Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T18:01:39.139Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The evolution of shame and its display

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 October 2022

Mitchell Landers*
Affiliation:
Center for Early Childhood Research, Department of Psychology, The University of Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA
Daniel Sznycer
Affiliation:
Oklahoma Center for Evolutionary Analysis, Department of Psychology, Oklahoma State University, Stillwater, OK, USA
*
*Corresponding author. E-mail: msblanders@uchicago.edu

Abstract

The shame system appears to be natural selection's solution to the adaptive problem of information-triggered reputational damage. Over evolutionary time, this problem would have led to a coordinated set of adaptations – the shame system – designed to minimise the spread of negative information about the self and the likelihood and costs of being socially devalued by others. This information threat theory of shame can account for much of what we know about shame and generate precise predictions. Here, we analyse the behavioural configuration that people adopt stereotypically when ashamed – slumped posture, downward head tilt, gaze avoidance, inhibition of speech – in light of shame's hypothesised function. This behavioural configuration may have differentially favoured its own replication by (a) hampering the transfer of information (e.g. diminishing audiences’ tendency to attend to or encode identifying information – shame camouflage) and/or (b) evoking less severe devaluative responses from audiences (shame display). The shame display hypothesis has received considerable attention and empirical support, whereas the shame camouflage hypothesis has to our knowledge not been advanced or tested. We elaborate on this hypothesis and suggest directions for future research on the shame pose.

Type
Perspective
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

Social media summary: The shame display functions to appease others. Landers and Sznycer propose an additional function: to render us invisible.

Introduction: Shame is an adaptation

Shame occurs in every known culture (Brown, Reference Brown1991; Darwin, Reference Darwin1872/2009; Fessler, Reference Fessler and Hinton1999); its components develop reliably and early (Barrett, Reference Barrett, Mascolo and Griffin1998; Lewis, Alessandri, & Sullivan, Reference Lewis, Alessandri and Sullivan1992; Stipek, Recchia, & McClintic, Reference Stipek, Recchia and McClintic1992), even in congenitally blind individuals (Tracy & Matsumoto, Reference Tracy and Matsumoto2008). Explicit instruction and reinforcement are unlikely to play a causal role in its development, since conditioning of social fear is resistant to extinction (Dimberg & Öhman, Reference Dimberg and Öhman1983; Öhman & Dimberg, Reference Öhman and Dimberg1978). And although there is cultural variation in its elicitors and behavioural outputs (Benedict, Reference Benedict1946; Fessler, Reference Fessler2004; Keltner & Anderson, Reference Keltner and Anderson2000; Mosquera, Manstead, & Fischer, Reference Mosquera, Manstead and Fischer2002; Shweder, Reference Shweder2003), shame has a culturally invariant cognitive substrate (Fessler, Reference Fessler and Hinton1999; Scherer & Wallbott, Reference Scherer and Wallbott1994). Shame thus has the hallmarks of an adaptation.

Adaptations are packages of design features retained over evolutionary time because they reliably solved tasks tributary to reproduction in ancestral environments. An adaptationist approach to understanding shame thus begins from theories of the adaptive problems our ancestors faced over deep evolutionary time (Tooby & Cosmides, Reference Tooby, Cosmides, Barkow, Cosmides and Tooby1992, Reference Tooby, Cosmides and Buss2015). In what follows, we provide an overview of the class of adaptive problems the human shame system appears designed to solve, how shame solves such problems and how this account of shame fits with the extant literature on shame and makes novel, unique predictions. Then, we review what is known about the stereotypical human shame display and analyse this display given shame's hypothesised function.

The adaptive problem of shame: Information-triggered devaluation

Our hominin ancestors evolved in environments characterised by high rates of mortality (Burger, Baudisch, & Vaupel, Reference Burger, Baudisch and Vaupel2012), resource scarcity (Hill & Hurtado, Reference Hill and Hurtado1996), variance in food acquisition (Hill & Hurtado, Reference Hill and Hurtado1996; Kaplan & Hill, Reference Kaplan and Hill1985), disease and injury (Sugiyama, Reference Sugiyama2004), and aggression from predators and conspecifics (Keeley, Reference Keeley1997). In contrast to other animals, including our primate cousins, humans often relied on other members of their groups for the assistance necessary to survive and reproduce (Clutton-Brock, Reference Clutton-Brock2009; Schrock, Snodgrass, & Sugiyama, Reference Schrock, Snodgrass and Sugiyama2020). Such heavy reliance on mutual aid implies selection for incentivising one's mates, friends, allies and fellow group members to render assistance in times of hunger, incapacitation, or interpersonal conflict (Sugiyama, Reference Sugiyama2004). Because being positively valued by fellow group members would have led to being helped more and exploited less, how our ancestors were valued by those around them would have had considerable impact on their reproductive success (von Rueden & Jaeggi, Reference von Rueden and Jaeggi2016).

Research indicates that when new information comes to light that reveals an individual to be less socially valuable to others than previously supposed (e.g. lacking in skills, selfish, diseased, of reduced social status), audiences react by attaching less weight to that person's welfare (e.g. see Delton & Robertson, Reference Delton and Robertson2016; Sell, Reference Sell2005; Lim, Reference Lim2012; Sznycer, Reference Sznycer2010; Ermer, Reference Ermer2007; Sparrowe, Reference Sparrowe2020). Over evolutionary time, individuals devalued in this manner would have incurred fitness costs by, for example, being avoided, shunned, denied help and/or ostracised more often (Kurzban & Leary, Reference Kurzban and Leary2001; Hales et al., Reference Hales, Kassner, Williams and Graziano2016). For our ancestors, the adaptive problem of being devalued would therefore have made the difference between a long, successful life and an early, possibly violent demise.

The information threat theory of shame

The need to avoid the costs resulting from devaluation would have selected for regulatory adaptations to minimise the spread of negative information about the self and the costs associated with any ensuing devaluation that resulted from it (Gilbert, Reference Gilbert1997; Tooby & Cosmides, Reference Tooby, Cosmides, Lewis, Haviland-Jones and Barrett2008; Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016; Fessler, Reference Fessler and Hinton1999; Weisfeld & Dillon, Reference Weisfeld and Dillon2012). Over the millennia, those individuals who better attracted goodwill and avoided the indifference, censure and wrath of potential aid-givers would have more frequently survived and reproduced. This information threat theory of shame therefore posits that shame is an adaptation that evolved to defend against information-triggered devaluation (Landers, Sznycer & Al Shawaf, Reference Landers, Sznycer, Al-Shawaf, Al-Shawaf and Shackelford2022; Sznycer, Reference Sznycer2010; Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016; Sznycer, Sell, & Lieberman, Reference Sznycer, Sell and Lieberman2021; Sznycer, Cosmides, & Tooby, Reference Sznycer, Cosmides and Tooby2017; Robertson et al., Reference Robertson, Sznycer, Delton, Tooby and Cosmides2018; see also Gilbert, Reference Gilbert1997; Fessler, Reference Fessler and Hinton1999; Weisfeld & Dillon, Reference Weisfeld and Dillon2012; Baumeister & Tice, Reference Baumeister and Tice1990; Schlenker & Leary, Reference Schlenker and Leary1982). According to this account, the shame system is an adaptation designed to coordinate psychology, physiology and behaviour to: (a) inhibit actions likely to yield more costs from social devaluation than the benefits said actions would yield; (b) limit the spread of potentially discrediting information about the self; (c) minimise the degree and scope of any social devaluation that does occur; and, if devaluation occurs, (d) motivate actions geared toward mitigating its costs.

In line with this account, experimentally manipulating (potential or actual) devaluation reliably elicits shame (Smith et al., Reference Smith, Webster, Parrott and Eyre2002; Dickerson et al., Reference Dickerson, Mycek and Zaldivar2008; Robertson et al., Reference Robertson, Sznycer, Delton, Tooby and Cosmides2018). Being devalued – disliked, excluded, tortured, oppressed – by others elicits shame even when individuals know they haven't done anything wrong (Robertson et al., Reference Robertson, Sznycer, Delton, Tooby and Cosmides2018; Shapiro, Reference Shapiro2003; Levi, Reference Levi1989). The true elicitor of shame, therefore, appears to be neither objective wrongdoing nor one's causal attributions for one's wrongdoing (Tracy & Robins, Reference Tracy and Robins2004), but rather the threat or actuality of social devaluation (Robertson et al., Reference Robertson, Sznycer, Delton, Tooby and Cosmides2018). Wrongdoing so often triggers shame because wrongdoing reliably predicts the threat of being devalued, but wrongdoing is neither necessary nor sufficient for triggering shame.

The information threat theory proposes that the shame system operates by incorporating both an invariant architecture and open parameters. This is because the best-bet response to counter devaluation depends on the internal and external environments in which the shame adaptation finds itself: you may or may not have enough physical strength or high-status allies to resist an attack against you; you may or may not have personal qualities that could compensate for your devalued trait; by the time you hear the sound of footsteps approaching, you may or may not have enough time to sneak out of the room before you're caught red-handed. These open parameters take variable, dynamically updated inputs – e.g. an audience is present but not expressing displeasure (Dickerson et al., Reference Dickerson, Mycek and Zaldivar2008); ‘I am well-connected’ (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Takemura, Delton, Sato, Robertson, Cosmides and Tooby2012); ‘the audience has weapons’ – and feeds them into the invariant architecture. Utilising specialised concepts (e.g. AUDIENCE; Sznycer, Reference Sznycer2010), the invariant architecture then specifies the decision logic that matches sub-classes of inputs to sub-classes of behavioural outputs (e.g. terminate action, give excuse) to minimise the devaluative threat (Sznycer, Reference Sznycer2010; Lukaszewski et al., Reference Lukaszewski, Lewis, Durkee, Sell, Sznycer and Buss2020; Sznycer & Cohen, Reference Sznycer and Cohen2021; see Table 1).

Table 1. Hypothesised outputs of the shame system as a function of its mode of operation

Adapted from Sznycer (Reference Sznycer2010: 165).

Differences in the expression of the shame system across situations, individuals and populations can thus be interpreted as differences in the distributions of relevant inputs fed into the open parameters. For example, the cost of devaluation can be mitigated by forming new alliances. Therefore, the information threat theory predicts that individual differences in shame-proneness will depend in part on perceptions of the ease with which one can form new relationships (i.e. ‘relational mobility’; see Yuki et al., Reference Yuki, Schug, Horikawa, Takemura, Sato, Yokota and Kamaya2007) to compensate for lost or damaged relationships. Testing this prediction, Sznycer et al. (Reference Sznycer, Takemura, Delton, Sato, Robertson, Cosmides and Tooby2012) compared the shame responses of Western participants with those of East-Asian participants – traditionally thought to be more shame prone (Benedict, Reference Benedict1946) – and found that this ‘cultural’ difference was partially mediated by East-Asian participants’ perception of lower relational mobility (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Takemura, Delton, Sato, Robertson, Cosmides and Tooby2012).

Additionally, the information threat theory predicts that individuals with highly valued (or feared) traits (e.g. resourcefulness, physical attractiveness, being well-connected) will be less prone to shame all else equal, because their superior position can be leveraged to (a) impose or threaten to impose more costs on others to incentivise less devaluation or prevent it altogether (Sell, Tooby, & Cosmides, Reference Sell, Tooby and Cosmides2009) and (b) allow them to better weather the consequences of devaluation when they are devalued. As predicted, such individuals are less prone to shame (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Takemura, Delton, Sato, Robertson, Cosmides and Tooby2012). Similarly, variation in audience composition should affect the degree of shame activation: a high-status audience, for example, can impose greater costs on others (and withhold greater benefits), and so being devalued by such an audience should be more shame-provoking than being devalued by a low-status audience, all else equal. In line with this, Garland and Brown (Reference Garland and Brown1972) found that in a task where longer singing time increased participant payment, teenage girls who evaluated their singing as poor sang longer when their audience was described as made up of ‘poor singers’ than when their audience was described as made up of ‘excellent singers’ (Garland & Brown, Reference Garland and Brown1972). Likewise, Jackson and Latané (Reference Jackson and Latané1981) found that participants reported more nervousness at the prospect of singing in front of an audience of graduate students and professors from a music school than at the prospect of singing in front of tone-deaf undergraduates. In line with the information threat theory, the shame people experience seems well calibrated to the specifics of the threat posed by devaluation.

A novel prediction derived from the information threat theory

To minimise the threat of devaluation aptly, the shame system must operate not only reactively, when one knows the audience is expressing or has expressed devaluative responses, but also prospectively, in advance of any action likely to bring about social devaluation (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016; Leary, Reference Leary2015; Sommerville, Schmidt, Yun, & Burns, Reference Sommerville, Schmidt, Yun and Burns2013; see also Fehr & Gächter, Reference Fehr and Gächter2000). To activate prospectively, the shame system needs accurate estimates of the degree to which fellow group members devalue a given act or personal characteristic. In short, the shame system needs to predict the precise magnitude of likely devaluation for a given act or trait, before any actual devaluation takes place, in order to guide decisions cost-effectively. According to the information threat theory, anticipatory feelings of shame internally transmit precise information about the predicted magnitude of audience devaluation one would incur were one to engage in an act disfavoured by the audience, weighted by the odds of being discovered by the audience (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016, see also Crockett, Siegel, Kurth-Nelson, Dayan, & Dolan, Reference Crockett, Siegel, Kurth-Nelson, Dayan and Dolan2017). This internal signal helps avoid the dual errors of prospective shame under-activation, whereby the individual mounts an insufficient response to prevent or diminish devaluation (and thus incurs excessive costs from others’ devaluation), and prospective shame over-activation, whereby the individual experiences so much shame that they refrain from taking actions that would yield more direct benefits than the costs they would incur from that devaluation.

This reasoning led to empirical tests of the hypotheses that the shame system is designed to (a) accurately forecast the magnitude of audience devaluation on an act-by-act basis, and (b) generate an internal signal of anticipatory shame in proportion to that forecast. Across three different cultures (the US, India and Israel), participants were presented with a set of socially devalued acts or traits (e.g. theft, sexual infidelity, poor table manners, lack of ambition) and were asked to rate in a between-subjects design, for each act or trait, either the intensity of shame they would feel if the act or trait were true of them or how negatively they would view another individual if the act or trait were true of that other individual (a measure of devaluation). In all three countries, the intensity of anticipatory shame closely tracked the magnitude of devaluation expressed by local audiences (Figure 1a–c). Furthermore, shame within each country tracked the magnitude of devaluation reported in the other two countries, suggesting universality in both the structure and content of shame (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016; see also Durkee, Lukaszewski, & Buss, Reference Durkee, Lukaszewski and Buss2019; Cohen, Chun, & Sznycer, Reference Cohen, Chun and Sznycer2020). Follow-up studies demonstrated that this close association is specific to shame: other negatively valenced emotions such as sadness and anxiety did not track audience devaluation (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016). Moreover, further follow-up studies conducted in 15 traditional small-scale societies around the world again found close associations between shame and audience devaluation: shame in each population closely tracked both the devaluation reported locally and the devaluation reported in each of the other 14 populations. Notably, measures of linguistic similarity, religious similarity, and geographic proximity – three common measures of cultural distance – each failed to account for the strength of between-community associations between shame and devaluation (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Xygalatas, Agey, Alami, An, Ananyeva and Tooby2018; Figure 1, d–r).

Figure 1. Shame tracks devaluation. The intensity of anticipatory shame tracks the intensity of audience devaluation. Scatterplots A–C: data from three mass societies (adapted from Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016). The stimuli were a set of brief hypothetical scenarios describing socially devalued actions and personal characteristics. The scenarios were phrased either from the perspective of the focal individual (e.g. ‘You are not generous with others’; shame condition) or from the perspective of an observer vis-à-vis the focal individual (e.g. ‘He is not generous with others’; audience condition; between-subjects design). For each scenario, participants rated either their feeling of shame if they took those actions or had those characteristics (shame), or the degree to which they would negatively view the individual in the scenarios if the individual took those actions or had those characteristics (audience). Each point represents the mean shame rating and mean devaluation rating of one scenario. Data from (number of scenarios): A, US (29); B, India (29); C, Israel (24). Scatterplots D–R, data from 15 small-scale societies (adapted from Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Xygalatas, Agey, Alami, An, Ananyeva and Tooby2018). Same experimental design, but with a set of 12 scenarios that were different from the ones used in Sznycer et al. (Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016). D, Cotopaxi, Ecuador; E, Morona-Santiago, Ecuador; F, Coquimbo, Chile; G, Drâa-Tafilalet, Morocco; H, Enugu, Nigeria; I, Chalkidiki, Greece; J, Ikland, Uganda; K, Le Morne, Mauritius; L, La Gaulette, Mauritius; M, Dhading, Nepal; N, Tuva, Russia; O, Khövsgöl, Mongolia; P, Shaanxi, China; Q, Farming Communities, Japan; R, Fishing Communities, Japan. In all cases, shame ratings and devaluation ratings were given by different participants. Effect sizes: r 2 linear.

The information threat theory can account for many known features of shame

The hypothesis that shame's adaptive function is to mitigate the threat of devaluation can explain many published findings on shame. For instance, being devalued causes people pain (MacDonald & Leary, Reference MacDonald and Leary2005; Eisenberger, Reference Eisenberger2012); people generally avoid actions that could exacerbate devaluation (De Hooge, Breugelmans, & Zeelenberg, Reference De Hooge, Breugelmans and Zeelenberg2008; Fehr & Gächter, Reference Fehr and Gächter2000); among students and depressed patients, shame proneness correlates with perceptions of low status and submissive behaviour (Gilbert, Reference Gilbert2000a); people tend to hide reputationally damaging information (Rockenbach & Milinski, Reference Rockenbach and Milinski2011; Sznycer, Schniter, Tooby, & Cosmides, Reference Sznycer, Schniter, Tooby and Cosmides2015); and when other people discover reputationally damaging information about them, shamed individuals withdraw (Leach & Cidam, Reference Leach and Cidam2015), appease those who know it (Keltner, Young, & Buswell, Reference Keltner, Young and Buswell1997) and apologise to them (Schniter, Sheremeta, & Sznycer, Reference Schniter, Sheremeta and Sznycer2013). Furthermore, shame is exacerbated when failing at easy (vs. difficult) tasks – expected if low competence elicits more devaluation and warrants more shame (Lewis et al., Reference Lewis, Alessandri and Sullivan1992). Some evidence suggests that shame increases with severity of disease, perhaps because severe diseases are impairing or communicable, and individuals suffering from such diseases are less capable of aiding others or defending their own interests (Leary, Rapp, Herbst, Exum, & Feldman, Reference Leary, Rapp, Herbst, Exum and Feldman1998; Homayoon et al., Reference Homayoon, Hiebler-Ragger, Zenker, Weger, Unterrainer and Aberer2020).

The information threat theory can explain the link between being victimised and feeling shame – an ethical and scientific puzzle, since victims are often victimised through no fault of their own. Some evidence indeed suggests such a link. For instance, being a victim of torture (Shapiro, Reference Shapiro2003), marital violence (Andrews & Brewin, Reference Andrews and Brewin1990), rape (Notman & Nadelson, Reference Notman and Nadelson1976) and physical and sexual abuse during childhood (Andrews & Hunter, Reference Andrews and Hunter1997) elicit shame and self-blame. Both literary and sociological data (Hovannisian, Reference Hovannisian1986; Levi, Reference Levi1989; Totten, Reference Totten2009) indicate that shame is prevalent in victims of wanton subjugation, where ‘on a rational plane, there should not have been much to be ashamed of’ (Levi, Reference Levi1989, p. 77). Yet while this link between victimisation and shame may seem odd or anomalous if shame is triggered as a result of attributing negative outcomes to the self (Tangney, Wagner, & Gramzow, Reference Tangney, Wagner and Gramzow1992) or violating a norm (Fessler, Reference Fessler and Hinton1999), from the perspective of the information threat theory, victimisation can meet the input conditions of devaluation: after all, being victimised often results from being devalued by others, and the inability to resist victimisation may indicate low personal formidability or status – personal characteristics that meet the input conditions of the shame programme.

When it comes to behavioural outputs, shame can produce a wide and seemingly paradoxical array of actions. For instance, shame can generate both enhanced cooperativeness and hostile tactics, such as shifting blame to victims, scapegoating third parties and threatening or mobilising aggression (Leach & Cidam, Reference Leach and Cidam2015; Fessler, Reference Fessler, Selten and Gigerenzer2001; Scheff, Reference Scheff and Lewis1987; Elison et al., Reference Elison, Garofalo and Velotti2014; Zhu et al., Reference Zhu, Xu, Tang, Liu, Wang, An, Mai and Liu2019), making amends (De Hooge et al., Reference De Hooge, Breugelmans and Zeelenberg2008; De Hooge, Breugelmans, Wagemans, & Zeelenberg, Reference De Hooge, Breugelmans, Wagemans and Zeelenberg2018; Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Schniter, Tooby and Cosmides2015), avoiding others (Barrett, Zahn-Waxler, & Cole, Reference Barrett, Zahn-Waxler and Cole1993), feeling depressed (Tangney et al., Reference Tangney, Wagner and Gramzow1992; Cheung, Gilbert, & Irons, Reference Cheung, Gilbert and Irons2004) and attempting to improve oneself (De Hooge et al., Reference De Hooge, Zeelenberg and & Breugelmans2010). Such heterogeneous tactics can interfere with each other if deployed concurrently (e.g. cooperation and aggression) but have the capacity to minimise the threat of devaluation if deployed in the right situations or sequences.

Forms and functions of the shame display

One hallmark of shame is a characteristic display that includes slumped posture, gaze aversion, downward head tilt (Fessler, Reference Fessler and Hinton1999; Keltner et al. Reference Keltner, Young and Buswell1997; Tracy, Robins, & Schriber, Reference Tracy, Robins and Schriber2009; see Figure 2) and behavioural inhibition, including reduced speech (Gilbert, Reference Gilbert, Gilbert and Andrews1998; Price & Sloman, Reference Price and Sloman1987; Fessler, Reference Fessler and Hinton1999). The shame display is produced when people experience personal failure (Tracy & Matsumoto, Reference Tracy and Matsumoto2008; Witkower, Mercadante, & Tracy, Reference Witkower, Mercadante and Tracy2020), and shame displayers are correspondingly perceived by observers as having suffered a reduction in their social status (Shariff, Tracy, & Markusoff, Reference Shariff, Tracy and Markusoff2012). The shame display develops reliably; it is produced by young children (Barrett, Reference Barrett, Mascolo and Griffin1998; Lewis et al., Reference Lewis, Alessandri and Sullivan1992; Stipek et al., Reference Stipek, Recchia and McClintic1992) and congenitally blind adults (Tracy & Matsumoto, Reference Tracy and Matsumoto2008). The shame display also affords teachable moments: people infer from expressions of shame what fellow group members devalue and correspondingly downgrade their inclination to perform those devalued actions or activities (Schaumberg & Skowronek, Reference Schaumberg and Skowronek2022).

Figure 2. Prototypical shame display. Reprinted from Martens et al. (Reference Martens, Tracy and Shariff2012), copyright (2022) by Taylor & Francis. Reprinted with permission.

The human shame display appears to be phylogenetically ancient; it resembles the displays of submission produced by non-human species in aggressive contests over dominance (Martens, Tracy, & Shariff, Reference Martens, Tracy and Shariff2012; Tracy, Robins, & Schriber, Reference Tracy, Robins and Schriber2009). Behavioral homologues or analogues of human shame occur widely across species (Gilbert, Reference Gilbert, Gilbert and Bailey2000b): in barbary macaques (Deag, Reference Deag1977), rhesus monkeys (Møller, Harlow, & Mitchell, Reference Møller, Harlow and Mitchell1968), chimpanzees (Nishida, Reference Nishida1983), lemurids (Pereira & Kappeler, Reference Pereira and Kappeler1997), mice, guinea-pigs and golden hamsters (Grant & Mackintosh, Reference Grant and Mackintosh1963), laboratory rats (Blanchard & Blanchard, Reference Blanchard and Blanchard1977), canids (Darwin, Reference Darwin1872/2009; Fox, Reference Fox1969), pigs (McGlone, Reference McGlone1985), lizards (Carpenter, Reference Carpenter1962), black-crowned night herons (Noble, Wurm, & Schmidt, Reference Noble, Wurm and Schmidt1938), fish (Grosenick, Clement, & Fernald, Reference Grosenick, Clement and Fernald2007; Lorenz, Reference Lorenz1966) and stone crabs (Sinclair, Reference Sinclair1977).

Compared with non-human animals, status in humans depends less heavily on fighting ability or readiness to submit to the powerful (Gilbert, Reference Gilbert1997; Fessler, Reference Fessler and Hinton1999) and more heavily on the individual's ability and willingness to confer benefits (Durkee, Lukaszewski, & Buss, Reference Durkee, Lukaszewski and Buss2020; Eisenbruch, Grillot, Maestripieri & Roney, Reference Eisenbruch, Grillot, Maestripieri and Roney2016; von Rueden, Gurven, Kaplan, Reference von Rueden, Gurven and Kaplan2008) and to abide by the coordinated values of fellow group members (Gilbert, Reference Gilbert1997; Fessler, Reference Fessler and Hinton1999). This difference has led some researchers to question the adaptive value of the shame display in modern humans: the gaze avoidance and general submissive stance delivered by the shame display may have been useful for signaling submission and deterring further attacks in our ancestral past, but may now no longer serve such a function in our modern, coordinated, prestige-driven societies (Gilbert & McGuire, Reference Gilbert, McGuire, Gilbert and Andrews1998; Gilbert, Reference Gilbert1997; see also Curtis & Miller, Reference Curtis and Miller1986). From an adaptationist standpoint, however, one might ask: are there features in the human shame display that seem improbably well-designed to solve an adaptive problem – here, defend against the threat of devaluation – relative to what chance would produce (Williams, Reference Williams1966)? An affirmative answer to this question seems quite plausible. The human shame display seems well-engineered to cost-effectively address two distinct sub-problems related to information-triggered devaluation: (a) mollifying observers when one has been identified as a transgressor; and (b) reducing observers’ ability to identify one as a transgressor in the first place.

