Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-ckgrl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-15T21:45:30.107Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Cyborg Turn in Law?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Abstract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

This Article deploys cybernetic theory to argue that a novel legal impact imaginary has emerged. In this imaginary, the subjects of legal interventions are performed and enacted as cybernetic organisms, that is, as entities that process information and adapt to changes in their environment. This Article, then, argues that in this imaginary, law finds its effectiveness—not by threatening, cajoling, educating, and moralizing humans as before, but by affecting the composition of cybernetic organisms, giving rise to new kinds of legal subjects that transcend the former conceptual boundary between humans and non-humans, or persons and things. The cybernetic interventions work to change the cyborgs' behavioral responses, thus giving law a new kind modality of power. This Article develops a model for understanding cyborg regulation through case studies and argues that cyborg regulation deploys three distinct strategies. Cyborgs can be controlled through affecting the informational inputs the entities receive, through agencement practices that intervene in the material constitution of the cyborg cognitions, and, finally, by psycho-morphing humans to make them useful components of the cyborg cognitive machineries. The Article ends with a discussion of the theoretical implications of the transition to the cyborg imaginary.

Type
Special Issue Traditions, Myths, and Utopias of Personhood
Copyright
Copyright © 2017 by German Law Journal, Inc. 

References

1 See generally 1 Friedrich Carl von Savigny, System des heutigen römischen Rechts 331–34 (1840).Google Scholar

2 See generally Posner, Richard A., Economic analysis of law (2014).Google Scholar

3 On the Whanganui River personhood dispute, see Hsiao, Elaine C., New Zealand Whanganui River Agreement, 42 Env. Pol'y & L. 371 (2012).Google Scholar

4 Citizens United v. Fed. Election Comm'n, 558 U.S. 310 (2010).Google Scholar

5 The case studies include Finnish gender equality plans under the Finnish Gender Equality Act, see 609/1986 Laki naisten ja miesten välisestä tasa-arvosta [Law on Equality Between Men and Women, Gender Equality Act] (Fin.), nudging, and two different banking regulation schemes.Google Scholar

6 See infra Section D.III.1.Google Scholar

7 For recent accounts, see Schauer, Frederick, The force of law (2015); Shapiro, Scott J., Legality (2011); Mc, Richard H.Adams, The Expressive Powers of Law: Theories and Limits (2015).Google Scholar

8 On the constant and failing boundary work required to sustain the distinction between nature and culture, see Latour, Bruno, We Have Never Been Modern (1993).Google Scholar

9 On the command model of law, see Postema, Gerald J., Law as Command: The Model of Command in Modern Jurisprudence, 11 Philos. Issues 470 (2001); Mark Greenberg, The Standard Picture and Its Discontents, 1 Oxford Stud. Phil. L. 39 (2011).Google Scholar

10 See also Schauer, supra note 7, at 93–109 (arguing that the threat of sanction and coercion of obedience are the characteristic signifiers of all modern law).Google Scholar

11 Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation Oxford: Clarendon Press 1907 at I.1 (1789).Google Scholar

12 See generally Becker, Gary S., Nobel Lecture: The Economic Way of Looking at Behavior, 101 J. Polit. Econ. 385 (1993). The beauty of the theory is that it can be applied even if demonstrably faulty as an empirical description, see Becker, Gary S., Irrational Behavior and Economic Theory, 70 J. Polit. Econ. 1 (1962).Google Scholar

13 Williamson, Oliver E., The Economic Institutions of Capitalism 4445 (1985).Google Scholar

14 Thaler, Richard H., From Homo Economicus to Homo Sapiens, 14 J. Econ. Persp. 133 (2000).Google Scholar

15 Stiglitz, Joseph E., Information and the Change in the Paradgm Economics, 92 Am. Econ. Rev. 460 (2002).Google Scholar

16 See, e.g., Steffen Andersen et al., Lost in State Space: Are References Stable?, 49 Int'l Econ. Rev. 1091 (2008).Google Scholar

17 For a general overview, see P. H. Robinson & Darley, John M., Does Criminal Law Deter? A Behavioural Science Investigation, 24 Oxford J. Leg. Stud. 173 (2004).Google Scholar

18 The imaginary seems to have received relatively little attention in Anglophone countries, see, e.g., generally Kenworthey Bilz et al., law, Psychology, and Morality, 101–31 (2009); Eyal Zamir et al., Law, Moral Attitudes, and Behavioral Change, Oxford Handbook of Behav. Econ. & L. (Eyal Zamir & Doron Teichman eds., 2014). It has, however, received more attention, for example in the Nordic countries, in regards to criminal law, see Tapani, Jussi & Tolvanen, Matti, Rikosoikeuden yleinen osa: vastuuoppi 43–45 (2nd rev. ed. 2013).Google Scholar

19 Habitual obedience, where people's submission gains a “unreflective, effortless, engrained character of a habit,” H. L. A. Hart, The concept of law 51–54 (2nd ed. 1994), is one version of the moral-creating effect of law.Google Scholar

20 McAdams provides the most sophisticated account of law's causal pathways. In his account, law serves an expressive, coordinating function, allowing humans to coordinate and homogenize their expectations, but it ultimately converges back on self-interested individual's calculations. See McAdams, supra note 7 passim.Google Scholar

21 See generally Shavell, Steven, Law versus Morality as Regulators of Conduct, 4 Am. L. Econ. Rev. 227 (2002); Jon Elster, Social Norms and Economic Theory, in Culture & Pol. 363 (Lane Crothers & Charles Lockhart eds., 2000); Buckholtz, Joshua W. & René Marois, The roots of modern justice: Cognitive and neural foundations of social norms and their enforcement, 15 Nat. Neurosci. 655 (2012).Google Scholar

22 In particular, feminist, black studies, and postcolonial studies scholars have argued that this may be an illusion and that legal normative power is, in fact, complicit in producing its subjects. The critics have pointed out that law frames issues, creates social institutions, sustains categorical boundaries and structures, and, most importantly, like other powerful discourses, offers subjectifiers that people can use to subjectify themselves. See, e.g., Lacey, Nicola, The Constitution of Identity: Gender, Feminist Legal Theory, and the Law and Society Movement, Blackwell Companion to L. & Soc'y 471 (Austin Sarat ed., 2004); Kimberlé Williams Crenshaw, Race, Reform, and Retrenchment: Transformation and Legitimation in Antidiscrimination Law, 101 Harv. L. Rev. 1331 (1988); Efrén Rivera Ramos, The Legal Construction of Identity: The Judicial and Social Legacy of American Colonialism in Puerto Rico (2001). The accounts have typically been inspired by the work of Michel Foucault and Judith Butler, see, e.g., Foucault, Michel, Technologies of the self, Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth 223–52 (1997); Judith Butler, The Psychic Life of Power: Theories in Subjection Theories in Subjection (1997).Google Scholar

23 See, e.g., Shavell, supra note 21.Google Scholar

24 Nick Bostrom, A History of Transhumanist Thought, 1 J. Evol. Techl. 1 (2005).Google Scholar

25 Nick Bostrom & Anders Sandberg, Cognitive Enhancement: Methods, Ethics, Regulatory Challenges, 15 Sci. Eng. Ethics 311.Google Scholar

26 M. J. McNamee & S. D. Edvards, Transhumanism, medical technology and slippery slopes, 32 J. Med. Ethics 513 (2006); Allen e. Buchanan, Beyond humanity? The Ethics of Biomedical Enhancement (2011).Google Scholar

27 Nick Bostrom, Superintelligence. Paths, Dangers, Strategies ch. 9 (2014).Google Scholar

28 Donna Haraway, A Cyborg Manifesto: Science, Technology and Socialist-Femenism in the Late Twentiety Century, in Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature 149 (1991).Google Scholar

29 Bernard Stiegler, Technics and time, 1: The fault of Epimetheus (1998).Google Scholar

30 For an early musical exploration of the theme, listen to Kraftwerk, Die Mensch-Maschine (Capital records, 1974).Google Scholar

31 N. Katherine Hayles, Flesh and Metal: Reconfiguring the Mindbody in Virtual Environments, 10 Configurations 297 (2002); Rosi Braidotti, The posthuman (2013); Andy Clark, Natural-born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence (2003). Compare with Jannice Käll's chapter in this volume, 18 German L.J. (2017).Google Scholar

32 Norbert Wiener, The Human Use of Human Beings (1974). See also generally Pickering, Andrew, The Cybernetic Brain: Sketches of Another Future (2010) (discussing the early British cybernetics thinkers).Google Scholar

33 N. Katherine Hayles, How we became posthuman ch. 1 (1999); Jean-Pierre Dupuy, On the Origins of Cognitive Science (2009); Jean-Pierre Dupuy, The Mechanization of the Mind (2000); Orit Halpern, Cybernetic rationality, 15 Distinction Scand. J. Soc. Theory 223 (2014).Google Scholar

34 See, e.g., Sandberg, A., Feasibility of Whole Brain Emulation, 5 Philos. Theory Artif. Intell. 251, 262 (2013) (arguing that the whole brain emulation has no “fundamental obstacles” but only requires “a large amount of engineering and research”); Nick Bostrom, Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies 35–43 (2014).Google Scholar

35 For an early jurisprudential deployment of the idea, see Taylor, Serge, Making Bureaucracies Think (1984) (arguing that the environmental statements were introduced to forge a particular bureaucratic way of thinking).Google Scholar

36 On micro- and macrocognitions, see Klein, Gary & Wright, Corinne, Macrocognition: From Theory to Toolbox, 7 Front. Psychol. 54 (2016).Google ScholarPubMed

37 A key template for the argument can be found in Philip Mirowski's history of post-World War II US economic thought, see Mirowski, Philip, Machine dreams: economics becomes a cyborg science (2002).Google Scholar

38 See infra at Section D.II.Google Scholar

39 See infra at Section D.III.Google Scholar

40 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, International Convergence of Capital Measurement and Capital Standards: A Revised Framework – Comprehensive Version Part III, http://www.bis.org/publ/bcbs128.htm (2006).Google Scholar

41 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, Enhancements to the Basel II framework, http://www.bis.org/publ/bcbs157.htm (2009).Google Scholar

42 Financial Conduct Authority, FCA Handbook COCON, https://www.handbook.fca.org.uk/handbook/COCON/2/?date=2016-06-30.Google Scholar

43 See infra at Section D.III.Google Scholar

44 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 40, at Part III.Google Scholar

45 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 41, at 9–27.Google Scholar

46 On the history of the Basel Accords, see C. A. E. Goodhart, The Basel Committee on Banking Supervision: A History of the Early Years, 19741997 (2011); Tarullo, Daniel K., Banking on Basel: The Future of International Financial Regulation (2008).Google Scholar

47 On the theoretical underpinnings, see, e.g., Joao A. C. Santos, Bank Capital Regulation in Contemporary Banking Theory: A Review of the Literature, 10 Fin. Mark. Institutions Instruments 41 (2001); David Miles, Jing Yang & Gilberto Marcheggiano, Optimal Bank Capital, 123 Econ. J. 1 (2013).Google Scholar

48 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 40, § 720.Google Scholar

49 Id. § 732–42.Google Scholar

50 The process in which the systems are built is also an agencement process. I will discuss agencement in more detail below in Section D.III, but in relation to the ICAAP risk measurement systems.Google Scholar

51 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 40, at § 452–53.Google Scholar

52 Id. § 462.Google Scholar

53 Id. § 416.Google Scholar

54 Id. § 447.Google Scholar

55 On methodologies available at the time Basel II was designed, see, e.g., Crouhy, Michel, Dan Galai & Robert Mark, A Comparative Analysis of Current Credit Risk Models, 24 J. Bank. & Fin. 59 (2000).Google Scholar

56 Michel Callon, Why Virtualism Paves the Way to Political Impotence: A Reply to to Daniel Miller's Critique of the Laws of the Markets, 6 Econ. Soc. Eur. Electronic Newsl. 3 (2005).Google Scholar

57 Michel Callon, Economic Markets and the Rise of Interactive Agencements: From Prosthetic Agencies to Habilitated Agencies, in Living in a Material World 28 (Trevor Pinch & Richard Swedberg eds., 2008).Google Scholar

58 callon, supra note 56, at 4.Google Scholar

59 See, e.g., Clark, supra note 31.Google Scholar

60 Iain Hardie & Donald MacKenzie, Assembling an Economic Actor: The Agencement of a Hedge Fund, 55 Soc. Rev. 57 (2007). For other deployments, see Swanton, Dan, The Steel Plant as Assemblage, 44 Geoforum 282 (2013); Cédric Calvignac & Franck Cochoy, From “Market Agencement” to “Vehicular Agencies”: Insights from the Quantitative Observation of Consumer Logistics, 19 Consum. Mark. Cult. 133–147 (2016); Luis Araujo & Hans Kjellberg, Enacting Novel Agencements: The Case of Frequent Flyer Schemes in the US Airline Industry (1981–1991), 19 Consum. Mark. Cult. 92 (2015); Thomas Lemke, New Materialisms: Foucault and the “Government of Things,” 32 Theory, Cult. & Soc. 3 (2015); Philip Roscoe, Economic Embeddedness and Materiality in a Financial Market Setting, 61 Soc. Rev. 41 (2013).Google Scholar

