Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T10:16:26.192Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Freedom as Non-Domination in the Jurisprudence of Constitutional Rights

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 July 2015

Get access

Abstract

In recent decades, neo-republican philosophers have developed a theory of freedom as non-domination, which, they claim, is conceptually and analytically distinct from the “liberal” concept of freedom as non-interference. However, neo-republicans have intervened in constitutional debate almost exclusively in relation to structural issues of institutional competence, and have made little impact on the analytical jurisprudence of constitutional rights. While judicial review seems ill equipped to respond to the distributive dimensions of republican freedom, republicans like Richard Bellamy have argued that the whole edifice of countermajoritarian, strong-form judicial review is itself an affront to freedom as non-domination properly understood. Republican freedom, in this lens, is defined structurally, procedurally and politically rather than in relation to a definite set, concept or theory of rights that is put outside and beyond politics. And partly for this reason, there has been little commentary concerning how the theory of freedom as non-domination might inform constitutional-rights doctrine. This article will argue, first, that the neo-republican view can usefully inform constitutional-rights doctrine notwithstanding republican reservations concerning judicial power. Second, it will propose a number of specific ways in which the jurisprudence of constitutional rights might account for the central concerns of the republican idea.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Pettit, Philip, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997) ch 1 and 2.Google Scholar

2. See, generally, Skinner, Quentin, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).Google Scholar

3. Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan: On the Matter, Forme, and Power of a Common-Wealth Ecclesiasticall and Civill, ed by Shapiro, Ian (Yale: Yale University Press, 2010) at ch XXI.Google Scholar

4. Pettit, supra note 1 at 18.

5. See, generally, Pettit, supra note 1.

6. See, e.g., Kramer, Matthew, “Liberty and Domination” in Laborde, Cecile & Maynor, John, Republicanism and Political Theory (London: Blackwell, 2008) at 3751.Google Scholar

7. Pettit, Philip, “Law and Liberty” in Besson, Samantha & Martí, José Luis, Legal Republicanism: National and International Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).Google Scholar

8. Ibid.

9. Ibid.

10. Supra note 1 at 134.

11. Pettit, Philip, On the People’s Terms: a Republican Theory and Model of Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013) at 3.Google Scholar

12. Ibid at ch 1 and 2.

13. Ibid at ch 4 and 5.

14. Neuhouser, Frederick, “Freedom, Dependence and the General Will” (1993) 102 Philosophical Rev 390.Google Scholar

15. Pettit, supra note 11 at ch 2.

16. Supra note 1 at 113-14.

17. On social justice and non-domination, see Pettit, supra note 11 at ch 2.

18. Pettit, supra note 11 at 15-18.

19. See, generally, Pettit, supra note 1 at ch 6.

20. See, generally, Fuller, Lon, “The Forms and Limits of Adjudication” (1978) 92 Harv L Rev 353.Google Scholar

21. Pettit, supra note 11 at ch 2.

22. However, for a countervailing view, see Fabre, Cecile, “Constitutionalising Social Rights” (1998) 3 Journal of Political Phil 363.Google Scholar

23. Bellamy, Richard, ‘Constitutive Citizenship versus Constitutional Rights: Republican Reflections on the EU Charter and the Human Rights Act’ in Campbell, Tom, Ewing, Keith & Tomkins, Adam, eds, Sceptical Essays on Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) at 15.Google Scholar

24. See generally Fuller, supra note 20.

25. On the constitutionalisation of social rights generally, see Fabre, supra note 22.

26. See, e.g., Thompson, Michael, “The Two Faces of Domination in Republican Political Theory” (2015) European Journal of Political Theory, Published online before print April 15, 2015, doi: 10.1177/1474885115580352, last accessed April 16, 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

27. See, generally, Pettit, supra note 1 at ch 6. See also, e.g., Honohan, Iseult, “Republicans, Rights and Constitutions: Is Judicial Review Compatible with Republican Self-Government” in Besson, Samantha & Marti, José-Luis, eds, Legal Republicanism: National and International Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).Google Scholar

28. Sellers, Mortimer, The Sacred Fire of Liberty: Republicanism, Liberalism and the Law (New York: Macmillan and NYU Press, 1998).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29. Ivison, Duncan, “Republican Human Rights?” (2010) 9 European Journal of Political Theory 34.Google Scholar

30. Ibid.

31. See Lindseth, Peter, “Law, History, and Memory: Republican Moments and the Legitimacy of Constitutional Review in France” (1996) 3 Colum J Eur L 49.Google Scholar

32. Michelman, Frank, “Conceptions of Democracy in American Constitutional Argument: Voting Rights” (1989) 41 Fla L Rev 443 at 446.Google Scholar

33. Bellamy, Richard, Political Constitutionalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

34. Tomkins, Adam, Our Republican Constitution (Oxford: Hart, 2005).Google Scholar

35. See Gee, Graham & Webber, Grégoire, “What is a Political Constitution?” (2010) 30 Oxford J Legal Stud 273.Google Scholar

36. Griffith, John, “The Political Constitution” (1979) 42 Mod L Rev 1. Alternatively, strong-form judicial review has equally been challenged from within rights-centred liberalism.)Google Scholar See, e.g., Allan, James, ‘Bills of Rights and Judicial Power: a Liberal’s Quandary’ (1996) 16 Oxford J Legal Stud 337.Google Scholar

37. Goldoni, Marco, “Constitutional Reasoning According to Political Constitutionalism” (2012) 11 German LJ 1 at 4.Google Scholar

38. Bellamy, supra note 33 at 152. See also Waldron, Jeremy, “A Right-Based Critique of Constitutional Rights” (1993) 13 Oxford J Legal Stud 18.Google Scholar

39. Pettit, Philip, “The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon” (2006) 34 Phil & Public Affairs 275.Google Scholar

40. Ibid.

41. Pettit, supra note 1 at 57.

42. See Bellamy, “Political Constitutionalism and the Human Rights Act” (2011) 9 Int’l J Constitutional L 86.

43. Pettit, supra note 11 at ch 4 and 5.

44. See Tomkins, supra note 34 at ch 4.

45. See Guttman, Julia, “Primary Elections and the Collective Right of Freedom of Association”, (1984) 94 Yale LJ 117Google Scholar; Issacharoff, Samuel, “Private Parties with Public Purposes: Political Parties, Associational Freedoms, and Partisan Competition” (2001) 101 Colum L Rev 274.Google Scholar

46. Issacharoff, ibid.

47. Ibid.

48. See, generally, Van Dijk, Pieter, Van Hoof, Fried & Van Rijn, Arjen, eds, Theory and Practice of the European Convention on Human Rights (The Hague: Kluwer, 1998).Google Scholar

49. Here I distinguish “interference” in the ECtHR’s terminology—a prima facie infringement of a right at the first stage of analysis—from the more technical sense of the term used in analytical legal/political philosophy.

50. Pettit, supra note 1 at ch 7; supra note 11 at ch 4 and 5.

51. 494 US 872 (1990).

52. Ibid.

53. On this issue, see Eisgruber, Christopher & Sager, Lawrence, Religious Freedom and the Constitution (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

54. See, generally, Laycock, Douglas, “Formal, Substantive, and Disaggregated Neutrality towards Religion” (1990) 39 DePaul L Rev 993.Google Scholar

55. Pettit, supra note 11 at 83.

56. Pettit insists that a broad range of activities and choices, but not “any old choices”, must be protected by the basic liberties; they “need resources and protection in a range of choice where all can operate at once without getting in another’s way…. [this is] the domain of the fundamental liberties.” Ibid.

57. Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, 1982, Article 1.

58. The first amendment provides: “Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble, and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances.”

59. Heaney v Ireland [1994] 3 IR 593; Cox v Ireland 14 [1992] 2 IR 503.

60. For discussion see, generally, Hickman, Tom, ‘The Substance and Structure of Proportionality’ (2008) PL 694.Google Scholar

61. Heaney v Ireland [1994] 3 IR 593 at 607.

62. Pettit, supra note 11 at ch 4 and 5.

63. Adler, Matthew, “Rights against Rules: The Moral Structure of American Constitutional Law” (1998) 97 Mich L Rev 1.Google Scholar