Mollifying observers

Gaze avoidance is a hallmark of the shame display, but people generally judge gaze-avoiders unfavourably (Larsen & Schackelford, Reference Larsen and Shackelford1996). This raises the question of why a component of the shame system – putatively designed to counter devaluation – would produce actions that increase devaluation. This puzzle may be solved, however, when considering that the relevant comparison is not between observer evaluations of gaze seekers and gaze avoiders generally, but rather between observer evaluations of gaze seekers and gaze avoiders whom observers know have committed disreputable behaviour. When evaluated against this more relevant standard, gaze avoidance appears to have positive (less negative) effects for gaze avoiders: indeed, when an individual commits a moral infraction of which observers are aware, individuals who subsequently gaze-avoid are judged more favourably than those who gaze-seek. And audiences’ responses toward individuals known to have transgressed are more forgiving when the transgressor produces the gaze-avoiding shame display than when the transgressor fails to produce gaze-avoidance (De Jong, Reference De Jong1999; Keltner, Young, & Buswell, Reference Keltner, Young and Buswell1997; Semin & Manstead, Reference Semin and Manstead1982). For example, Keltner and colleagues (Reference Keltner, Young and Buswell1997) found that audience members were more sympathetic toward students whom they were told had failed a presentation when those students exhibited the shame display rather than an embarrassment display (Keltner et al., Reference Keltner, Young and Buswell1997). And in a follow-up experiment, it was found that observers judged a convicted criminal to be less guilty and assigned them less prison time when criminals displayed shame or embarrassment compared with neutral expressions. Similarly, Giner-Sorolla, Castano, Espinosa, and Brown (Reference Giner-Sorolla, Castano, Espinosa and Brown2008) found that when told of a CEO who verbally apologised on behalf of his company for a chemical spill, audiences were more accepting of the apology when he expressed shame than when he expressed guilt or no emotion (Giner-Sorolla et al., Reference Giner-Sorolla, Castano, Espinosa and Brown2008). Further, in experiments asking participants to assign penalties to fictitious sex offenders, Proeve and Howells (Reference Proeve and Howells2006) found that audiences were more lenient when told the offenders expressed shame than when they expressed sadness or remorse (Proeve & Howells, Reference Proeve and Howells2006). These findings demonstrate the effect of the gaze-avoidant shame display to mollify the angry reactions of observers, and suggest, contra mismatch arguments, that shame-driven gaze avoidance need not be a vestigial feature on its way to being selected out (see Sznycer, Reference Sznycer2010).

The mollifying effect of gaze avoidance (and the general submissive stance) on audiences has been interpreted as appeasement (Keltner et al., Reference Keltner, Young and Buswell1997) – the evolutionarily conserved inhibition of another's aggression by signaling that one withdraws from a contest (Fessler, Reference Fessler, Tracy, Robins and Tangney2007; Sloman, Price, Gilbert, Gardner, Reference Sloman, Price, Gilbert and Gardner1994; Weisfeld & Dillon, Reference Weisfeld and Dillon2012). However, positive evaluations of gaze avoidance have also been observed in contexts in which there is no apparent transgression. For example, gaze-avoidance is judged less favourably than gaze-seeking when the target is physically attractive or expressing happiness, but gaze-avoidance is judged more favourably when the target is physically unattractive or expressing disgust (Main, DeBruine, Little, & Jones, Reference Main, DeBruine, Little and Jones2010; Rall, Greenspan, & Neidich, Reference Rall, Greenspan and Neidich1984). The latter effects may still fall under the rubric of appeasement, however, if gaze avoidance signals the pre-emptive rejection of a claim for attention or social valuation perceived as undeserved. Nevertheless, more research is needed to affirm the appeasement hypothesis.

The invisibility hypothesis

While a sizeable literature deals with the appeasing function of the shame display, no research we are aware of has elaborated on the possibility that the shame ‘display’ might serve another function: evasion from identification (and thus from devaluation). We use quotation marks around ‘display’ here because according to this hypothesis, the characteristic constellation of shame actions functions not to elicit a forgiving response from audiences, but to evade recognition and evaluation by the audience. That is, in some contexts the shame ‘display’ may function as camouflage rather than as a signal (Smith & Harper, Reference Smith and Harper2003). In what follows, we describe the logic behind this idea (what we term the invisibility hypothesis), suggest ways the shame system could realise this function, and offer questions that future research could address.

If shame functions to diminish costs owing to devaluation as the information threat theory suggests, then one powerful way to accomplish that goal would be to prevent identification or recognition of the transgressor in the first place. Or, to paraphrase Sun Tzu (Reference Tzu2010), the most effective form of appeasement for one's transgressions is the one not required. If caught committing a harmful, immoral, or disgraceful act, appeasing those who discover you might be prudent. However, you'd be even better served to evade detection and identification entirely, thus saving yourself the cost of appeasement (itself an admission of reduced status or social value) and any ensuing reduction in status or esteem. As Zhu and colleagues have shown (2019), people prefer not to appease: when feeling shame, people tolerate being treated poorly by others when others know why they feel ashamed but angrily protest that same poor treatment when it can be portrayed credibly as undeserved – that is, when people know others are in the dark about their transgression (Zhu et al., Reference Zhu, Xu, Tang, Liu, Wang, An, Mai and Liu2019).

The view of the shame ‘display’ as a means to achieve invisibility can be found in Darwin's Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals:

Under a keen sense of shame there is a strong desire for concealment. We turn away the whole body, more especially the face, which we endeavour in some manner to hide. An ashamed person can hardly endure to meet the gaze of those present, so that he almost invariably casts down his eyes or looks askant. (1872/2009: 340)

Incidentally, we note that the hunger for invisibility – to act free of the threat of others’ devaluation and aggression, to gain information about others unmolested by reputational concerns, to snoop around without being regarded as a snoop (Rockenbach & Milinsky, 2011; Dana, Weber & Kuang, Reference Dana, Weber and Kuang2007) – appears to be a human universal. Allusions to this desire can be found across time and cultures, from Plato's Ring of Gyges, Tolkien's The One Ring, Rowling's Cloak of Invisibility, Wells’ Invisible Man and Marvel Comics’ Invisible Woman, to the Daoist texts on goddess Jiutian Xuannü and Persian mythology's Khrafstra.

The idea that the shame system may be designed to evade devaluation by rendering one invisible (Tooby, personal communication) may seem odd or hyperbolic, but shame can render people invisible to audiences in the literal sense that shame operates preemptively and anticipatorily (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016, Reference Sznycer, Xygalatas, Agey, Alami, An, Ananyeva and Tooby2018), leading people to interrupt their disgraceful actions, hide, flee or destroy incriminating evidence when they perceive an audience looming. Thus, the shame system can motivate behaviour that makes invisible one's disgraceful act. However, when evading observers is impractical, the static shame ‘display’, or camouflage, may still confer some measure of invisibility, albeit to a lesser (and less literal) degree. This camouflage may be effective at interfering with the audience's attention, face-processing, identification, recognition, encoding and other information-gathering pre-requisites for devaluing wrongdoers or ‘undesirables’ (i.e. via down-regulation of welfare tradeoff ratio; see Tooby, Cosmides, Sell, Lieberman, & Sznycer, Reference Tooby, Cosmides, Sell, Lieberman and Sznycer2008; Delton & Robertson, Reference Delton and Robertson2016) and thus at interfering with the behaviours that result from that devaluation (e.g. disassociation, condemnation, banishment). The static shame ‘display’-as-camouflage may confer its producer a measure of invisibility both when occluding one's face with a top hat (see Figure 3) and in less extreme cases such as in the prototypical shame ‘display’ (Figure 2).

Figure 3. Concealment through total occlusion of the face. A. Fellig (1944). ‘In The Paddy Wagon’ (photograph by Weegee/International Center of Photography). Via Getty Images. https://www.gettyimages.com/detail/news-photo/premium-rates-apply-not-to-be-used-for-postcards-news-photo/2716706?adppopup=true

The shame system can produce invisibility in various ways: leading one to forgo actions that may result in being devalued, interrupting one's actions when detection by others is imminent, hiding, fleeing, equivocating, deceiving, justifying one's actions, and concocting other ruses for concealing oneself in plain sight. How might the static shame ‘display’, or camouflage, confer invisibility? We suggest two possible ways.

