Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-03T23:04:58.915Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE ROLE OF EPISTEMIC VIRTUE IN THE REALIZATION OF BASIC GOODS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 December 2016

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that, contrary to popular opinion, there is good reason to think that the qualities that make people good reasoners also make them better off. I will focus specifically on epistemic virtue: roughly, the kind of character in virtue of which one is excellently oriented towards epistemic goods. I propose that epistemic virtue is importantly implicated in the realization of some of the goods that are widely believed to be instrumental to, or even constitutive of, well-being. Here I focus on one such good: friendship.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Adler, J. 2004. ‘Reconciling Open-mindedness and Belief.’ Theory and Research in Education, 2: 127–42.Google Scholar
Alston, W. 1993. ‘Epistemic Desiderata.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53: 527551.Google Scholar
Alston, W. 2005. Beyond Justification: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Aristotle, 2000. Nicomachean Ethics. In Crisp, R. (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Baehr, J. 2011. The Inquiring Mind: On Intellectual Virtues and Virtue Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Baril, A. 2013. ‘Pragmatic Encroachment in Accounts of Epistemic Excellence.’ Synthese, 190: 3929–52.Google Scholar
Baril, A. 2016. ‘Virtue and Well-Being.’ In Fletcher, G. (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being, pp. 242–58. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Block, J. and Colvin, C. 1994. ‘Positive Illusions and Well-Being Revisited: Separating Fiction from Fact.Psychological Bulletin, 116: 28.Google Scholar
Colvin, C. and Block, J. 1994. ‘Do Positive Illusions Foster Mental Health? An Examination of the Taylor and Brown Formulation.Psychological Bulletin, CXVI (1): 320.Google Scholar
Colvin, C., Block, J. and Funder, D. 1995. ‘Overly Positive Self-Evaluations and Personality: Negative Implications for Mental Health.’ Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 68: 1152–62.Google Scholar
Elga, A. 2005. ‘On Overrating Oneself … and Knowing it.’ Philosophical Studies, 123: 115–24.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fletcher, G. 2013. ‘A Fresh Start for the Objective-List Theory of Well-Being.’ Utilitas, 25: 206–20.Google Scholar
Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. 1989. ‘Friendship and Moral Growth.’ Journal of Value Inquiry, 23: 313.Google Scholar
Guenin, L. 2005. ‘Intellectual Honesty.Synthese, 145: 177232.Google Scholar
Hare, W. 2003. ‘Is it Good to be Open-minded?International Journal of Applied Philosophy, 17: 7387.Google Scholar
Hazlett, A. 2012. ‘Higher-Order Epistemic Attitudes and Intellectual Humility.Episteme, 9: 205–23.Google Scholar
Helm, B. 2013. ‘Friendship.’ In Zalta, E. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/friendship/.Google Scholar
Kawall, J. 2002. ‘Other-regarding Epistemic Virtues.Ratio, 15: 257–75.Google Scholar
Kawall, J. 2013. ‘Friendship and Epistemic Norms.Philosophical Studies, 165: 341–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, S. 2004. ‘Friendship and Belief.Philosophical Papers, 33: 329–51.Google Scholar
King, N. 2014. ‘Perseverance as an Intellectual Virtue.’ Synthese, 191: 3501–23.Google Scholar
Lauinger, W. 2013. ‘The Missing-Desires Objection to Hybrid Theories of Well-Being.Southern Journal of Philosophy, 51: 270–95.Google Scholar
Murphy, M. 2001. Natural Law and Practical Rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rice, C. 2013. ‘Defending the Objective List Theory of Well-Being.’ Ratio, 26: 196211.Google Scholar
Riggs, W. 2010. ‘Open-mindedness.’ Metaphilosophy, 41: 172–88.Google Scholar
Roberts, R. and Wood, W. 2007. Intellectual Virtues: An Essay in Regulative Epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Sherman, N. 1987. ‘Aristotle on Friendship and the Shared Life.’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 47: 589613.Google Scholar
Stroud, S. 2006. ‘Epistemic Partiality in Friendship.Ethics, 116: 498524.Google Scholar
Swanton, C. 1995. ‘Profiles of the Virtues.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 76: 4772.Google Scholar
Taylor, G. 1985. Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-Assessment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, S. and Brown, J. 1988. ‘Illusion and Well-Being: A Social Psychological Perspective on Mental Health.’ Psychological Bulletin, 103: 193210.Google Scholar
Taylor, S., Brown, J. 1994. ‘Positive Illusions and Well-Being Revisited: Separating Fact from Fiction.’ Psychological Bulletin, 116: 21–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Whitcomb, D., Battaly, H., Baehr, J. and Howard-Snyder, D. 2015. ‘Intellectual Humility: Owning Our Limitations.Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91(1). doi: 10.1111/phpr.12228.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. 1991. ‘Impersonal Friends.Monist, 74: 329.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, L. 1996. Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar