Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-wzw2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-20T18:02:41.862Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Patent Law and the Assurance Game: Refitting Intellectual Property in the Box of Regulation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 July 2015

Get access

Extract

Patent law is often understood through the fiction of social contract. The author argues that this fiction does not offer an adequate economic or political theory of patent law, that is, one that will explain the unique relationship between government and property that patents entail. As an alternative to social contract theory, a regulatory theory of patent law is developed based on the assurance game taken from game theory. The assurance game is used to show how patent law serves to regulate the invention process and the market for innovative products.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

A longer version of this article was published as “Patents and the Regulatory State: Rethinking the Patent Bargain Metaphor After Eldred,” 19 Berkeley Technology Law Journal (2004), with permission.

1. 537 U.S. 186 at 197-199 (2003).

2. Ibid. at 215.

3. Ibid. at 216.

4. Rubin, Ed, After Camelot, Chapter Five, From Legitimacy to Compliance (2003) [unpublished, on file with the author of this article] at 9.Google Scholar

5. Ibid. at 10.

6. See Boucher, David & Kelly, Paul, “The Social Contract and Its Critics: An Overview” in Boucher, David & Kelly, Paul, eds., The Social Contract from Hobbes to Rawls (London, New York: Routledge, 1994) 1 CrossRefGoogle Scholar at 13-16; Dienstag, Joshua Foa, “Between History and Nature: Social Contract Theory in Locke and the Founders” (1996) 58:4 Politics, J. 985 at 99295 Google Scholar.

7. See Paul Kelly, “Justifying ‘Justice’: Contractarianism, Communitarianism, and the Foundations of Contemporary Liberalism” in Boucher & Kelly, supra note 6, 229 at 241-43.

8. See Binmore, Ken, “Bargaining and Morality” in Gauthier, David & Sugden, Robert, eds., Rationality, Justice and the Social Contract: Themes from Morals by Agreement (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1993) 131 at 36140.Google Scholar

9. See Dienstag, supra note 6 at 993-94.

10. See Kelly, supra note 7 at 230-31; Murray Forsyth, “Hobbes’ Contractarianism: A Comparative Analysis” in The Social Contract, supra note 6 at 35, 39-43 (comparing Hobbes, Locke, and communitarian theorists).

11. See Dienstag, supra note 6 at 997-99.

12. See Rubin, supra note 4 at 13-15.

13. Ibid. at 14.

14. Ibid. at 15.

15. See, e.g., J. Gordon, Wendy, “A Property Right in Self-ex Pression: Equality and Individualism in the Natural Law of Intellectual Property” (1993) 102 Yale L. J. 1533 at 1541-45Google Scholar; Hughes, Justin, “The Philosophy of Intellectual Property” (1988) 77 Geo. L. J. 287 at 300-15.Google Scholar

16. See Hughes, ibid. at 302-03.

17. See, e.g., Chander, Anupam, “The New, New Property” (2003) 81 Tex. L. Rev. 715 at 745.Google Scholar

18. Locke, John, Treatise of Civil Government and a Letter Concerning Toleration(1689), ed. by L. Sherman, Charles (1937) at 22.Google Scholar

19. See Hughes, supra note 15 at 309-11.

20. See Mossoff, Adam, “Rethinking the Development of Patents: an Intellectual History, 1550-1800” (2001) 52 Hastings L. J. 1255 at 1259.Google Scholar

21. For a discussion of these and other limits, see S. Lunney Jr., Glynn, “Patent Law, the Federal Circuit, and the Supreme Court: A Quiet Revolution” (2004) 11 Sup. Ct. Econ. Rev. 1 at 9-11 (describing shifts in doctrines limiting patents).Google Scholar

22. See Hughes, supra note 15 at 330-39.

23. See Boucher & Kelly, supra note 6 at 23-26.

24. Ibid. at 24-25.

25. See Bell, Daniel, ‘“American Exceptionalism” Revisited: The Role of Civil Society’ in Eberly, Don E., ed., The Essential Civil Society Reader: The Classic Essays (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2000) 373 at 381-82.Google Scholar