Interfering with identification

One way in which the shame camouflage could confer invisibility is by disrupting observers’ ability to identify the ashamed individual. Data exist which are consistent with this possibility. For example, observers are quicker to find faces in an array (Von Grünau & Anston, Reference Von Grünau and Anston1995) and to categorise such faces (Macrae, Hood, Milne, Rowe, & Mason, Reference Macrae, Hood, Milne, Rowe and Mason2002) when those faces have direct gaze (vs. gaze averted). Similarly, faces with gazes trained at an observer (vs. with gazes averted as in the shame display) capture more of observers’ attention (Baron-Cohen, Reference Baron-Cohen1995; Senju & Hasegawa, Reference Senju and Hasegawa2005; Frischen, Bayless, & Tipper, Reference Frischen, Bayliss and Tipper2007). Importantly, direct eye gaze, relative to gaze aversion, enhances unconscious processing of faces (Stein, Senju, Peelen, & Sterzer, Reference Stein, Senju, Peelen and Sterzer2011). Additionally, Young and colleagues (Reference Young, Slepian, Wilson and Hugenberg2014) have shown with a composite face task that neither participant accuracy nor reaction time differed across aligned and misaligned conditions for faces with averted gaze, suggesting gaze aversion interferes with configural facial processing (Young, Slepian, Wilson, & Hugenburg, 2014). Further, because the meeting of gazes creates common knowledge among gazers, gaze avoidance may also function to hamper the generation of common knowledge between the transgressor and audience regarding the transgressor's complicity (Thomas, DeScioli, & Pinker, Reference Thomas, DeScioli and Pinker2018), something that may subsequently allow transgressors to plausibly deny or dispute the facts (or others’ interpretation of the facts) of their disgraceful act (see Pinker, Nowak, & Lee, Reference Pinker, Nowak and Lee2008).

Interfering with memory encoding

Another way in which the shame camouflage could confer invisibility is by disrupting the observers’ ability to encode in memory the ashamed individual as the perpetrator of a disgraceful act. In line with this possibility, faces with direct (vs. averted) gaze are better remembered by observers (Hood, Macrae, Cole-Davies, & Dias, Reference Hood, Macrae, Cole-Davies and Dias2003; Mason et al., Reference Mason, Hood and Macrae2004; Smith, Hood, & Hector, Reference Smith, Hood and Hector2006); this effect seems to influence facial memory at both the encoding and retrieval phases (Hood et al., Reference Hood, Macrae, Cole-Davies and Dias2003). While such results are consistent with the invisibility hypothesis, more research is needed to examine how emotional expression influences facial memory. Work by Nakashima and colleagues (Reference Nakashima, Langton and Yoshikawa2012), for example, found an interactive effect of emotional expression and eye gaze on facial memory, such that angry faces were remembered less well when gaze was averted than directed, while happy faces were unaffected by gaze direction (Nakashima, Langton, & Yoshikawa, Reference Nakashima, Langton and Yoshikawa2012). Future work could explore whether the shame pose – compared with more neutral expressions – is remembered less well and/or interacts with eye gaze to influence facial memory.

While there are both anecdotal and systematic data consistent with the invisibility hypothesis, no research has yet directly tested whether the characteristic syndrome of shame actions functions (at least in part) to render shamed individuals invisible to observers – that is, to interfere with observers’ ability to identify or recall ashamed individuals and thus to devalue them. In what follows, we offer a series of questions to help guide future research on the invisibility hypothesis.

How quickly do observers identify targets who adopt the characteristic static shame pose (Figure 2) vs. a neutral pose/expression or other combinations of poses and expressions (e.g. combat readiness)? For example, Hansen and Hansen (Reference Hansen and Hansen1988) found that angry faces are more quickly picked out of a crowd of neutral or happy faces than happy or neutral faces are picked out of a crowd of angry faces (Hansen & Hansen, Reference Hansen and Hansen1988). Might the shame pose be less quickly picked out of a crowd of neutral or alternative expressions compared with non-shame emotional expressions (e.g. anger)? How quickly do observers pick out shame poses vs. neutral poses or other expressions within an array of distractors? What process or processes contribute to a possible reduction in identification speed? One candidate process is attention: how much attention does the shame pose capture relative to neutral or other emotional expressions? We know from previous research that averted gaze captures less attention than direct gaze (Baron-Cohen, Reference Baron-Cohen1995; Senju & Hasegawa, Reference Senju and Hasegawa2005), but might other features of the prototypical shame pose capture less attention than their non-shame alternatives as well? How does the shame pose influence memory? Are individuals who exhibit the shame pose recalled more infrequently than individuals who exhibit other emotional or neutral expressions? What are the corresponding rates of memory decay for individuals exhibiting these emotional expressions? And what process or processes contribute to any differences in memory decay?

The hypothesised invisibility effect of the shame pose on both memory and identification is likely to interact with observer knowledge: how would learning the identity of the culprit who committed the shame-inducing act alter observer identification of and/or memory for individuals who exhibit the shame pose relative to other emotional expressions? Learning that a shameful event has occurred but lacking knowledge of the culprit, or lacking knowledge of any shameful event occurring in first place, may also uniquely affect observer identification and/or memory for individuals exhibiting the shame pose relative to other emotional expressions. Precisely because the shame display may also function as a signal of appeasement, learning that a shameful event has occurred, but lacking knowledge of the culprit, may increase observer identification of and/or memory for individuals exhibiting the shame pose relative to other expressions. Indeed, in reactive mode, the shame system may produce a shame display designed to call attention to one's submission, coupled with characteristic verbal and nonverbal actions drawing attention to one's acceptance of lower status (e.g. saying ‘I'm sorry’). In prospective mode, however, before observers know that a transgression has occurred, the shame pose may reduce observer identification and/or memory compared with other kinds of emotional expressions. To corroborate the invisibility hypothesis, research must demonstrate reduced observer ability to identify and/or recall individuals exhibiting the shame pose relative to other emotional expressions given at least one level of observer knowledge.

According to the invisibility hypothesis, invisibility is conferred by adaptive design. This assumes that net benefits from invisibility would have accrued over deep time on average to those who adopted the shame pose in the right place at the right time in the kinds of high-coresidence, tightly knit ecologies in which our ancestors evolved. Therefore, an important test of the invisibility hypothesis is whether known community members (vs. the strangers generally used as stimuli in research) attain invisibility dividends when they adopt the shame pose. The attainment of invisibility by known community members seems less probable, because observers possess a wealth of background knowledge that can aid in identifying familiar transgressors (e.g. height, body shape, dress), and more is at stake for observers when identifying actual wrongdoers in their community compared to when identifying the fictional wrongdoing of strangers. Yet this high evidentiary bar needs to be met for the invisibility hypothesis to show viability.

Answers to these and related questions will corroborate or falsify the invisibility hypothesis.

Concluding remarks

An adaptationist approach to shame paints a unique picture of this emotion: rather than a maladaptive source of hostility and psychopathology, shame is a messenger, one that defends the individual by transmitting devaluation-relevant information to an array of countermeasures against devaluation. The information threat theory can explain many known facts about shame and generate novel predictions. Some of these have received broad support across cultures (Sznycer et al., Reference Sznycer, Tooby, Cosmides, Porat, Shalvi and Halperin2016, Reference Sznycer, Xygalatas, Agey, Alami, An, Ananyeva and Tooby2018; Durkee et al., Reference Durkee, Lukaszewski and Buss2019; Cohen et al., Reference Cohen, Chun and Sznycer2020; Sznycer & Cohen, Reference Sznycer and Cohen2021). Others, like the invisibility hypothesis, remain to be tested.

Author contributions

Mitchell Landers and Daniel Sznycer both wrote and edited this piece.

Financial support

This paper received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial or not-for-profit sectors.

Conflicts of interest

Mitchell Landers and Daniel Sznycer declare none.

References

Andrews, B., & Brewin, C. R. (1990). Attributions of blame for marital violence: A study of antecedents and consequences. Journal of Marriage and the Family, 52, 757767.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andrews, B., & Hunter, E. (1997). Shame, early abuse, and course of depression in a clinical sample: A preliminary study. Cognition & Emotion, 11(4), 373381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). The eye direction detector (EDD) and the shared attention mechanism (SAM): Two cases for evolutionary psychology. Presented at the Society for Research in Child Development Conference, New Orleans, March 1993; the British Psychological Society, Welsh Branch, ‘FacesConference, University of Wales College of Cardiff, September 1993; and the British Society for the Philosophy of Science’ Roots of Joint ReferenceConference, University of Bristol, November 1993. Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Barrett, K. C. (1998). A functionalist perspective to the development of emotions. In Mascolo, M. F. & Griffin, S. (Eds.), What develops in emotional development? (pp. 109133). Plenum.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrett, K. C., Zahn-Waxler, C., & Cole, P. M. (1993). Avoiders vs. amenders: Implications for the investigation of guilt and shame during toddlerhood? Cognition & Emotion, 7(6), 481505.Google Scholar
Baumeister, R. F. & Tice, D. M. (1990). Point–counterpoints: Anxiety and social exclusion. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology, 9, 165195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benedict, R. (1946). The chrysanthemum and the sword. Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Blanchard, R. J., & Blanchard, D. C. (1977). Aggressive behavior in the rat. Behavioral Biology, 21(2), 197224.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brown, D. E. (1991). Human universals. Temple University Press.Google Scholar
Burger, O., Baudisch, A., & Vaupel, J. W. (2012). Human mortality improvement in evolutionary context. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, USA, 109(44), 1821018214.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Carpenter, C. C. (1962). Patterns of behavior in two Oklahoma lizards. American Midland Naturalist, 67(1), 132151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cheung, M. P., Gilbert, P., & Irons, C. (2004). An exploration of shame, social rank and rumination in relation to depression. Personality and Individual Differences, 36(5), 11431153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clutton-Brock, T. (2009). Cooperation between non-kin in animal societies. Nature 462, 5157. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature08366CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cohen, A. S., Chun, R., & Sznycer, D. (2020). Do pride and shame track the evaluative psychology of audiences? Preregistered replications of Sznycer et al. (2016, 2017). Royal Society Open Science, 7, 191922.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crockett, M. J., Siegel, J. Z., Kurth-Nelson, Z., Dayan, P., & Dolan, R. J. (2017). Moral transgressions corrupt neural representations of value. Nature Neuroscience, 20(6), 879885.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Curtis, R. C., & Miller, K. (1986). Believing another likes or dislikes you: Behaviors making the beliefs come true. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51(2), 284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dana, J., Weber, R. A., & Kuang, J. X. (2007). Exploiting moral wiggle room: Experiments demonstrating an illusory preference for fairness. Economic Theory, 33(1), 6780.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, C. R. (1872/2009). The expression of emotions in man and animals. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deag, J. M. (1977). Aggression and submission in monkey societies. Animal Behaviour, 25, 465474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Hooge, I. E., Breugelmans, S. M., Wagemans, F. M., & Zeelenberg, M. (2018). The social side of shame: Approach versus withdrawal. Cognition and Emotion, 32(8), 16711677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Hooge, I. E., Breugelmans, S. M., & Zeelenberg, M. (2008). Not so ugly after all: When shame acts as a commitment device. Journal of Personal and Social Psychology, 95, 933943.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
De Hooge, I.E., Zeelenberg, M., & Breugelmans, S. (2010). Restore and protect motivations following shame. Cognition and Emotion, 24, 111127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Jong, P. J. (1999). Communicative and remedial effects of social blushing. Journal of Nonverbal Behavior, 23(3), 197217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Delton, A. W., & Robertson, T. E. (2016). How the mind makes welfare tradeoffs: Evolution, computation, and emotion. Current Opinion in Psychology, 7, 1216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dickerson, S. S., Mycek, P. J., & Zaldivar, F. (2008). Negative social evaluation, but not mere social presence, elicits cortisol responses to a laboratory stressor task. Health Psychology, 27(1), 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dimberg, U., & Öhman, A. (1983). The effects of directional facial cues on electrodermal conditioning to facial stimuli. Psychophysiology, 20(2), 160167.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Durkee, P. K., Lukaszewski, A. W., & Buss, D. M. (2019). Pride and shame: Key components of a culturally universal status management system. Evolution and Human Behavior, 40(5), 470478.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Durkee, P. K., Lukaszewski, A. W., & Buss, D. M. (2020). Psychological foundations of human status allocation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 117(35), 2123521241.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eisenberger, N. I. (2012). The pain of social disconnection: Examining the shared neural underpinnings of physical and social pain. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13(6), 421434.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eisenbruch, A. B., Grillot, R. L., Maestripieri, D., & Roney, J. R. (2016). Evidence of partner choice heuristics in a one-shot bargaining game. Evolution and Human Behavior, 37(6), 429439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elison, J., Garofalo, C., & Velotti, P. (2014). Shame and aggression: Theoretical considerations. Aggression and Violent Behavior, 19, 447453CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ermer, E. R. (2007). Coalitional support and the regulation of welfare tradeoff ratios. University of California, Santa Barbara.Google Scholar
Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2000). Cooperation and punishment in public goods experiments. American Economics Review, 90(4), 980994.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fessler, D. M. T. (2001). Emotions and cost/benefit assessment: The role of shame and self-esteem in risk taking. In Selten, R. & Gigerenzer, G. (Eds.), Bounded Rationality: The Adaptive Toolbox (pp. 191214). MIT University Press.Google Scholar
Fessler, D. M. T. (2004). Shame in two cultures: Implications for evolutionary approaches. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 4(2), 207262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fessler, D. M. T. (1999). Toward an understanding of the universality of second order emotions (Hinton, A. L., Ed., pp. 75116). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fessler, D. M. T. (2007). From appeasement to conformity: Evolutionary and cultural perspectives on shame, competition, and cooperation (Tracy, J. L., Robins, R. W., & Tangney, J. P., Eds., pp. 174193). Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Fox, M. W. (1969). The anatomy of aggression and its ritualization in Canidae: A developmental and comparative study. Behaviour, 35, 242258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frischen, A., Bayliss, A. P., & Tipper, S. P. (2007). Gaze cueing of attention: Visual attention, social cognition, and individual differences. Psychological Bulletin, 133(4), 694.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garland, H., & Brown, B. R. (1972). Face-saving as affected by subjects’ sex, audiences’ sex and audience expertise. Sociometry, 35(2), 280289.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gilbert, P. (1997). The evolution of social attractiveness and its role in shame, humiliation, guilt and therapy. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 70, 113147.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gilbert, P. (1998). What is shame? Some core issues and controversies. In Gilbert, P. & Andrews, B. (Eds.), Shame: Interpersonal behavior, psychopathology, and culture (pp. 338). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gilbert, P. (2000a). The relationship of shame, social anxiety and depression: The role of the evaluation of social rank. Clinical Psychology & Psychotherapy: An International Journal of Theory & Practice, 7(3), 174189.3.0.CO;2-U>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, P. (2000b). Social mentalities: Internal ‘social’ conflicts and the role of inner warmth and compassion in cognitive therapy. In Gilbert, P. & Bailey, K. G. (Eds.), Genes on the couch: Explorations in evolutionary psychotherapy (pp. 118150). Psychology Press.Google Scholar
Gilbert, P., & McGuire, M. T. (1998). Shame, status, and social roles: Psychobiology and evolution. In Gilbert, P. & Andrews, B. (Eds.), Shame: Interpersonal behavior, psychopathology, and culture (pp. 99125). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Giner-Sorolla, R., Castano, E., Espinosa, P., & Brown, R. (2008). Shame expressions reduce the recipient's insult from outgroup reparations. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44(3), 519526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grant, E. C., & Mackintosh, J. H. (1963). A comparison of the social postures of some common laboratory rodents. Behaviour, 21, 246259.Google Scholar
Grosenick, L., Clement, T. S., & Fernald, R. D. (2007). Fish can infer social rank by observation alone. Nature, 445(7126), 429432.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hales, A. H., Kassner, M. P., Williams, K. D., & Graziano, W. G. (2016). Disagreeableness as a cause and consequence of ostracism. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 42, 782797.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hansen, C. H., & Hansen, R. D. (1988). Finding the face in the crowd: an anger superiority effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54(6), 917.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, K., & Hurtado, A. M. (1996). Ache life history: The ecology and demography of a foraging people. De Gruyter.Google Scholar
Homayoon, D., Hiebler-Ragger, M., Zenker, M., Weger, W., Unterrainer, H., & Aberer, E. (2020). Relationship between skin shame, psychological distress and quality of life in patients with psoriasis: A pilot study. Acta Dermato-Venereologica, 100(14), 00015555-3563.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hood, B. M., Macrae, C. N., Cole-Davies, V., & Dias, M. (2003). Eye remember you: The effects of gaze direction on face recognition in children and adults. Developmental Science, 6(1), 6771.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hovannisian, R. G. (Ed.). (1986). The Armenian genocide in perspective. Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
Jackson, J. M., & Latané, B. (1981). All alone in front of all those people: Stage fright as a function of number and type of co-performers and audience. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 40(1), 73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, H., & Hill, K. (1985). Food sharing among ache foragers: Tests of explanatory hypotheses. Current Anthropology, 26, 223239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keeley, L. H. (1997). War before civilization. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Keltner, D., & Anderson, C. (2000). Saving face for Darwin. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 9(6), 187192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keltner, D., Young, R. C., & Buswell, B. N. (1997). Appeasement in human emotion, social practice, and personality. Aggressive Behavior, 23, 359374.3.0.CO;2-D>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kurzban, R., & Leary, M. R. (2001). Evolutionary origins of stigmatization: The functions of social exclusion. Psychology Bulletin, 127, 18720860CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Landers, M., Sznycer, D., & Al-Shawaf, L. (2022). Shame. In Al-Shawaf, L. & Shackelford, T. K. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of evolution and the emotions. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Larsen, R. J., & Shackelford, T. K. (1996). Gaze avoidance: Personality and social judgments of people who avoid direct face-to-face contact. Personality and Individual Differences, 21(6), 907917. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0191-8869(96)00148-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leach, C. W., & Cidam, A. (2015). When is shame linked to constructive approach orientation? A meta-analysis. Journal of Personal and Socical Psychology, 109(6), 9831002.27.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Leary, M. R. (2015). Emotional responses to interpersonal rejection. Dialogues in Clinical neuroscience, 7, 435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leary, M. R., Rapp, S. R., Herbst, K. C., Exum, M. L., & Feldman, S. R. (1998). Interpersonal concerns and psychological difficulties of psoriasis patients: Effects of disease severity and fear of negative evaluation. Health Psychology, 17(6), 530.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levi, P. (1989). The drowned and the saved. Vintage.Google Scholar
Lewis, M., Alessandri, S. M., & Sullivan, M. W. (1992). Differences in shame and pride as a function of children's gender and task difficulty. Child Development, 63(3), 630638. https://doi.org/10.2307/1131351CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lim, J. (2012). Welfare tradeoff ratios and emotions: Psychological foundations of human reciprocity. University of California, Santa Barbara.Google Scholar
Lorenz, K. (1966). On aggression. Harcourt Brace & World.Google Scholar
