Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T11:14:06.536Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

In Search of a First-Person Plural, Second-Best Theory of Constitutional Interpretation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

The purpose of this paper is not to argue for a particular approach to constitutional interpretation, but to map the domain thereof and clarify the requirements that an adequate theory of the subject must meet. A comprehensive constitutional theory has to address both how and by whom a given constitution should be interpreted. While everyone admits that these two issues are not entirely unrelated, many constitutional theorists presume that a theory of constitutional interpretation can usefully insulate these two questions. The argument is that once we have answered the question of who will interpret the constitution and we have made a decision on institutional design, we can then focus our efforts on the proper method of interpretation. Although I do not deny that the two questions can be analytically separated, my contention is that a theory of constitutional interpretation focusing only on the how question is wholly inadequate.

Type
Part A: Political Theory and Constitutional Reasoning
Copyright
Copyright © 2013 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 See, e.g., Sotirios A. Barber & James E. Fleming, Constitutional Interpretation: The Basic Questions xv–xvi (2007); Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire 370 (1986) [hereinafter Law's Empire].Google Scholar

2 Ronald Dworkin, , Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution 1–38 (1997) [hereinafter Freedom's Law].Google Scholar

4 For an account of these theories as attempts to put forward amoral methods of interpretation, see Barber & Fleming, supra note 1, at 65.Google Scholar

5 Scalia, Antonin, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. Cin. L. Rev. 849, 864 (1989).Google Scholar

6 Bork, Robert H., The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law 146 (First Touchstone ed. 1991).Google Scholar

7 Kyllo v. United States, 533 U.S. 27 (2001).Google Scholar

8 See, e.g., Keith E. Whittington, The New Originalism, 2 Geo.J.L. & Pub.Pol'y 599, 611 (2004) (“[O]riginalists should explicitly admit: interpretation requires judgment. It is not a mechanical process, and interpretive results cannot be rigidly determined.”).Google Scholar

9 For a criticism of this argument, see Andrew B. Coan, Irrelevance of Writtenness in Constitutional Interpretation, 158 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1025 (2010).Google Scholar

10 See Whittington, , supra note 8, at 612. But see Bork, supra note 6 at 177; Scalia, supra note 5 at 862.Google Scholar

11 Thayer, James B., The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law, 7 Harv. L. Rev. 129 (1893).Google Scholar

12 Dworkin, Freedom's Law, supra note 2, at 2.Google Scholar

14 Id. at 10.Google Scholar

15 Rawls, John, Political Liberalism 54–58 (1993).Google Scholar

16 This distinction is similar to the one made by Jeremy Waldron between first-order and second-order values; but, because this terminology could be confused with the first-best/second-best distinction that is central to section B. III., I use different terminology to avoid confusion. See Jeremy Waldron, Law and Disagreement 196 (1999).Google Scholar

17 Dworkin, , Law's Empire, supra note 1, at 370.Google Scholar

19 Thayer, , supra note 11.Google Scholar

20 See Sunstein, Cass R., Foreword: Leaving Things Undecided, 110 Harv. L. Rev. 4 (1996) [hereinafter Leaving Things Undecided]; Cass R. Sunstein, Burkean Minimalism, 105 Mich.L. Rev. 353 (2006) [hereinafter Burkean Minimalism]; Cass R. Sunstein, Second-Order Perfectionism, 75 Fordham L. Rev. 2867 (2007) [hereinafter Second-Order].Google Scholar

21 See Sunstein, , Leaving Things Undecided, supra note 20, at 15–25.Google Scholar

22 Joseph, Raz, Practical Reason and Norms 35–48 (1990).Google Scholar

23 See Barber & Fleming, supra note 1, at 29.Google Scholar

24 Dworkin, , Law's Empire, supra note 1.Google Scholar

25 Dworkin, Ronald, Equality, Democracy, and Constitution: We the People in Court, 28 Alta. L. Rev. 324 (1990); Dworkin, Ronald, The Partnership Conception of Democracy, 86 Calif. L. Rev. 453 (1998); Dworkin, , Freedom's Law, supra note 2.Google Scholar

26 Dworkin, Ronald, The Forum of Principle, 56 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 469 (1981).Google Scholar

27 See Primus, Richard A., When Should Original Meanings Matter, 107 Mich. L. Rev. 165 (2008).Google Scholar

28 Id. at 172.Google Scholar

29 See Sunstein, Cass R. & Vermeule, Adrian, Interpretation and Institutions, 101 Mich. L. Rev. 885 (2003).Google Scholar