26. See Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Philosophy of Right, trans. by Knox, T. M. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952) at 3741 Google Scholar. For a scholarly discussion applying Hegel to property theory, see Margaret Radin, Jane, “Property and Personhood” (1982) 34 Stan. L. Rev. 957 at 976-78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

27. See Sterk, Stewart E., “Rhetoric and Reality in Copyright Law” (1996) 94 Mich. L. Rev. 1197 at 1243-45.Google Scholar

28. See, e.g., Holman, Molly A. & Munzer, Stephen R., “Intellectual Property Rights in Genes and Gene Fragments: A Registration Solution for Ex Pressed Sequence Tags” (2000) 85 Iowa L. Rev. 735 at 836, n. 273 (pointing out the Hegel discussed copyrights but not patents).Google Scholar

29. While intellectual property and other scholars have written about Hobbes and possessive individualism, there seems to be very little connecting Hobbes’s philosophy with either copyright or patent. See Nimmer, David, “Copyright in the Dead Sea Scrolls: Authorship and Originality” (2001) 38 Hous. L. Rev. 1 at 9 (commenting on absence of any discussion of copyright in Hobbes’ work except for reference to “writers”).Google Scholar

30. See Forsyth, supra note 10 at 43-48.

31. See Rubin, supra note 4 at 12.

32. Ibid.

33. Hirschman, Albert O., The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism Before Its Triumph (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1977) at 53.Google Scholar

34. Ibid. at 53-54.

35. See, e.g., Gauthier, David, “The Social Contract as Ideology” (1977) 6:2 Phil. & Pub. Affairs 130 at 134-35 (discussing Locke’s supposition that social contract is among landed proprietors seeking to protect their property).Google Scholar

36. See Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971).Google Scholar

37. See Harsanyi, J.C., “Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility” (1955) 63 J. Pol. Econ. 309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

38. See Binmore, “Bargaining and Morality” supra note 8 at 132.

39. See Rawls, supra note 36 at 20, n.9 (describing Harsanyi as a utilitarian); Binmore, Ken, “Social Contract I: Harsanyi and Rawls” (1989) 99 The Economic J. 84 at 86 (stating that Harsanyi is not a contractarian but a utilitarian).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

40. See Binmore, “Social Contract I” supra note 39 at 84-85 (discussing the economic literature on social contract theory).

41. For definitions of the veil of ignorance and the difference principle, see Rawls, supra note 36 at 118-23, 65-73. For one indication of the influence of Rawls on legal theory and reform, see Dean William Treanor, Michael, “Introduction: Rawls and the Law” (2004) 72 Fordham L. Rev. 1385. A few random citations illustrate the appeal of the veil of ignorance to diverse fields of lawGoogle Scholar. See, e.g., Vermeule, Adrian, “Veil of Ignorance Rules in Constitutional Law” (2001) 111 Yale L. J. 399 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Korobkin, Russell, “Determining Health Care Rights from Behind a Veil of Ignorance1998 U. Ill. L. Rev. 801 Google ScholarPubMed; Linder, Marc, “Tax Glasnost’ for Millionaires: Peeking Behind the Veil of Ignorance Along the Publicity-privacy Continuum” (1998) 18 N.Y.U. Rev. of L. & Soc. Change 951.Google Scholar

42. See Binmore, “Social Contract I” supra note 39 at 86-88.

43. Ibid. at 90-92 (describing Harsanyi’s ideas in relationship to game theory).

44. See Campbell, Donald E., Resourc e Allocation Mechanisms (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987) at 1-2 (defining economics as a tool to analyze alternative resource allocation mechanisms).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

45. See Rawls, supra note 36 at 239-42; Campbell, ibid. at 14-15.

46. See Rawls, supra note 36 at 49-50 (discussing constitutive rules as shaping institutions).

47. Ibid. at 132-33 (defining maxi-min principle).

48. See Rex Martin, “Economic Justice: Contractarianism and Rawls’s Difference Principle” in Boucher & Kelly, supra note 6 at 248-52 (analyzing implications of difference principle for egalitarian distribution).

49. See Binmore, “Social Contract I” supra note 39 at 84 (contrasting Harsanyi and Rawls).

50. See Harsanyi, supra note 37 at 311.

51. See ibid. at 315.

52. See Binmore, “Social Contract I” supra note 39 at 100 (characterizing Harsanyi as a utilitarian whose ideas can be justified in contractarian terms).

53. See ibid. at 86-87 (outlining the contractarian elements of Harsanyi’s ideas).

54. See ibid. at 94-95.

55. See Boucher & Kelly, supra note 6 at 22-23.

56. Lincoln, Abraham, “Discoveries and Inventions, Jacksonville, Illinois, February 11, 1859” in Fehrenbacher, Don E., ed., Lincoln: Selected Speeches and Writing (New York: Vintage/Library of America, 1992) 200 at 208.Google Scholar

57. See Scherer, F. M., “The Innovation Lottery” in Rochelle Cooper Dreyfuss, et al., eds., Expanding the Boundaries of Intellectual Property: Innovation Policy for the Knowledge Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) 3 at 18-19.Google Scholar

58. See, e.g., Merton, Robert K., On Social Structure and Science, ed. by Sztompka, Piotr, (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996) 26776 Google Scholar (describing the ethos of science as consisting of uni-versalism, communism, disinterestedness, and organized skepticism).

59. See, e.g., Eisenberg, Rebecca S., “Proprietary Rights and the Norms of Science in Biotechnology Research” (1987) 97 Yale L. J. 177 at 182-95 (contrasting the traditional view of the ethos and science with the normative framework of patent law).CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

60. For a discussion of the role of collaboration and cumulative invention in academy, see McSherry, Corynne, Who Owns Academic Work?: Battling for Control of Intellectual Property (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001) at 4650 Google Scholar (describing patents and academic incentives); Krimsky, Sheldon, Science in the Private Interest: Has the Lure of Profits Corrupted Biomedical Research? (Lanham, MD: Rowan & Littlefield, 2003) at 2756 (describing the development of university-industry collaboration).Google Scholar

61. See, e.g., Heller, Michael A. & Eisenberg, Rebecca S., “Can Patents Deter Innovation? The Anticommons in Biomedical ResearchScience 280:5364 (1 May 1998) 698 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Oddi, A. Samuel, “The Tragicomedy of the Public Domain in Intellectual Property Law” (2002) 25 Hastings Comm. & Ent. L.J 1 at 10.Google Scholar

62. For the key works of scholarship on the assurance game (also called the stag hunt game), see Sen, Amartya K., “Isolation, Assurance, and the Social Rate of Discount” (1967) 81 Quart. J. Econ. 11224 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (presenting the assurance game as an alternative to prisoner’s dilemma); Bergstrom, Theodore C., “Evolution of Social Behavior: Individual and Group Selection” (2002) 16 J. Econ. Persp. 6788 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (exploring different implications for individual and group behavior of prisoner’s dilemma and assurance game); Skyrms, Brian, The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 2004) at 413 Google Scholar (discussing implications of stag hunt game for social contract theory); Skyrms, Brian, Evolution of the Social Contract (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, 1996) 6379 CrossRefGoogle Scholar (discussing evolution of correlated conventions such as legal institutions). John Rawls acknowledged the assurance problem (although he does not analyze the problem as a formal game) and used the problem to explain why individuals in society would agree to accept fairness as a decision-making criterion. See Rawls, supra note 36 at 237-38, 305-06.

63. See Kaufer, Erich, The Economics of the Patent System (Chur: Hardwood Academic, 1989) at 2441 Google Scholar (presenting a pure economic theory of patent law).

64. See Arrow, K.J., “Economic Welfare and the Allocation of Resources for Invention” in Nelson, R.R., ed., The Rate and Direction of Economic Activity (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1962) at 609.Google Scholar

65. Ibid. at 610; Kaufer, supra note 63 at 31.

66. For a discussion of the Lockean view of intellectual property developed in a game theoretic context, see Wendy J. Gordon, “Intellectual Property” in Peter Cane & Tushnet, Mark, eds., Oxford Handbook of Legal Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003) 617.Google Scholar

67. Cf. ibid. at 640-41 (applying prisoner’s dilemma to copyright).

68. See ibid. at 622-23 (describing free riding and externality problems in intellectual property).

69. See, e.g., Landes, William M. & Posner, Richard A., The Economic Structure of Intellectual Property Law(Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2003) at 1415 Google Scholar (analyzing the economics of the commons).

70. See Fennell, Lee Anne, “Common Interest Tragedies (2004) 98 Nw. U. L. Rev. 907 at 942-46Google Scholar (describing anti-commons problem as prisoner’s dilemma); Depoorter, Ben & Parisi, Francesco, “Fair Use and Copyright Protection: A Price Theory Explanation” (2002) 21 Int’l Rev. L. & Econ. 453 at 460CrossRefGoogle Scholar (presenting formal model of anti-commons problem as prisoner’s dilemma).

71. See Skyrms, Stag Hunt, supra note 62 at 2-3 (discussing dominant strategy in prisoner’s dilemma).

72. See McSherry, supra note 60; Kornberg, Arthur, The Golden Helix: Inside Biotech Ventures (Sausalito, CA: University Science Books, 1995) at 1318 Google Scholar (describing conflict between academic and industry research norms); Lynne G. Zucker et. al., “Collaboration Structure and Information Dilemmas in Biotechnology: Organizational Boundaries as Trust Production” in Kramer, Roderick M. & Ty ler, Tom R., eds., Trust in Organizations: Frontiers of Theory and Research (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 1996) 90 Google Scholar at 96-99.

73. Merton, supra note 58 at 332.

74. Ibid. at 272.

75. See Ungwin, Julia, “Business Method Patents Create Growing ControversyThe Wall Street Journal (3 October 2000) C1.Google Scholar

76. Chandler, Alfred D., Jr., Scale and Scope: The Dynamics of Industrial Capitalism (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 1990) at 228.Google Scholar

77. See Heller, Michael A., “The Boundaries of Private Property” (1999) 108 Yale L. J. 1163 at 1188-91 (discussing problems of boundaries, scale, and scope in the metaphors of property).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

78. See Axelrod, Robert, The Evolution of Cooperation (New York: Basic Books, 1984) at 53 Google ScholarPubMed; Skyrms, Stag Hunt, supra note 62 at 5; Bergstrom, supra note 62 at 69.

79. See Bergstrom, supra note 62 at 70.

80. See ibid. at 71.

81. See ibid.

82. See Gordon, supra note 66 at 642.

83. See Eldre d v. Ashcroft, supra note 1 at 192 (stating that perpetual copyright term, and by inference patent term, would violate the limited times provision of Article I, Section 8, Clause 8 of the Constitution).

84. See Skyrms, Stag Hunt, supra note 62 at 8.

85. See ibid.

86. See Ayres, Ian & Klemperer, Peter, “Limiting Patentees’ Market Power Without Reducing Innovation Incentives: the Perverse Benefits of Uncertainty and Non-injunctive Remedies” (1999) 97 Mich. L. Rev. 985 at 1007-12 (arguing that uncertainty in patent enforcement has important implications for duration and limiting the patentee’s power).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

87. See ibid. at 989-93.

88. See ibid. at 1027-28.

89. The mathematical derivation works as follows. Under a probabilistic version of the game, there is a fifty per cent chance that the game will be played again and fifty per cent that it will not at each time period. This means that each payoff of the game has to be discounted by the probability that the game will actually be played during a particular time period. Suppose the two players start out reciprocating. Then there will be no need to retaliate and the players will reciprocate forever. The resulting payoff is 5 units discounted by the probability that the game will be played during a given period. The total payoff will be the sum of all of these discounted payoffs, an infinite series. The sum turns out to be 10, as presented in the table. Now suppose that one (or both) of the players fail to reciprocate. Then there will be retaliation forever under the terms of the game so that each play receives 3 discounted by the probability that the game will be plated during a given period, another infinite series. The sums of those infinite series are presented in the table.

90. See Skyrms, Stag Hunt, supra note 62 at 10-13; Skyrms, Social Contract, supra note 62 at 76-79 (discussing evolution of institution of property out of reciprocity described as correlated convention).

91. See Epstein, Richard A., “The Constitutional Protection of Trade Secrets under the Takings Clause” (2004) 71 U. Chi. L. Rev. 57 at 59Google Scholar; Landes & Posner, supra note 69 at 357-71.

92. See Landes & Posner, supra note 69 at 30.

93. See Fennell, supra note 70 at 909; Kahan, Dan M., “The Logic of Reciprocity: Trust, Collective Action, and Law” (2003) 102 Mich. L. Rev. 71 at 78-79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

94. See Kewanee Oil Co. v. Bicron Corp., 416 U.S. 470 at 475-80 (1974) [Kewanee].

95. Ibid. at 473.

96. Ibid. at 482.

97. Ibid. at 495.

98. Ibid. at 474.

99. See, e.g., Merges, Robert P., “Rent Control in the Patent District: Observations on the Grady-Alexander Thesis” (1992) 78 Va. L. Rev. 359 at 376-77 (discussing various forms of secrecy).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

100. Kewanee, supra note 94 485.

101. See, e.g., Macey, Jonathan R., “The Fraud on the Market Theory: Some Preliminary Issues” (1989) 74 Cornell L. Rev. 923 at 926-27Google Scholar (discussing market integrity); Fukuyama, Francis, Trust: The Social Virtues and the Creation of Prosperity (New York: Free Press, 1995) at 2332.Google Scholar

102. See, e.g., Macey, supra note 101. For a discussion of market integrity in the securities case law, see Basic v. Levinson, 485 U.S. 224 at 246 (1988).

103. On disclosure norms, see Talley, Eric L., “Disclosure Norms” (2001) 149 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1955 at 1961CrossRefGoogle Scholar; McAdams, Richard, “Group Norms, Gossip, and Blackmail” (1996) 144 U. Pa. L. Rev. 2237 at 2284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

104. See Skyrms, Stag Hunt, supra note 62 at 87-104; Skyrms, Social Contract, supra note 62 at 76-79 (discussing evolution of property).

105. See ibid. at 105-09; Bergstrom, supra note 62 at 83-84.

106. See, e.g., Robert P. Merges, “Institutions for Intellectual Property Transactions: The Case of Patent Pools” in Expanding the Boundaries, supra note 57, 123 at 133-35.

107. See Jerome H. Reichman, “Of Green Tulips and Legal Kudzu: Repackaging Rights in Subpatentable Inventions” in Expanding the Boundaries, supra note 57 at 25-29; Petra Moser, “How Do Patent Laws Influence Innovation?: Evidence from Nineteenth-Century World Fairs,” Working Paper 9909, National Bureau of Economic Research (August 2003).

108. See Ghosh, Shubha, “Deprivatizing Copyright” (2003) 54 Case Western L. Rev. 387 at 394-400Google Scholar; Litman, Jessica, Digital Copyright: Protecting Intellectual Property on the Internet (Amherst, MA: Prometheus Books, 2001).Google Scholar

109. See Kaufer, supra note 63 at 1-10; Boyle, James, “The Second Enclosure Movement and the Construction of the Public Domain” (2003) 66 L. & Contemp. Probs. 33 at 56-57.Google Scholar

110. To Promote Innovation: The Proper Balance of Competition and Patent Law and Policy: AReport by the Federal Trade Commission (2003), online: Federal Trade Commission http://ftc.gov/os/2003/10/innovationrpt.pdf.