Lukaszewski, A. W., Lewis, D. M. G., Durkee, P. K., Sell, A. N., Sznycer, D., & Buss, D. M. (2020). An adaptationist framework for personality science. European Journal of Personality, 34, 11511174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacDonald, G., & Leary, M. R. (2005). Why does social exclusion hurt? The relationship between social and physical pain. Psychological Bulletin, 131(2), 202.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Macrae, C. N., Hood, B. M., Milne, A. B., Rowe, A. C., & Mason, M. F. (2002). Are you looking at me? Eye gaze and person perception. Psychological Science, 13(5), 460464.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Main, J. C., DeBruine, L. M., Little, A., & Jones, B. C. (2010). Interactions among the effects of head orientation, emotional expression, and physical attractiveness on face preferences. Perception, 39(1), 6271. https://doi.org/10.1068/p6503CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Martens, J. P., Tracy, J. L., & Shariff, A. F. (2012). Status signals: Adaptive benefits of displaying and observing the nonverbal expressions of pride and shame. Cognition & Emotion, 26(3), 390406.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mason, M. F., Hood, B. M., & Macrae, C. N. (2004). Look into my eyes: Gaze direction and person memory. Memory, 12, 637643.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McGlone, J. J. (1985). A quantitative ethogram of aggressive and submissive behaviors in recently regrouped pigs. Journal of Animal Science, 61(3), 556566.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Møller, G. W., Harlow, H. F., & Mitchell, G. D. (1968). Factors affecting agonistic communication in rhesus monkeys (Macaca mulatta). Behaviour, 31, 339357.Google Scholar
Mosquera, P. M., Manstead, A. S., & Fischer, A. H. (2002). The role of honour concerns in emotional reactions to offences. Cognition & Emotion, 16(1), 143163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nakashima, S. F., Langton, S. R., & Yoshikawa, S. (2012). The effect of facial expression and gaze direction on memory for unfamiliar faces. Cognition & Emotion, 26(7), 13161325.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Nishida, T. (1983). Alpha status and agonistic alliance in wild chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes schweinfurthii). Primates, 24(3), 318336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Noble, G. K., Wurm, M., & Schmidt, A. (1938). Social behavior of the black-crowned night heron. The Auk, 55(1), 740.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Notman, M. T., & Nadelson, C. C.. (1976). The rape victim: Psychodynamic considerations. The American Journal of Psychiatry, 133(4), 408413.Google ScholarPubMed
Öhman, A., & Dimberg, U. (1978). Facial expressions as conditioned stimuli for electrodermal responses: A case of ‘preparedness’? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 36(11), 12511258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereira, M. E., & Kappeler, P. M. (1997). Divergent systems of agonistic behaviour in lemurid primates. Behaviour, 134, 225274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinker, S., Nowak, M. A., & Lee, J. J. (2008). The logic of indirect speech. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 105(3), 833838.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Price, J. S., & Sloman, L. (1987). Depression as yielding behavior: An animal model based on Schjelderup-Ebbe's pecking order. Ethology and Sociobiology, 8, 8598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Proeve, M. J., & Howells, K. (2006). Effects of remorse and shame and criminal justice experience on judgements about a sex offender. Psychology, Crime & Law, 12(2), 145161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rall, M., Greenspan, A., & Neidich, E. (1984). Reactions to eye contact initiated by physically attractive and unattractive men and women. Social Behavior and Personality: An International Journal, 12(1), 103110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robertson, T. E., Sznycer, D., Delton, A. W., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2018). The true trigger of shame: Social devaluation is sufficient, wrongdoing is unnecessary. Evolution and Human Behavior, 39, 566573.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rockenbach, B., & Milinski, M. (2011). To qualify as a social partner, humans hide severe punishment, although their observed cooperativeness is decisive. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, USA, 108, 1830718312.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schaumberg, R. L., & Skowronek, S. E. (2022). Shame broadcasts social norms: The positive social effects of shame on norm acquisition and normative behavior. Psychological Science, 09567976221075303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheff, T. J. (1987). The shame–rage spiral: A case study of an interminable quarrel. In Lewis, H. B. (Ed.), The role of shame in symptom formation (pp. 109–49). Erlbaum.Google Scholar
Scherer, K. R., & Wallbott, H. G. (1994). Evidence for universality and cultural variation of differential emotion response patterning. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 66(2), 310328.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schlenker, B. R., & Leary, M. R. (1982). Social anxiety and self-presentation: A conceptualization model. Psychology Bulletin, 92, 641669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schniter, E., Sheremeta, R. M., & Sznycer, D. (2013). Building and rebuilding trust with promises and apologies. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 94, 242256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schrock, J. M., Snodgrass, J. J., & Sugiyama, L. S. (2020). Lassitude: The emotion of being sick. Evolution and Human Behavior, 41, 4457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sell, A. (2005). Regulating welfare tradeoff ratios: Three tests of an evolutionary-computational model of human anger. University of California, Santa Barbara.Google Scholar
Sell, A., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2009). Formidability and the logic of human anger. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, USA, 106(35), 1507315078.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Semin, G. R., & Manstead, A. S. R. (1982). The social implications of embarrassment displays and restitution behavior. European Journal of Social Psychology, 12, 367377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Senju, A., & Hasegawa, T. (2005). Direct gaze captures visuospatial attention. Visual Cognition, 12, 127144CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, D. (2003). The tortured, not the torturers, are ashamed. Social Research: An International Quarterly, 70(4), 11311148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shariff, A. F., Tracy, J. L., & Markusoff, J. L. (2012). (Implicitly) judging a book by its cover: The power of pride and shame expressions in shaping judgments of social status. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 38(9), 11781193. https://doi.org/10.1177/0146167212446834CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Shweder, R. (2003). Toward a deep cultural psychology of shame. Social Research: An International Quarterly, 70(4), 11091129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinclair, M. E. (1977). Agonistic behaviour of the stone crab, Menippe mercenaria (Say). Animal Behaviour, 25, 193207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sloman, L., Price, J. S., Gilbert, P., & Gardner, R. (1994). Adaptive function of depression: Psychotherapeutic implications. American Journal of Psychotherapy, 48, 401416.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Smith, A. D., Hood, B. M., & Hector, K. (2006). Eye remember you two: Gaze direction modulates face recognition in a developmental study. Developmental Science, 9(5), 465472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, J. M., & Harper, D. (2003). Animal signals. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, R. H., Webster, J. M., Parrott, W. G., & Eyre, H. L. (2002). The role of public exposure in moral and nonmoral shame and guilt. Journal of Personal and Social Psychology, 83, 13815971.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sommerville, J. A., Schmidt, M. F., Yun, J. E., & Burns, M. (2013). The development of fairness expectations and prosocial behavior in the second year of life. Infancy, 18(1), 4066.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sparrowe, R. T. (2020). LMX and welfare trade-off ratios: An evolutionary perspective on leader-member relations. The Leadership Quarterly, 31(2), 101271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, T., Senju, A., Peelen, M. V., & Sterzer, P. (2011). Eye contact facilitates awareness of faces during interocular suppression. Cognition, 119(2), 307311.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stipek, D., Recchia, S., & McClintic, S. (1992). Self-evaluation in young children. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 57(1), 100. https://doi.org/10.2307/1166190CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sugiyama, L. S. (2004). Illness, injury, and disability among Shiwiar forager–horticulturists: Implications of health-risk buffering for the evolution of human life history. American Journal of Physical Anthropology, 123, 371389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sznycer, D. (2010). Cognitive adaptations for calibrating welfare tradeoff motivations, with special reference to the emotion of shame. Doctoral dissertation (University of California, Santa Barbara).Google Scholar
Sznycer, D., & Cohen, A. S. (2021). Are emotions natural kinds after all? Rethinking the issue of response coherence. Evolutionary Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1177/14747049211016009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sznycer, D., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2017). Adaptationism carves emotions at their functional joints. Invited commentary in Psychological Inquiry, 28(1), 5662.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sznycer, D., Schniter, E., Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (2015). Regulatory adaptations for delivering information: The case of confession. Evolutionary Human Behavior, 36, 4451.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sznycer, D., Sell, A., & Lieberman, D. (2021). Forms and functions of the social emotions. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 30(4), 292299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sznycer, D., Takemura, K., Delton, A. W., Sato, K., Robertson, T., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2012). Cross-cultural differences and similarities in proneness to shame: An adaptationist and ecological approach. Evolutionary Psychology, 10(2), 147470491201000213.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sznycer, D., Tooby, J., Cosmides, L., Porat, R., Shalvi, S., & Halperin, E. (2016). Shame closely tracks the threat of devaluation by others, even across cultures. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 113, 26252630.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sznycer, D., Xygalatas, D., Agey, E., Alami, S., An, X.-F., Ananyeva, K. I., … Tooby, J. (2018). Cross-cultural invariances in the architecture of shame. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 115(39), 97029707.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tangney, J. P., Wagner, P., & Gramzow, R. (1992). Proneness to shame, proneness to guilt, and psychopathology. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 101(3), 469.Google ScholarPubMed
Thomas, K. A., DeScioli, P., & Pinker, S. (2018). Common knowledge, coordination, and the logic of self-conscious emotions. Evolutionary Human Behavior, 39(2), 179190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological foundations of culture. In Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture (pp. 19136). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (2008). The evolutionary psychology of the emotions and their relationship to internal regulatory variables. In Lewis, M., Haviland-Jones, J. M. & Barrett, L. F. (Eds.), Handbook of emotions (3rd ed., pp. 114137). Guilford.Google Scholar
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (2015). The theoretical foundations of evolutionary psychology. In Buss, D. M. (Ed.), The handbook of evolutionary psychology (2nd ed., Vol. 1: Foundations, pp. 387). John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Tooby, J., Cosmides, L., Sell, A., Lieberman, D., & Sznycer, D. (2008). Internal regulatory variables and the design of human motivation: A computational and evolutionary approach. Handbook of Approach and Avoidance Motivation, 15, 251.Google Scholar
Totten, S. (2009). Plight and fate of women during and following genocide. Transaction.Google Scholar
Tracy, J. L., & Matsumoto, D. (2008). The spontaneous expression of pride and shame: Evidence for biologically innate nonverbal displays. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 105(33), 1165511660. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0802686105CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tracy, J. L., & Robins, R. W. (2004). Putting the self into self-conscious emotions: A theoretical model. Psychological Inquiry, 15, 103125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tracy, J. L., Robins, R. W., & Schriber, R. A. (2009). Development of a FACS-verified set of basic and self-conscious emotion expressions. Emotion, 9(4), 554559. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0015766CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tzu, S. (2010). The art of war. Capstone.Google Scholar
Von Grünau, M., & Anston, C. (1995). The detection of gaze direction: A stare-in-the-crowd effect. Perception, 24(11), 12971313.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
von Rueden, C., Gurven, M., & Kaplan, H. (2008). The multiple dimensions of male social status in an Amazonian society. Evolution and Human Behavior, 29(6), 402415. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2008.05.001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Rueden, C., & Jaeggi, A. V. (2016). Men's status and reproductive success in 33 nonindustrial societies: Effects of subsistence, marriage system, and reproductive strategy. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, USA, 113(39), 1082410829.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Weisfeld, G. E., & Dillon, L. M. (2012). Applying the dominance hierarchy model to pride and shame, and related behaviors. Journal of Evolutionary Psychology, 10, 1541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, G. C. (1966). Natural selection, the costs of reproduction, and a refinement of Lack's principle. The American Naturalist, 100(916), 687690.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Witkower, Z., Mercadante, E. J., & Tracy, J. L. (2020). How affect shapes status: Distinct emotional experiences and expressions facilitate social hierarchy navigation. Current Opinion in Psychology, 33, 1822. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.copsyc.2019.06.006CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Young, S. G., Slepian, M. L., Wilson, J. P., & Hugenberg, K. (2014). Averted eye-gaze disrupts configural face encoding. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 53, 9499.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yuki, M., Schug, J., Horikawa, H., Takemura, K., Sato, K., Yokota, K., … Kamaya, K. (2007). Development of a scale to measure perceptions of relational mobility in society. (CERSS Working Paper 75). Sapporo, Japan: Center for Experimental Research in Social Sciences, Hokkaido University.Google Scholar
Zhu, R., Xu, Z., Tang, H., Liu, J., Wang, H., An, Y., Mai, X., & Liu, C. (2019). The effect of shame on anger at others: Awareness of the emotion-causing events matters. Cognition and Emotion, 33(4), 696708. https://doi.org/10.1080/02699931.2018.1489782CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Figure 0