64. Employment Division v Smith 494 US 872 (1990).

65. Kagan, Elena, “Private Speech, Public Purpose: The Role of Governmental Motive in First Amendment Doctrine” (1996) 63 U Chicago L Rev 413.Google Scholar Pildes cites Board of Education v Pico 457 US 853 (1982) to support this view. Pildes, Richard, “Why Rights Are Not Trumps: Social Meanings, Expressive Harms, and Constitutionalism” (1998) 27 J Legal Stud 725.Google Scholar

66. Eisgruber, Christopher & Sager, Lawrence, “Religious Liberty and the Moral Structure of Constitutional Rights” (2000) 6 Legal Theory 253.Google Scholar

67. Pildes, supra note 65 at 731.

68. Ibid at 733.

69. Ibid.

70. Ibid at 729 [emphasis added].

71. Pettit, supra note 11 at 88, 84.

72. See, e.g., Halldenius, Lena, “Non-Domination and Egalitarian Welfare Politics” (1998) 1 Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 335Google Scholar; White, Stuart, “The Republican Critique of Capitalism” (2011) 14 Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 561.Google Scholar

73. Fabre, supra note 22.

74. On the South African experience, see Kende, Mark, ‘The South African Constitutional Court’s. Embrace of Socio-Economic Rights: A Comparative Perspective’ (2003) 6 Chapman L Rev 137.Google Scholar

75. Chirwa, Danwood, “The Horizontal Application of Constitutional Rights in a Comparative Perspective” (2006) 10 Law, Democracy and Development 21.Google Scholar On the Irish example specifically see, e.g., Meskell v CIE [1973] 1 IR 121; Educational Co of Ireland v Fitzpatrick (no. 2) [1961] IR 345; SPUC v Grogan [1989] IR 761. Banda, Sibo, “Taking Indirect Horizontality Seriously in Ireland: A Time to Magnify the Nuance” (2009) 31 Dublin University L J 263Google Scholar; O’Cinnéide, Colm, “Irish Constitutional Law and Direct Horizontal Effect” in Oliver, D & Fedkte, J, Human Rights and the Private Sphere (London: Taylor & Francis, 2007).Google Scholar

76. Pettit, supra note 11 at 91.

77. Norris v Attorney General [1984] IR 36.

78. [1984] IR 36 at 69 [emphasis added].

79. East Donegal Co-Operative Ltd v Att Gen [1970] IR 317 at 338 [emphasis added].

80. See Northeastern Fla. Chapter of the Associated Gen. Contractors of Am. v City of Jacksonville, 508 US 656, 662-63 (1993); (quoting Lujan v Defenders of Wildlife, 504 US 555, 560 (1992); Simon v Eastern Ky Welfare Rights Org, 426 US 26, 41-42 (1976); Allen v Wright, 468 US 737, 752 (1984), all cited in Adler, supra note 63. See also Sunstein, Cass, ‘What’s Standing after Lujan? Of Citizen Suits, ‘‘Injuries,’’ and Article III’ (1992) 91 Mich L Rev 163.Google Scholar

81. Pildes, supra note 65 at 733.

82. See, e.g., the Irish case Crotty v An Taoiseach [1987] IR 713.

83. Hoffman Estates v The Flipside, Hoffman Estates, 455 US 489 (1982).

84. Pildes, supra note 65.

85. Ibid at 730.

86. See Geuss, Raymond, Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

87. See Lee v Weisman, 505 US 577, 689 (1992).

88. See Irish cases King v Attorney General [1981] IR 233; Douglas v Director of Public Prosecutions [2013] IEHC 3.

89. Pettit, supra note 1 at 55; see also Lovett, Frank, “What Counts as Arbitrary Power” (2012) 5 Journal of Political Power 137.Google Scholar

90. O’Neill, Timothy, “Liberal Constitutionalism & Bureaucratic Discretion” (1988) 20 Polity 371.Google Scholar

91. Dicey, Albert, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (London: Macmillan, 1897) Part 2 at ch 4.Google Scholar

92. Ibid. See also McAuslan, Patrick, “Administrative law, collective consumption and judicial policy” (1983) 46 Mod L Rev 1Google Scholar; Pestritto, Ronald, “The Progressive Origins of the Administrative State” (2007) 24 Social Phil & Policy 16.Google Scholar

93. As a consequentialist, Pettit assumes non-domination is a value to be maximized. Philip Pettit, “The Consequentialist can Recognise Rights” (1998) 35 Phil Quarterly 537.