111. See, e.g., Gathii, James Thuo, “The Legal Status of the Doha Declaration on TRIPS and Public Health Under the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties” (2002) 15 Harv. J. L. & Tech. 291 at 293-96.Google Scholar

112. See, e.g., Gathii, James Thuo, “Construing Intellectual Property Rights and Competition Policy Consistently with Facilitating Access to Affordable Aids Drugs to Low-end Consumers” (2001) 53 Fla. L. Rev. 727 at 770-74 (discussing relationship between patent law and FDA regulatory review).Google Scholar

113. See Rubin, supra note 4 at 14-15 (criticizing social contract theory as unhelpful in understanding the modern administrative state).

114. See discussion in Lessig, Lawrence, Free Culture: How Big Media Uses Technology and the Law to Lock Down Culture and Control Creativity (New York: Penguin Press, 2004) at 21348 (analyzing litigation strategy in Eldred and discussing failure to argue case in terms of actual harms created by the legislation).Google Scholar

115. See Macneil, Ian R., The New Social Contract: An Inquiry into Modern Contractual Relations (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1980) at 4748 Google Scholar. For a thorough criticism of the relational contracting perspective, see Barnett, Randy E., “Conflicting Visions: a Critique of Ian Macneil’s Relational Theory of Contract” (1992) 78 Va. L. Rev. 1175 at 1178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

116. See, e.g., Merges, Robert P., “Intellectual Property Rights and the New Institutional Economics” (2000) 53 Vand. L. Rev. 1857 at 1868-70 (analyzing the political economy of intellectual property rights in historical and evolutionary terms).Google Scholar

117. For a discussion of the administrative complexities of patent law, particularly with respect to the applicability of the Administrative Procedure Act to the United States Patent and Trademark Office, see Nard, Craig Allen, “Deference, Defiance, and the Useful Arts” (1995) 56 Ohio State L. J. 1415 at 1419-25Google Scholar. Professor Orin Kerr is critical of Professor Nard’s administrative view of patent law. See Kerr, Orin S., “Rethinking Patent Law in the Administrative State” (2000) 42 Wm & Mary L. Rev. 127 at 134 (presenting a purely private law model of patent law that ex Pressly describes patents as a contract).Google Scholar

118. See Rubin, supra note 4 and accompanying discussion in text.

119. See ibid.

120. For a survey of the literature and caselaw, see Tom, Willard K. & Newberg, Joshua A., “U.S. Enforcement Approaches to the Antitrust-Intellectual Property Interface” in Anderson, Robert D. & Gallini, Nancy T., eds., Competition Policy and Intellectual Property Rights in the Knowledge-Based Economy(Calgary, Alberta: University of Calgary Press, 1998) 343 Google Scholar; Carrier, Michael A., “Unraveling the Patent-Antitrust Paradox” (2002) 150 U. Pa. L. Rev. 761 at 807-15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

121. See Carrier, ibid. at 848-52; “Executive Summary” in To Promote Innovation, supra note 110 at 3-10.

122. See Gathii, supra note 112; Ghosh, Shubha, “Pills, Patents, and Power: State Creation of Gray Markets as a Limit on Patent Rights” (2001) 53 Fla. L. Rev. 789 at 799-802.Google Scholar

123. See Gathii, supra note 112.

124. See Merges, supra note 116.

125. See Rai, Arti K., “Engaging Facts and Policy: A Multi-Institutional Approach to Patent System Reform” (2003) 103 Colum. L. Rev. 1035 at 1122-27CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lemley, Mark A., “Rational Ignorance at the Patent Office” (2001) 95 Nw. U. L. Rev. 1495.Google Scholar

126. See Rai, supra note 125 at 1040-41; Ghosh, Shubha & Kesan, Jay, “What Do Patents Purchase? In Search of Optimal Ignorance in the Patent Office” (2004) 40 Hous. L. Rev. 1219 at 1250-51.Google Scholar

127. See, for an analogous discussion, Kieff, F. Scott, “The Case for Registering Patents and the Law and Economics of Patent-Obtaining Rules” (2003) 45 Boston C. L. Rev. 55.Google Scholar