Table 1. Hypothesised outputs of the shame system as a function of its mode of operation

Figure 1

Figure 1. Shame tracks devaluation. The intensity of anticipatory shame tracks the intensity of audience devaluation. Scatterplots A–C: data from three mass societies (adapted from Sznycer et al., 2016). The stimuli were a set of brief hypothetical scenarios describing socially devalued actions and personal characteristics. The scenarios were phrased either from the perspective of the focal individual (e.g. ‘You are not generous with others’; shame condition) or from the perspective of an observer vis-à-vis the focal individual (e.g. ‘He is not generous with others’; audience condition; between-subjects design). For each scenario, participants rated either their feeling of shame if they took those actions or had those characteristics (shame), or the degree to which they would negatively view the individual in the scenarios if the individual took those actions or had those characteristics (audience). Each point represents the mean shame rating and mean devaluation rating of one scenario. Data from (number of scenarios): A, US (29); B, India (29); C, Israel (24). Scatterplots D–R, data from 15 small-scale societies (adapted from Sznycer et al., 2018). Same experimental design, but with a set of 12 scenarios that were different from the ones used in Sznycer et al. (2016). D, Cotopaxi, Ecuador; E, Morona-Santiago, Ecuador; F, Coquimbo, Chile; G, Drâa-Tafilalet, Morocco; H, Enugu, Nigeria; I, Chalkidiki, Greece; J, Ikland, Uganda; K, Le Morne, Mauritius; L, La Gaulette, Mauritius; M, Dhading, Nepal; N, Tuva, Russia; O, Khövsgöl, Mongolia; P, Shaanxi, China; Q, Farming Communities, Japan; R, Fishing Communities, Japan. In all cases, shame ratings and devaluation ratings were given by different participants. Effect sizes: r2 linear.

Figure 2

Figure 2. Prototypical shame display. Reprinted from Martens et al. (2012), copyright (2022) by Taylor & Francis. Reprinted with permission.

Figure 3

Figure 3. Concealment through total occlusion of the face. A. Fellig (1944). ‘In The Paddy Wagon’ (photograph by Weegee/International Center of Photography). Via Getty Images. https://www.gettyimages.com/detail/news-photo/premium-rates-apply-not-to-be-used-for-postcards-news-photo/2716706?adppopup=true