61 Callon himself also pointed out that “[a]gency … can be attributed to heterogeneous and unexpected entities which are not necessarily human beings ('”the French economy“’ that creates unemployment; ‘”biotechnology“’ which generates ethical problems; ‘”genes“’ which are said to cause severe diseases and/or impairments).” Callon, supra note 56, at 4.Google Scholar

62 Hardie & MacKenzie, supra note 60, at 75–76.Google Scholar

63 Callon, supra note 56, at 4.Google Scholar

64 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 40, § 728–30.Google Scholar

65 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 41, at 12–15.Google Scholar

66 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 40, § 728.Google Scholar

67 Id. § 730.Google Scholar

68 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 41, at 14.Google Scholar

69 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 40, § 397.Google Scholar

70 See e.g., id. at § 688.Google Scholar

71 On the state-of-play in Europe, see, e.g., Joana Sousa Lourenco et al., Behavioural Insights Applied to Policy: European Report 2016 (2016).Google Scholar

72 For a sample of countless articles, see, e.g., Cass R Sunstein, Nudging and Choice Architecture: Ethical Considerations, Yale J. on Reg. 1 (2014); Andreas Kapsner & Barbara Sandfuchs, Nudging as a Threat to Privacy, 6 Rev. Phil. Psychol. 455 (2015); Jeff King & Christopher McCrudden, The Dark Side of Nudging: The Ethics, Political Economy, and Law of Libertarian Paternalism, Choice Architecture in Democracies: Exploring the Legitimacy of Nudging 75 (Alexandra Kemmerer et al. eds., 2016); T. M. Wilkinson, Nudging and Manipulation, 61 Pol. Stud. 341 (2013); Pelle Guldborg Hansen & Andreas Maal&;e Jespersen, Nudge and the Manipulation of Choice, 1 Eur. J. Risk Reg. 3 (2013).Google Scholar

73 On a critique of the “Third Way” political program of nudging, see, e.g., Pierre Schlag, Nudge, Choice Architecture, and Libertarian Paternalism, 108 Mich. Law Rev. 913 (2010).Google Scholar

74 A legal framework for understanding and evaluating nudging is still largely missing. See, e.g., Alberto Alemanno & Alessandro Spina, Nudging Legally: On the Checks and Balances of Behavioral Regulation, 12 Int. J. Const. Law 429 (2014).Google Scholar

75 Thaler, Richard H. & Sunstein, Cass R., Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness 6 (2008).Google Scholar

76 Robert Baldwin, From Regulation to Behaviour Change: Giving Nudge the Third Degree, 77 Mod. L. Rev. 831, 833 (2014).Google Scholar

77 Thaler & Sunstein, supra note 75, at 56–60.Google Scholar

78 The results of appropriate default choice architecture are sometimes striking. Studies have, for example, shown that people enroll in organ donor programs in great numbers if the enrolment is an opt-out choice on a driver's license application form, while the enrolment rate is much lower if people are required to tick a box to opt in on the very same form. On default choice nudges, see, e.g., Sunstein, Cass R., Deciding by Default, 162 Univ. PA. L. Rev. 1 (2013).Google Scholar

79 Healthy snacks, for example, can be placed close to typical routes and easily visible in stores or in academic conferences, while the unhealthy ones are stacked in hard-to-find places. See, e.g., Ida Kongsbak et al., Increasing Fruit and Vegetable Intake Among Male University Students in an Ad Libitum Buffet Setting: A Choice Architectural Nudge Intervention, 49 Food Qualty & Preference 183 (2016).Google Scholar

80 Gharad Bryan, Dean Karlan & Scott Nelson, Commitment Devices, 2 Annu. Rev. Econ. 671–98 (2010).Google Scholar

81 Baldwin, supra note 76, at 843.Google Scholar

82 For an introduction, see Kahneman, Daniel, Thinking, Fast and Slow (2011). Surprisingly, the neuroscientific foundations and explanations of nudging still seem somewhat fuzzy. See Gidon Felsen & Reiner, Peter B., What Can Neuroscience Contribute to the Debate Over Nudging?, 6 Rev. Phil. Psychol. 469 (2015).Google Scholar

83 Bruno Latour, Reassembling the social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory 204–06 (2005).Google Scholar

86 Id.B Google Scholar

87 The relationship between nudging and psycho-morphing is fraught as there seems good reason to think that the rational Econs, in particular, are cultural constructs. The Econs' rationality can only be imprinted on the Humans with the help of countless years of education and training, that is, psycho-morphing and material agencement.Google Scholar