30 See Vermeule, Adrian, Judging Under Uncertainty: An Institutional Theory of Legal Interpretation 63–85 (2006); Sunstein, & Vermeule, , supra note 29, at 886.Google Scholar

31 Sunstein, & Vermeule, , supra note 29, at 914–15.Google Scholar

32 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 13.Google Scholar

33 Vermeule, , supra note30, at 2; Sunstein & Vermeule, supra note 29, at 915–19.Google Scholar

34 Sunstein, Cass R., Five Theses on Originalism, 19 Harv. J. L. & Pub. Pol'y 311, 311 (1996).Google Scholar

35 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 45.Google Scholar

36 Id. at 237.Google Scholar

37 Id. at 3.Google Scholar

38 Vermeule, Adrian, Law and the Limits of Reason 8 (2009); Waldron, Jeremy, The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review, 115 Yale L. J. 1346, 1373–74 (2006).Google Scholar

39 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 5.Google Scholar

40 Waldron, , supra note 38, at 1372–73.Google Scholar

41 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 3.Google Scholar

42 See Ackerman, Bruce, We the People: Foundations (1993).Google Scholar

43 Id. at 6–16.Google Scholar

44 Id. at 12.Google Scholar

45 For Ackerman's hypothetical case about the anti-establishment clause, see id. at 14.Google Scholar

46 Id. at 15.Google Scholar

47 Id. at 14Google Scholar

48 Id. at 14–15.Google Scholar

50 I remain agnostic on the question of whether the text should impose an absolute limit on interpretation. One could argue that the very concept of constitutional interpretation makes sense only if the text draws the outer limits of possible interpretations. Others hold the opinion that while the text is important, it does not impose absolute limits on interpretation. For a conventionalist explanation of the importance of the text, see David A. Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, 63 U. Chi. L. Rev. 877, 906–25 (1996).Google Scholar

51 For a sophisticated defense of procedural democracy, see Richard Bellamy, Political Constitutionalism: A Republican Defence of the Constitutionality of Democracy (2007).Google Scholar

52 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 4. Though, I should emphasize that Vermeule does not defend formalism on procedural grounds.Google Scholar

53 Bork, , supra note 6, at 146.Google Scholar

54 See, e.g., Whittington, supra note 8, at 609 (“Others are clear that a commitment to originalism is distinct from a commitment to judicial deference and that originalism may often require the active exercise of the power of judicial review in order to keep faith with the principled commitments of the founding. The new originalism does not require judges to get out of the way of legislatures. It requires judges to uphold the original Constitution—nothing more, but also nothing less.”).Google Scholar

55 Primus, , supra note 27, at 188.Google Scholar

56 I will set aside the possibility that originalism is conceptually incoherent. For a general overview of the debate, see Daniel A. Farber, The Originalism Debate: A Guide for the Perplexed, 49 Ohio St. L. J. 1085 (1989).Google Scholar

57 Primus, , supra note 27, at 192–202.Google Scholar

58 Id. at 195–99.Google Scholar

59 Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously 135 (1977).Google Scholar

60 Vermeule, , supra note 38, at 70.Google Scholar

61 Id. at 92.Google Scholar

62 Id. at 82.Google Scholar

63 Myers v. United States, 272 U.S. 52 (1926).Google Scholar

64 Scalia, , supra note 5, at 852.Google Scholar

65 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 16, 2729, 242–43.Google Scholar

66 Dworkin, , Freedom's Law, supra note 2, at 7.Google Scholar

67 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 1.Google Scholar

68 Id. at 150.Google Scholar

69 Vermeule, , supra note 38, at 90.Google Scholar

70 Vermeule, , supra note 30, at 265.Google Scholar

71 For such a position, see Bellamy, supra note 51, at 98.Google Scholar

72 Although Vermeule tackles the allocation of burden of proof, his account remains within the consequentialist paradigm, and does not give weight to process-related reasons. See Vermeule, supra note 30, at 153–54, 169–71.Google Scholar

73 Rawls, , supra note 15, at 139–40.Google Scholar

74 Gaus, Gerald F., Contemporary Theories of Liberalism: Public Reason as a Post-Enlightenment Project 214 (2003).Google Scholar

75 Rawls, , supra note 15, at 12.Google Scholar

76 For the idea that the task of government is to keep track of our publicly justified principles, see Gerald F. Gaus, Justificatory Liberalism: An Essay on Epistemology and Political Theory 184–91 (1996).Google Scholar

77 Rawls, , supra note 15, at 54–58.Google Scholar

78 Gaus, See,supra note 76, at 230.Google Scholar