94. Pettit, supra note 1 at 54, 64, [emphasis added]. He continues at page 54: “what is required for non-arbitrary state power … is that the power be exercised in a way that tracks, not the power-holder’s worldview, but rather the welfare and world-view of the public … the acts of interference perpetrated by the state must be triggered by the shared interests of those affected under an interpretation of what those interests require that is shared, at least at the procedural level, by those affected.”

95. Ibid at 56.

96. Ibid at 56.

97. Ibid at 55.

98. Ibid at 55.

99. See the limiting provisos in Articles 8-11 of the European Convention on Human Rights. See also DPP v Fagan [1994] 2 IR 265; Howard v Commissioners of Public Works [1994] 1 IR 101. Articulating a more general principle of legality, Justice Kearns stated: “every executive or administrative act which affects legal rights, interests or legitimate expectations must be legally justified.” Browne v Attorney General [2002] IEHC 47.

100. Heaney v Ireland [1994] 3 IR 593.

101. Malone v United Kingdom (App. 8691/79), 2 August 1984, (1985) EHRR 14.

102. Pettit, supra note 1 at 54.

103. In the UK, see Paul Craig, Administrative Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012) at ch 12, 14, 15. In Ireland, see David Gwynn Morgan, Hogan and Morgan’s Administrative Law (Dublin: Round Hall, 2010) at ch 12-15. In some jurisdictions, the procedural rights associated with natural justice have been elevated to constitutional status, meaning they cannot be overridden by parliamentary legislation. In Ireland, see McDonald v Bord na gCon [1965] IR 217.

104. Pettit, supra note 1 at 58.

105. On the distinction between procedural and substantive understandings of arbitrariness, see Lovett, supra note 89.

106. Pettit, supra note 1 at 63.

107. The “constitutional” status of the right to judicial review varies across different common-law jurisdictions. While its “constitutional” status is obviously most ephemeral in the United Kingdom, the right to judicial review of administrative action is implicit in Article 34 of the Irish Constitution of 1937, while Article 24 of the Canadian Charter Rights and Freedoms guarantees the right to apply to a court for a remedy for infringement of Charter rights. Article 6 of the ECHR guarantees a “fair and public hearing within a reasonable time by an independent and impartial tribunal established by law”.

108. Pettit, supra note 11 at 87.

109. See, e.g., Daly, Eoin & Hickey, Tom, “Religious Freedom and the ‘Right to Discriminate’ in the School Admissions Context: A Neo-Republican Critique” (2011) 31 LS 615.Google Scholar

110. Article 40.1, Constitution of Ireland, 1937.

111. See, e.g., Murtagh Properties v Cleary [1972] IR 330.

112. See, e.g., the Irish case Schlegel v Corcoran and Gross [1942] IR 19.

113. McGrath and Ó Ruairc v Trustees of Maynooth College [1979] ILRM 166.

114. Re Article 26 and the Employment Equality Bill 1996 [1997] 3 IR 321, 360.

115. In Ireland, the Equal Status Act 2000 while prohibiting discrimination on religious grounds in the provision of goods and services, exempts “educational establishments”, “whether or not supported by public funds”, where “the objective of the school is to provide education in an environment which promotes certain religious values”. See sections 7 (1) and 7 (2). See similarly section 37 of the Employment Equality Act 1998. See Daly & Hickey, supra note 109.

116. Hurley v Irish American Gay, Lesbian, and Bisexual Group of Boston, 515 US 557 (1995); Boy Scouts of America v Dale, 530 US 640 (2000). However, see also Bob Jones University v United States, 461 US 574 (1983). In relation to religious freedom as distinct from freedom of association, see Bruce Bagni, “Discrimination in the Name of the Lord: A Critical Evaluation of Discrimination by Religious Organisations” (1979) 79 Colum L Rev 1514.

117. Hosanna-Tabor Evangelical Lutheran Church and School v EEOC, 565 US (2012).

118. See Daly & Hickey, supra note 109.

119. Ibid.