88 Bruno Latour, How to Talk About the Body? the Normative Dimension of Science Studies, 10 Body Soc. 205 (2004).Google Scholar

89 Id. at 207.Google Scholar

90 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 40, § 729.Google Scholar

91 Basel Committee on Banking Supervision, supra note 41, at 13.Google Scholar

92 For contributions to the discussion, see, e.g,. Getting the Culture and the Ethics Right: Towards a New Age of Responsibility in Banking and Finance (Kenadjian, Patrick S. & Andreas Dombret eds., 2016); Justin O'Brien, Fixing the Fix: Governance, Culture, Ethics and the Extending Perimeter of Financial Regulation, 8 L. Fin. Mark. Rev. 373 (2014); Alison Lui, Greed, Recklessness and/or Dishonesty? An Investigation into the Culture of Five UK Banks between 2004 and 2009, 16 J. Bank. Reg. 106 (2015); Group of Thirty, Banking Conduct and Culture. a Call for Sustained and Comprehensive Reform, group30.org (2015); Michael Power, Simon Ashby & Tommaso Palermo, Risk Culture in Financial Organisations: a Research Report (2013).Google Scholar

93 Financial Conduct Authority, supra note 42, at COCON.Google Scholar

94 See Dunkley, Emma, “Banker Bashing” Draws to an End as Watchdog Scraps Review, Financial Times, December 31, 2015, at 1.Google Scholar

95 Financial Conduct Authority, supra note 42, at COCON 2.1.Google Scholar

96 Id. at COCON 4.Google Scholar

97 Id. at COCON 3.1.1.Google Scholar

98 F. Patrick Hubbard, Do Androids Dream: Personhood and Intelligent Artifacts, 83 Temp. L. Rev. 405 (2010); Wendell Wallach, From Robots to Techno Sapiens: Ethics, Law and Public Policy in the Development of Robotics and Neurotechnologies, 3 L. Innov. Tech. 185 (2011); Solum, Lawrence B., 70 Legal Personhood for Artificial Intelligences, N.C. L. Rev. 1231 (1994.Google Scholar

99 On management-based regulation and its close sibling, meta-regulation, see, e.g., Parker, Christine, The open corporation: Effective Self-regulation and Democracy (2002); Christine Parker, Meta-regulation: Legal Accountability for Corporate Social Responsibility, in The New Corporate Accountability: Corporate Social Responsibility and the Law 207 (Doreen McBarnet, Aurora Voiculescu, & Tom Campbell eds., 2007); Cary Coglianese & David Lazer, Management-Based Regulation: Prescribing Private Management to Achieve Public Goals, 37 L. Soc. Rev. 691 (2003); Cary Coglianese & Evan Mendelson, Meta-Regulation and Self-Regulation (2010); Mia Mahmudur Rahim, Legal Regulation of Corporate Social Responsibility: a Meta-regulation Approach of Law for Raising CSR in a Weak Economy (2013); Neil Gunningham & Darren Sinclair, Organizational Trust and the Limits of Management-Based Regulation, 43 L. Soc. Rev. 865 (2009).Google Scholar

100 Coglianese & Mendelson, supra note 99, at 150.Google Scholar

101 Fiona Haines, Regulatory Failures and Regulatory Solutions: A Characteristic Analysis of the Aftermath of Disaster, 34 L. Soc. Inq. 31, 31, 35 (2009).Google Scholar

102 Parker, supra note 99, at 212, 235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

103 Gunningham & Sinclair, supra note 99, at 866.Google Scholar

104 The continuing human hegemony is clearly visible in, for example, Christopher Stone's argument; things can be subject to law in the sense of having a standing, rights, and a guardian to sue in their name. See Stone, Christopher D., Should Trees have standing? (2010).Google Scholar

105 See Schlag, Pierre, The Aesthetics of American Law, 115 Harv. L. R. 1047, 1107–09 (2002). Compare also with Selkälä & Rajavuori chapter in this volume, 18 German L.J. (2017).Google Scholar

106 Schlag, supra note 105, at 1110.Google Scholar

107 For a similar argument, see Hildebrandt, Mireille, Smart Technologies and the End(s) of Law: Novel Entanglements of Law and Technology 217–19 (2015).Google Scholar

108 Luhmann's account of law's binary nature is probably best known. Niklas Luhmann, Law as a Social System 9091 (2005).Google Scholar