. Moral principles can, according to Glover’s view, be falsified by appeals to inconsistency and incoherence, and further tested by observing the responses provoked in various individuals by their application to reality. Glover believed that the logical and conceptual tests of consistency and coherence can objectively establish or refute general moral principles, whereas the role of people’s moral responses is, due to the possibilities of manipulation and cultural differences, more problematical. The task of applied ethicists in the model is to develop moral rules and regulations which are maximally acceptable and reasonably applicable to real-life moral issues.Footnote 51

Häyry went on to formulate a multistep reiterative method of applied ethics based on Glover’s outline. In addition to the logic-responses division, two intertwined tasks were identified for the philosopher: cognitive deprogramming and rational reconstruction. As for the first:

Conceptual cognitive deprogramming consists of the analysis and critical assessment of the terms and arguments which have been used in the formulation of everyday moral rules and principles. If the terminology in use is ambiguous, or if the inferences made are invalid, the rules and principles in question must be either reformulated or rejected. Emotional cognitive deprogramming, in its turn, centres on the use of idealized or imaginary examples. These examples are normally designed to portray how, under particular hypothetical circumstances, apparently reasonable moral rules and principles lead to actions which have intuitively unacceptable consequences. Imaginary cases cannot be employed to establish moral views or to refute them absolutely or objectively, but if they are well chosen, they can in many cases provide good grounds for abandoning certain prima facie approvable ethical rules and principles.Footnote 52

Once all questionable alternatives have been refuted, the philosopher should try to rationally reconstruct a view that would fare better. There is a limitation, however, in the moral response, or emotional, part of the analysis:

While conceptual consistency and logical soundness may yield to objective criteria, intuitive acceptability is often the function of the deep values which persist in the community under scrutiny. The conclusions of the applied ethicist are in these cases ad hominem, or of the form: “Since your own basic norms, values and beliefs are this-and-this, and you presumably wish to be consistent, you ought to consider it your duty or right to have or to do that-and-that.” Reconstruction instead of free creation is therefore frequently needed.Footnote 53

In the methods of applied ethics defined by these passages, elaborating on Glover’s sketch, the bioethical community would have had the scientific, experimental approach Rydenfelt calls for, complete with Peirce’s emotional interpretants as the backbone of the intuitive examination and Dewey’s requirement of cautious democracy in the ad hominem nature of the conclusions. For better or for worse, however, the proposal has gone largely unnoticed by the community for 30 years.

Sergei Shevchenko and Alexey Zhavoronkov highlight one reason for the avoidance of strict, timeless logic in the analyses of moral conundrums. New medical and biomedical developments sometimes raise fears that prevent ethicists from using one-to-one comparisons with earlier, better-known practices. The developments—the spread of the human immunodeficiency virus,Footnote 54 , Footnote 55 advances in genetic screening, Footnote 56 , Footnote 57 , Footnote 58 the rapid rise of neuroscience,Footnote 59 , Footnote 60 and the like—then receive special treatment under the banner of exceptionalism. For the people who have the conditions or should receive services or treatments, this can mean exclusion. Familiarity with the condition or technology often removes, in time, the perceived need for the exception and exclusion.Footnote 61

New and Revised Theories and Arguments

The four remaining contributions present new and revised ideas for the consideration of bioethicists and discuss their merits. Theories can be built from scratch, using notions from other fields as springboards, or they can lean on concepts and doctrines already in circulation. In both cases, they systemize and balance our basic intuitions, an approach defined by Henry Sidgwick in his 1874 book The Methods of Ethics. Footnote 62 He first established the credibility of the fundamental intuitions of justice (like cases should be treated alike), prudence (we should pursue our long-term self-interest), and the universality of goodness (everybody’s interests should count equally). Armed with these, he assessed the main contenders for an overarching ethical theory: intuitionism (for him, both prevailing traditional morality and Kantian and Aristotelian doctrines), rational egoism (I am allowed to pursue my interests and so is everyone else), and universal altruism (utilitarianism). In the end, he could not make a final decision between rational egoism and universal altruism,Footnote 63 a conundrum that we shall witness in one of our contributions.

Steven Firth presents a new theory of disability, claiming that all existing approaches fail to capture the essence of the phenomenon. The medical model treats disability as a disease, an individual’s malfunctioning; and the social model sees it as a political construction caused by the unwillingness of others to make proper adjustments.Footnote 64 , Footnote 65 Firth’s picture theory sees disability as the negative experience a person has confronted with the inability to perform tasks related to daily living or to reaching life goals taken for granted by the nondisabled. When the medical model asks “What is it?” and the social model “Why is it?” Firth’s picture theory asks “How does it feel?”Footnote 66 This concentration on people’s own experiences can also be extended to characterizations of life’s quality and value more generally.Footnote 67 , Footnote 68

Firth’s definition could easily be seen as complementary to the standards views, each having their own angle. The medical approach attempts to be objective, the social model is deliberately intersubjective, and the picture theory can be seen as their subjective counterpart. Interestingly, Firth’s account seems to exclude those who cannot picture their own lives in comparison with others—and who therefore cannot see the negativity of their experience. People with profound intellectual and multiple disabilities could be an example. They are disabled medically and (possibly) socially but not pictorially. They are not consciously facing an inability to reach their goals but rather experiencing their own particular human condition.

Matti Häyry proceeds in a more Sidgwickian manner and tries to find a balance between basic utilitarian and liberal intuitions—an endeavor that has engaged him before. Footnote 69 , Footnote 70 , Footnote 71 , Footnote 72 , Footnote 73 , Footnote 74 , Footnote 75 His starting point is negative utilitarianism—the view that our first and foremost duty is to eliminate and prevent bad, not to maximize good, as in the classical utilitarianism of Jeremy Bentham.Footnote 76 Following his liberal convictions, Häyry makes two revisions to the creed. He names two values—the need to avoid suffering and the need not to have one’s autonomy dwarfed—and postulates that only clear cases of need frustration without conflicts of basic interests generate moral duties straightforwardly. When the fundamental needs of several agents or patients clash, the cases must be assessed (also) by nonutilitarian criteria.Footnote 77

Karim Akerma provides a critical commentary to Häyry’s suggestion. He observes that the revised view could match people’s intuitions marginally better than the more orthodox version of negative utilitarianism—which would make ending sentient life on earth a moral duty. He argues, however, that a slightly less orthodox reading of the doctrine would remedy the situation without the need to introduce autonomy as an almost independent principle like Häyry does. If the end of moral action is to reduce suffering and if suffering is understood as a category wider than mere physical pain, respect for people’s own choices would be automatically included in complete assessments.Footnote 78 Akerma’s analysis highlights the difference between those who abide by pure, aggregative utilitarianism and those who waver when an individual’s self-direction ceases to be an entitlement and becomes a measurable factor in a utility calculation.

Matti Häyry and Amanda Sukenick present what they call a new argument for antinatalism. Also touched upon in the contributions by Akerma and Häyry, antinatalism is a view that assigns a negative value to reproduction and maintains that people should not have children. Häyry and Sukenick argue that standard defenses of the creed are complicated and counterintuitive to the degree that a novel angle is needed. They identify talk about non-existing beings—“The unborn have a right not to become existent.”—difficult for lay audiences to grasp and propose a shift of focus to those who already live. The authors maintain that pronatalism is such a strong force that children are almost automatically indoctrinated into believing in its blessings. And since the indoctrination takes place before they can form their own opinions, the arrangement violates their right to an open future. This postnatal mental imposition, Häyry and Sukenick conclude, makes the cycle of procreation undesirable.Footnote 79

Financial Support

The research was supported financially by the Jenny and Antti Wihuri Foundation, project “Justice in Crisis,” and the Ministry of Agriculture and Forestry of Finland, project decision VN/2470/2022 “Justainability.”

Competing Interest

The author declares none.

References

Notes

1. Hare, RM Abortion and the golden rule. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1975;4:201–22Google ScholarPubMed.

2. Häyry, M. Abortion and applied ethics. In: Peden, C, Roth, JK, eds. Rights, Justice, and Community. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press; 1992:177–86Google Scholar.

3. Häyry, M, Takala, T, eds. Scratching the Surface of Bioethics. Amsterdam/New York, NY: Rodopi; 2003 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4. Häyry, M, Takala, T, Herissone-Kelly, P, eds. Bioethics and Social Reality. Amsterdam/New York, NY: Rodopi; 2005 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5. Takala, T, Herissone-Kelly, P, Holm, S, eds. Cutting Through the Surface: Philosophical Approaches to Bioethics. Amsterdam/New York, NY: Rodopi; 2009 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6. Häyry, M, Takala, T, Herissone-Kelly, P, Árnason, G, eds. Arguments and Analysis in Bioethics. Amsterdam/New York, NY: Rodopi; 2010 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7. Takala, T, Häyry, M, eds. Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics in the Social Sciences. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar CrossRefGoogle Scholar; forthcoming.

8. Holm, S. Bioethics without theory? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2024;33 Google ScholarPubMed; forthcoming. doi:10.1017/S0963180123000348.

9. Callahan, D. Bioethics as a discipline. Hastings Center Studies 1973;1:6673 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

10. Schutz, M. Strategic ambiguity: The pragmatic utopianism of Daniel Callahan’s “bioethics as a discipline.” Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2024;33 Google Scholar; forthcoming. doi:10.1017/S0963180123000440.

11. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedical ethics [orig. 1979]. 8th ed. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2019.

12. Häyry, M, Takala, T, eds. Common morality. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2022;31:161219 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

13. Glover, J. Causing Death and Saving Lives: The Moral Problems of Abortion, Infanticide, Suicide, Euthanasia, Capital Punishment, War and Other Life-or-Death Choices. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books; 1977 Google Scholar.

14. Singer, P. Practical Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1979 Google Scholar.

15. Harris, J. The Value of Life: An Introduction to Medical Ethics. London: Routledge/Kegan Paul; 1985 Google Scholar.

16. Rachels, J. The Elements of Moral Philosophy. New York, NY: Random House; 1986 Google Scholar.

17. Häyry, M. Critical Studies in Philosophical Medical Ethics. Helsinki: Department of Philosophy, University of Helsinki; 1990 Google Scholar.

18. Häyry, M. Liberal Utilitarianism and Applied Ethics. London/New York, NY: Routledge; 1994 Google Scholar.

19. Häyry, M. Just better utilitarianism. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2021;30:343–67CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed. doi:10.1017/S0963180120000882.

20. Häyry, M. Exit duty generator. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2023;33 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. doi:10.1017/S096318012300004X.

21. Childress, J. Practical Reasoning in Bioethics. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press; 1997 Google Scholar.

22. Habermas, J. The Future of Human Nature. Regh, W, Pensky, M, Beister, H, trans. Cambridge: Polity Press; 2003 Google Scholar.

23. Green, RM. Babies by Design: The Ethics of Genetic Choice. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press; 2007 Google Scholar.

24. Cabrera, J. Discomfort and Moral Impediment: The Human Situation, Radical Bioethics and Procreation. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing; 2019 Google Scholar.

25. Thomasma, DC, Pellegrino, ED. Philosophy of medicine as the source for medical ethics. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 1981;2:511 Google ScholarPubMed.

26. Pellegrino, ED, Thomasma, DC. The Virtues in Medical Practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1993 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27. Engelhardt, HT. The Foundations of Bioethics. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1996 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

28. Oderberg, DS. Applied Ethics: A Non-Consequentialist Approach. Oxford: Blackwell; 2000 Google Scholar.

29. Jackson, J. Ethics in Medicine. Cambridge: Polity Press; 2006 Google Scholar.

30. Rhodes, R. The Trusted Doctor: Medical Ethics and ProfessionalismNew York, NYOxford University Press2020 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

31. Daniels, N. Just Health Care. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press; 1985 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

32. Scruton, R. A Political Philosophy: Arguments for Conservatism. London: Continuum; 2006 Google Scholar.

33. Häyry, M. Roles of Justice in Bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2022 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. doi:10.1017/9781009104364.

34. Sherwin, S. No Longer Patient: Feminist Ethics and Health Care. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press; 1992 Google Scholar.

35. Kittay, EF , Feder, EK, eds. The Subject of Care: Feminist Perspectives on Dependency. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers; 2002 Google Scholar.

36. Luna, F, ed. Bioethics and Vulnerability: A Latin American View. Amsterdam: Brill; 2006 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37. Häyry, M, Takala, T, Herissone-Kelly, P, eds. Ethics in Biomedical Research: International Perspectives. Amsterdam/New York, NY: Rodopi; 2007 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38. Tangwa, GB, ed. African Perspectives on Some Contemporary Bioethics Problems. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing; 2019 Google Scholar.

39. Häyry, M, Häyry, H. The nature and role of professional codes in modern society. In: Chadwick, RF, ed. Ethics and the Professions. Aldershot: Avebury; 1994:136–44Google Scholar.

40. Genes, Takala T., Sense and Sensibility: Philosophical Studies on the Ethics of Modern Biotechnologies. Turku: University of Turku; 2000 Google Scholar.

41. Takala, T. What is wrong with global bioethics? On the limitations of the four principles approach. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2001;19:72–7CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

42. Takala, T. Demagogues, firefighters, and window dressers: Who are we and what should we be? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2005;14:385–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

43. Häyry, M. What exactly did you claim? A call for clarity in the presentation of premises and conclusions in philosophical contributions to ethics. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2015;24:107–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar. doi:10.1017/S0963180114000358.

44. Häyry, M. What do you think of philosophical bioethics? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2015;24:139–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar. doi:10.1017/S0963180114000449.

45. Räsänen, J, Häyry, M. The role of philosophers in bioethics. American Journal of Bioethics 2022;22:5860 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

46. Rydenfelt, H. Pragmatism and experimental bioethics. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2024;33 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; forthcoming. doi:10.1017/S0963180123000282.

47. Rydenfelt, H. Emotional Interpretants and Ethical Inquiry. Sign System Studies 2015;43 CrossRefGoogle Scholar:501–13.

48. Rydenfelt, H. Pragmatism, social inquiry and the method of democracy. In: Holma, K, Kontinen, T, eds. Practices of Citizenship in East Africa. Perspectives from Philosophical Pragmatism. London: Routledge; 2019:2943 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

49. Rydenfelt, H. Democracy and moral inquiry: Problems of the methodological argument. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 2019;55:254–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

50. Rydenfelt, H. Environmental pragmatism and the revision of valuesTransactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 2022;58:5266 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51. See note 18, Häyry 1994, at 152–3.

52. See note 18, Häyry 1994, at 154.

53. See note 18, Häyry 1994, at 155.

54. Häyry, H, Häyry, M. AIDS now. Bioethics 1987;1:339–56CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

55. Häyry, M, Häyry H, AIDS, Society, , and , moralityA philosophical survey. Philosophia 1989;19:331–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

56. Häyry, M, Takala, T. Genetic engineering and the risk of harm. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1998;1:61–4CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

57. Häyry, M, Takala, T. Commercial genetic testing and the right to know. In: Takala, T, ed. Genes, Sense and Sensibility: Philosophical Studies on the Ethics of Modern Biotechnologies. Turku: University of Turku; 2000:87105 Google Scholar.

58. disgust, Häyry M. DeeplyA Devlinian objection to cloning humans. In: Almond, B, Parker, M, eds. Ethical Issues in the New Genetics: Are Genes Us? Aldershot: Ashgate; 2003:5567 Google Scholar.

59. Takala, T, ed. Philosophical issues in neuroethics. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2010;19:161229 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

60. Takala, T, Häyry, M. Neuroethics and animals, methods and philosophy. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2014;23:182–7CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

61. Shevchenko, S, Zhavoronkov, A. The role of exceptionalism in the evolution of bioethics and regulation. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2024;33 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; forthcoming. doi:10.1017/S0963180123000336.

62. Sidgwick H. Methods of Ethics [orig. 1874]. 7th ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Sidgwick, H. Methods of Ethics []. 7th ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company; 1981 Google Scholar.

63. See note 18, Häyry 1994, at 50–3.

64. Häyry, M. There is a difference between selecting a deaf embryo and deafening a hearing child. Journal of Medical Ethics 2004;30:510–12CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed. doi:10.1136/jme.2002.001891.

65. Häyry, M. Rationality and the Genetic Challenge: Making People Better? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2010, at 7898 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66. Firth, SJ. The picture theory of disability. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2024;33 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; forthcoming. doi:10.1017/S0963180123000154.

67. Häyry, M. Measuring the quality of life: Why, how and what? Theoretical Medicine 1991;12:97116 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

68. Häyry M. If you must give them a gift, then give them the gift of nonexistence. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics; forthcoming. doi:10.1017/S0963180122000317.

69. See note 18, Häyry 1994.

70. Häyry, M. Mahdollisimman monen onnellisuus: Utilitarismin historia, teoria ja sovellukset. Helsinki: WSOY; 2001 Google Scholar.

71. Häyry, M. Utilitarian approaches to justice in health care. In: Rhodes, R, Battin, MP, Silvers, A, eds. Medicine and Social Justice: Essays on the Distribution of Health Care. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2002:5364 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

72. Häyry, M. Utilitarianism and bioethics. In: Ashcroft, R, Dawson, A, Draper, H, McMillan, J, eds. Principles of Health Care Ethics. 2nd ed. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons; 2007:5764 Google Scholar.

73. Häyry, M. Doctrines and dimensions of justice: Their historical backgrounds and ideological underpinnings. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2018;27:188216 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

74. Häyry, M. Causation, responsibility, and harm: How the discursive shift from law and ethics to social justice sealed the plight of nonhuman animals. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2020;29:246–67CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed. doi:10.1017/S096318011900104X.

75. See note 19, Häyry 2021.

76. Bentham, J. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation []. Burns, JH, Hart, HLA, eds. London: Methuen; 1982 Google Scholar.

77. See note 20, Häyry 2023.

78. Akerma, K. On Matti Häyry’s exit duty generator. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2024;33 Google Scholar; forthcoming. doi:10.1017/S0963180123000142.

79. Häyry, M, Sukenick, A. Imposing a lifestyle: A new argument for antinatalism. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2024;33 Google ScholarPubMed; forthcoming. doi:10.1017/S0963180123000385.