128. See Ghosh & Kesan, supra note 126 at 1248 for further discussion.

129. For an overview, see Bagley, Margo A., “Patent First, Ask Questions Later: Morality and Biotechnology in Patent Law” (2003) 45 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 469 at 473-77.Google ScholarPubMed

130. See Juicy Whip, Inc. v. Orange Bang, Inc., 292 F.3d 728 (Fed. Cir. 2002).

131. See, e.g.,Greenpeace, Ltd. v. Plant Genetic Systems N.V. et al., 28 IIC 75 (1997).

132. Professor Bagley argues against such decoupling. See Bagley, supra note 129 at 516.

133. See Webber v. Virginia, 103 U.S. 344 at 347-48 (1880) (Court stating that patent law did not displace police power). For a discussion of the relationship between intellectual property and the police power, see Ghosh, ibid. at 402-03.

134. The analysis of this problem under the prisoner’s dilemma rests on how non-cooperation is framed. If patents are viewed as an exception to the police power or competition law, then extending patenting to certain subject matter may provide a means to escape regulatory schemes. Within the United States, however, it is clear that patents do not provide a safe harbor from the exercise of the police power. See discussion in Webber, supra note 133.

135. See Ho, Cynthia M., “Splicing Morality and Patent Law: Issues Arising from Mixing Mice and Men”(2000) 2 Wash. U. J. L. & Pol’y, 247 at 248 (stating that seekers of patent were planning to re Press the invention).Google Scholar

136. See Ruckelshaus v. Monsanto Co.,467 U.S. 986 (1984).

137. To put this another way, the grant of a patent creates a legal interest that can be regulated just like property can be regulated. For a discussion of how law creates regulable interests, see Scott, James C., Seeing Like A State: how certain schemes to improve the human condition have failed (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998) at 5384.Google Scholar

138. See, e.g., McSherry, supra note 60; Krimsky, supra note 60.

139. For a discussion of patent law’s relationship to non-commercial activities, see Strandburg, Katherine J., “What Does The Public Get? Experimental Use and the Patent Bargain2004 Wisc. L. Rev. 81 at 135-38Google Scholar. Bagley, supra note 129; Rai, Arti K., “Regulating Scientific Research: Intellectual Property Rights and the Norms of Science” (1999) 94 Nw. U. L. Rev. 77 at 81-88.Google Scholar

140. Lindbloom, Charles, The Market System: What It Is, How It Works, and What to Make of It (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2001) at 25864.Google Scholar

141. See ibid. at 271.

142. See Kaufer, supra note 63 at 2-3.

143. Statute of Monopolies, 21 James I, ch.3 (1623).

144. See, e.g., Landes & Posner, supra note 69 at 35-36 (pointing out the central role of the state in the system of intellectual property in contrast with real property).

145. For a criticism of the reward theory of patent, see Abramowicz, Michael, “Perfecting Patent Prizes” (2003) 56 Vand. L. Rev. 115 at 127-58.Google Scholar

146. See Kaufer, supra note 63 at 1-2.

147. See Lindbloom, supra note 140 at 117-19.

148. See ibid. at 118.

149. See Allison, John R. & Tiller, Emerson H., “The Business Method Patent Myth” (2003) 18 Berkeley Tech. L. J. 987 at 1079 (describing how the nonobviousness requirement has become more slack).Google Scholar

150. See ibid. at 1078 (discussing subjectivity of patent granting process).

151. See Lindbloom, supra note 140 at 207-08.

152. See ibid. at 226-27.

153. See ibid. at 102-06.

154. See Allison & Tiller, supra note 149 at 1078.

155. See Bonito Boats v. Thunder Craft Boats, 489 U.S. 141 at 150 (1989) (Court explaining how novelty and non-obviousness criteria in tandem further values of competition and exploitation of public domain knowledge).

156. See Lindbloom, supra note 140 at 262-63.

157. See discussion found in essay, supra note 108.

158. For an excellent discussion of the relationship between scientific discovery and democracy, see Kitcher, Philip, Science, Truth, and Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) at 11416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar