Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-21T17:13:27.397Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Religious Education in Germany in Light of Religious Diversity: Constitutional Requirements for Religious Education

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 October 2019

Abstract

In Article 7, paragraph 3, the German Constitution provides that religious education shall be a part of the curriculum of public school. This is one of the three approaches of dealing with religious education existing today. Originally, religious education as a regular subject at public schools in Germany was only offered by the two Christian Churches—Catholic and Protestant. As the number of Christians decreased and the number of Muslims increased, the demand for Islamic religious education at public schools grew. Therefore, the question arose whether the constitutional law concerning religion is capable of facing the new challenges of religious diversity. This Article tries to answer this question with regard to the introduction of Islamic religious education as a measure of adaptiveness. In the first step, the requirements of Article 7, paragraph 3 of the Constitution posed to religious education will be outlined in order to be able to examine in the second step whether Islamic religious education may be introduced at public schools as a regular subject. In this regard, the issue of the qualification of an umbrella association as a religious society and the constitutionality of the advisory board model will be discussed.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s) 2019. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the German Law Journal

A. Introduction

Education touches upon the core of a state’s foundational values. Religious education, as an aspect of education, raises crucial questions about the purpose of education in shaping individual identity, character, and conscientious beliefs,Footnote 1 and is “one of the ‘battlefields’ between religion and certain ideologies or political streams.”Footnote 2 It implicates a range of constitutional rights, including the rights of children to education, the child’s right to freedom of religion or belief, and rights of parents and legal guardians to ensure their child is educated in conformity with their own convictions. Where minorities are involved, religious education can also emerge as a point of contention for ensuring the accommodation of minorities. Furthermore, religious education may also become a contested area in vindicating the proper constitutional arrangement between state and religion. These issues and more are also reflected in how the German state has addressed religious education over the years.

According to Article 7, paragraph 3 of the German Constitution,Footnote 3 religious education shall be part of the curriculum of public schools and, indeed, has been part of it for the last seventy years since the German Constitution came into existence. Prior to that, a corresponding rule had also been included in the 1919 Constitution of the Weimar Republic.Footnote 4 Such religious education has typically been taught in a denominational way, in other words, in accordance with the principles laid down by the relevant religious society. This constitutional choice that religious education shall be part of the curriculum of public schools is neither historically mandatory nor, compared to other European countries, self-evident. During medieval times, the education system in Europe was solely organized by the Christian church, but it was focused on the training of clergy.Footnote 5 General education—such as the teaching of values, standards, vocational skills, and abilities—was mainly done by one’s own family and social class. A formal education was not available for everyone at that time.Footnote 6 This changed with the French Revolution in 1789, in which various nations modified their relationship between church and state, and thus also the understanding of religious education.Footnote 7 Jean-Jacques Rousseau had a significant impact on the development in France: He claimed in The Social Contract that a “religion civile” had to be created for which the state was solely responsible.Footnote 8 In the course of these events, the Prussian state established the “Prussian Common Law” in 1794, which institutionalized schools as a part of the state and mandated public education for its citizens.Footnote 9 Thus, one can notice a shift of education in general from the church, family, and social environment to the state. Furthermore, religious education also shifted increasingly to the schools since the nineteenth century. This is due to the fact that schooling became compulsory.Footnote 10 In connection with the Enlightenment, the state attempted to separate itself from church and social class structures in order to realize the principles of freedom and equality. In the Prussian State, this led to the quite radical educational approach that children should be shielded from their parents so that they wouldn’t be shaped by their social background and environment.Footnote 11 Therefore, in the Prussian Constitution of 1850, the only right parents had was bringing their children to school.Footnote 12 On the contrary, the church did not adhere to this position and argued that the parent’s rights superseded the state law, and thus the state’s monopoly on education as well.Footnote 13 The confrontation between church and state ended in the so-called Kulturkampf.Footnote 14 The state tried to radically push back the influence of the Church in all areas, but did not succeed in the end. The Church retained its position. Nonetheless, some changes lasted, such as the limitation of the Church’s supervision of schools.Footnote 15 Clergymen were still local school inspectors, but the next highest supervision was transferred to state officials.Footnote 16

In the Weimar Constitution, the balance between church and state was further settled in the so-called Kulturkompromiss.Footnote 17 On the one hand, school supervision by the Church was finally completely abandoned, and thus the separation of church and state in principle was established.Footnote 18 On the other hand, parental rights, as proclaimed by the church, were emphasized.Footnote 19 Moreover, both the Catholic and Lutheran churches were allowed to hold religious education classes in public schools according to their own denominational understanding. Under Article 146 paragraph, 2 of the Weimar Constitution,Footnote 20 denominational schools could even be established at the request of parents—the so-called Weimar School compromise.Footnote 21 The German Constitution adopted more or less the same arrangements, but with the slight modification that the guarantee for denominational schools wasn’t adopted.Footnote 22 As a compromise, the importance of denominational religious education at school was stressed.Footnote 23 Therefore, the historical events—such as the Enlightenment and the Kulturkampf Footnote 24—had a significant impact on the specific form of religious education in Germany today.Footnote 25

The offering of denominational religious education in public schools is the predominant model in Europe, and even in other parts of the world. For example, in Austria, the Netherlands, Poland, Spain, and Italy; as well as in Latin American countries, such as Colombia, Chile and Peru, denominational religious education is offered.Footnote 26 Of course, each country has its specific characteristics.Footnote 27 Compared to Germany, France experienced a different development. The process of separation of state and church in France culminated in the introduction of laicism on December 9, 1905.Footnote 28 Consequently, no teaching of or about religion is offered in public schools, with the exception of Alsace-Moselle due to historical reasons.Footnote 29 Only in secondary schools can parents or students request the creation of a chaplaincy. If the school authorities authorize this, the chaplain can offer religious education on the school premises to those students who are interested in it, but it neither can take place during school time, nor is it part of the regular curriculum.Footnote 30 Hungary and the Czech Republic follow this approach and do not offer lessons of, or about, religion as part of the regular curriculum.Footnote 31 Beyond Europe, the U.S., Japan, South Korea, and China also do not allow religious education in public schools.Footnote 32 A third approach to religious education can be found, for example, in the U.K.Footnote 33 This can be described as a middle course. Instead of offering no religious education at all, non-denominational teaching about religion is offered. Thus, the knowledge and information about several different religions is taught from an external point of view.Footnote 34

The incorporation of denominational religious education as part of the obligatory subjects at public schools in Germany is based on the belief that schools—as the places where knowledge is imparted and values are taught—Footnote 35cannot ignore the “religious dimension of human existence.”Footnote 36 Furthermore, religiously determined moral education may function as a precondition for the existence of a free democratic constitution. As Böckenförde put it in his famous dictum, “[t]he liberal, secularized state lives on prerequisites which it cannot guarantee.”Footnote 37 Religious education may help to establish these prerequisites.Footnote 38 In addition to Article 7, paragraphs 2 and 3 of the German Federal Constitution, most of the state constitutions contain corresponding guarantees. They are substantiated by state laws, as well as several church agreements and concordats.Footnote 39

As indicated, religious education is a common concern of the State and the Church, and thus belongs to the group of so-called “res mixtae.”Footnote 40 Article 7, paragraph 3 imposes on the state an obligation to ensure that the institutional and organizational requirements of religious education are met, while the religious societies decide its instructional contents. Therefore, religious education is marked by close cooperation between the state and the religious societies. It illustrates the existing so-called “limping” separation of church and state in Germany.Footnote 41 The relationship between state and churches, or religious societies, varies widely—as already alluded to above—even in liberal democracies.Footnote 42 Whereas France, for example, has a very strict separation of church and state, England and Sweden still have state churches.Footnote 43 Germany represents a middle course by having a cooperative relationship between the state and religious societies.Footnote 44 Each approach of regulating the relationship between the state and the religious societies may lead to different concepts of religious education, as seen above, and thus, of course, faces its own specific problems when it comes to religious diversification.

Therefore, this Article tries to highlight a problem which a cooperative approach of church and state relations is particularly exposed to—the issue of changing religious demography. Initially, only the two Christian churches—Catholic and Protestant—offered religious education in accordance with Article 7, paragraph 3. This remained consistent, as even until 1950, 96.5 % of the Western German population and 92 % of the Eastern German population were members of either of these two big Christian churches.Footnote 45 But in 1990, the number of Christian church members dropped down to around 72 %, the number of Muslims reached about 3.7 %, and non-denominational individuals made up about 22.4 %. This trend continues today: In 2015, only 56 % of the German population were members of one of the two Christian churches, whereas 5.5 % belonged to Islam, 2.1 % were part of a free church or other special communities, and 2.0 % belonged to the Orthodox or Oriental church. The percentage of non-denominational citizens increased to 31.4 %. In addition to the decrease in the total number of religious people, Germany also experienced a religious diversification. Corresponding to this diversification, the claim to establish other types of religious education rose. In particular, the claim for Islamic religious education has grown stronger in the recent past as people practicing Islam make up the second largest group after Christian believers, and their numbers are expected to grow further.Footnote 46

This leads to the essential question: Is the German Constitution capable of facing the new religious diversity? How does the state respond to it? This Article tries to answer this question with regard to the establishment of Islamic religious education. In the first part, the legal requirements of Article 7, paragraph 2 concerning religious education will be outlined. This then permits an examination, in the second part, of which legal problems will have to be solved before Islamic religious education can be offered as a regular subject at public schools.

B. Legal Significance of Article 7, Paragraph 3

Article 7, paragraph 3, sentence 1 of the ConstitutionFootnote 47 is what, in German constitutional law, is referred to as an institutional guarantee.Footnote 48 As such, Article 7, paragraph 3 ensures that religious education is part of the public school curriculum. Thus, the state cannot abolish religious education but must provide a framework that allows religious education to be taught.Footnote 49 The constitutional principle of neutrality in ideological or religious matters prohibits the state from teaching religious education on its own, or even from deciding the instructional contents. Consequently, Article 7, paragraph 3, sentence 2 provides that religious education be taught in accordance with the principles of the religious society. This institutional guarantee operates within an understanding of neutrality in the German Constitution, which can be called a “positive neutrality”.Footnote 50 This is due to the cooperative relationship between church and state. On the one hand, the state has to provide a framework for religious education in public schools. On the other hand, the state may not identify itself with a specific religion, and it must not determine the content of the religious education.

Nonetheless, the legal effects of Article 7, paragraph 3 are not limited to an institutional guarantee. It also houses a fundamental right. There is—nearly unanimous—agreement that Article 7, paragraph 3 at least grants religious societies a fundamental right to teach religious education.Footnote 51 It, however, remains controversial whether pupils and their parents have a corresponding fundamental right that they or their children receive religious education. The prevailing view favors such a right.Footnote 52 According to this view, Article 7, paragraph 3 is seen as part of the section of the Constitution that guarantees fundamental rights. Moreover, supporters of this point of view consider religious education to be complementary to the fundamental right of religious freedom and expression, which otherwise would be neglected. They maintain that religious education is part and parcel of religious expression.Footnote 53 In this context, it is important to point out that, in any event, only the state, not the religious society, is bound by Article 7, paragraph 3. Thus, even if one follows this opinion, parents or their children can only demand the establishment of religious education from the state. They cannot force the religious society itself to offer religious education.

Those who deny a fundamental right to religious education of parents and pupils point out that the text of Article 7, paragraph 3 suggests that this provision only equips religious societies with a fundamental right. Footnote 54 Furthermore, they maintain that all the state can do is provide an institutional and organizational framework for religious education. The state is constitutionally banned from teaching religious education directly through its own agents due to its obligation of neutrality in religious and ideological matters.Footnote 55 It is left to the religious societies to decide whether they avail themselves of their right. As mentioned before, Article 7, paragraph 3 does not entail the right of the parents or their children to force the religious society to offer religious education. If the religious society decides to refuse to offer religious education, it is the legal consequence of Article 7, paragraph 3 that the state won’t able to offer this particular religious education.Footnote 56 That a religious society decides to do so is rather unlikely, but it is part of their constitutionally granted right of self-determination. Therefore, the state is not in a position to ensure that all those who want to take religious education as a subject can do so.Footnote 57 A conditional fundamental right, which is dependent on the consent of the religious society, hardly improves the legal status of parents and their children. Moreover, such a conditional fundamental right is generally not known to the Constitution.Footnote 58

C. Religious Education as a Regular Subject

As mentioned before, Article 7, paragraph 3, sentence 1 stipulates that religious education has to be a regular subject at all public schools except in non-denominational schools. Article 7, paragraph 3 is the only rule in the German Constitution that prescribes a particular subject to be taught in schools. Nevertheless, religious education is not privileged in its rank and treatment compared to other subjects, but is secured in a specific way by the Constitution.Footnote 59

I. Religious Education

The doctrine of the religious society itself is taught. This follows from Article 7, paragraph 3 stating that “religious instruction shall be given in accordance with the tenets of the religious community concerned.”Footnote 60 Thus, religious education courses offered in schools are not interdenominational; there is no requirement that the courses provide comparative reflections on religious doctrines, nor are they mere lectures on moral philosophy, or the history of customs and manners, or the history of religion. Quite the contrary: In these courses, the doctrine of the particular religious society is taught and often presented as the only truth.Footnote 61 This is an essential difference from a non-denominational religious education, as it exists in the U.K. and Denmark. Still, this does not preclude the possibility of emphasizing or preferring a certain religion in the non-denominational religious education lessons.Footnote 62 For instance, in Denmark and the U.K., non-denominational religious education classes tend to emphasize Christianity.Footnote 63

Pursuant to Article 7, paragraph 3, religious education is taught in a denominational way.Footnote 64 Nevertheless, it is possible for the religious societies to organize an ecumenical religious education or to allow pupils belonging to a different denomination, or to none at all, to attend the denominational religious education offered by them.Footnote 65 That said, education also requires that knowledge be imparted. Therefore, a fine line needs to be drawn between religious education within the meaning of Article 7, paragraph 3 and the preaching of religious doctrine. For example, if the religious education lessons simply consist of praying, rites, cults, or meditation, this is considered to be preaching and hence it contradicts Article 7, paragraph 3.Footnote 66 Thus, the provision of religious education cannot be construed as creating a “church within the school.”Footnote 67

II. Public Schools

The provision of religious education under the German Constitution applies only to public schools, a term that is conventionally understood as all schools belonging to a governmental body. This broad definition means that religious education must be a regular subject at all schools providing a general education, as well as at professional training schools, except for technical schools and evening schools.Footnote 68 Yet, private schools are excluded even if they are open to the public at large. As a result of Article 7, paragraph 3’s character as an institutional guarantee, non-denominational schools—in other words, schools that have renounced a religious commitment and are strictly secular or ideological—cannot be established as a rule.Footnote 69

III. Regular Subject

As religious education must be a regular subject, the subject thus enjoys the same rank and must be treated just like any other so-called regular subjects.Footnote 70 This means that religious education must be integrated into the curriculum and be taught within the regular classrooms inside the school.Footnote 71 It is not an elective subject but a compulsory one. A registration to participate in religious education is not necessary.Footnote 72 Nevertheless, it is possible to opt-out.Footnote 73 According to Article 7, paragraph 2 of the German Constitution, the legal guardian, usually a parent, can decide on behalf of the child whether s/he will attend classes in religious education, unless the child has acquired the legal capacity to decide. This flows from the right of religious freedom—Article 4, paragraphs 1 and 2 of the Constitution—and the parental right to educate their children in the way the parents so choose—Article 6, paragraph 2 of the Constitution.Footnote 74 The conditions under which children can decide for themselves whether or not to attend religious education are laid down in the law concerning the religious education of children—“Gesetz über die religiöse Kindererziehung” [RelKErzG].Footnote 75 According to the law, parents can decide the child’s religious education until the child reaches the age of twelve. Thereafter, the parents’ decision requires the child’s approval between the ages of 12 and 14, and, finally, from the age of 14 onwards, children can decide on their own.

Furthermore, religious education must not be discriminated against in terms of the number of lessons per week or its position on the time-table.Footnote 76 Nevertheless, just as in the case of any regular subject, classes in religious education may be offered under the condition that a particular quorum of participating pupils is reached.Footnote 77 In a comparative perspective, this is nothing surprising, as a lot of countries offer denominational religious education on the basis that a specific quorum of pupils is reached.Footnote 78 A pupil’s performance has to be graded.Footnote 79 The final mark one receives in religious education can be decisive for promotion to the next grade.Footnote 80

In addition, each German constituent state is responsible for a proper religious education. Thus, the state must—through appropriate colleges or universities—ensure that qualified personnel are available to teach religious education.Footnote 81 The state has to employ sufficient number of teachers and must pay their salaries and cover other costs of providing religious education, including providing books and other teaching materials.Footnote 82 Irrespective of their official position, those who teach religious education may attend school staff meetings with an equal right to vote on decisions taken during those meetings.

D. Implementation

According to Article 7, paragraph 3, sentence 2, religious education is based on the central doctrine of faith and the central moral philosophy of the religion.Footnote 83 That is what is meant when the Constitution speaks of religious education being offered in accordance with the principles of the religious society. The denominational character of religious education is clearly envisaged under the German Constitution.

I. In Accordance with the Principles of the Religious Society

In order to be qualified as a religious society in terms of Article 7, paragraph 3, a number of requirements must be fulfilled.Footnote 84 In view of the close cooperation between the state and the religious society, the latter must identify a contact person on its behalf to ensure that the state can communicate with them. The prevailing view is that the religious society does not necessarily have to be organized as a corporation under public law—Article 140 of the German Constitution in conjunction with Article 137, paragraph 5 of the Weimar Constitution of 1919.Footnote 85

Religious societies participate in the preparation of the curriculum of religious education, and they can influence the teaching method, the content of the schoolbooks, and the content of other teaching aids.Footnote 86 They decide basically on their own, insofar as the content of the religious education is concerned.

The religious societies also participate in employment-related decisions concerning the teaching staff. Only teachers who have received an ecclesiastical authorization can teach religious education.Footnote 87 Protestant churches of the Länder issue the vocatio, while the Catholic Church issues the missio canonica. This requirement seems similar to what is required by other countries offering denominational religious education. For instance, in the Netherlands, Poland, Austria, Spain, and Italy, an ecclesiastic authorization of the church is mandatory, too.Footnote 88Article 7, paragraph 3, sentence 3 of the Constitution, however, also provides that no one has to teach religious education against his or her will. In this regard, Article 7, paragraph 3, sentence 3 again relates to the religious freedom protected under Article 4, paragraphs 1 and 2.Footnote 89 There is also a close link to Article 33, paragraph 3 and Article 3, paragraph 3 of the Constitution, which provide that no person is to be discriminated against on the ground of his or her faith. A teacher refusing to teach religious education must not suffer any official or unofficial disadvantages because of that decision.Footnote 90 Finally, the religious societies also have a right to inspect classes of religious education taught on their behalf.Footnote 91

Interestingly, the scope of freedom of religion and non-discrimination protection under the German Constitution is wider than in certain countries where religious education is taught in a non-denominational way. For instance, in the U.K., it is the state that selects, appoints, and dismisses teachers; defines the curriculum and syllabus, and approves textbooks without direct interference from the religious society.Footnote 92 Nonetheless, this does not exclude the possibility of cooperating with religious societies in certain activities.Footnote 93

As mentioned before, religious societies have a right, not an obligation, to offer a religious education. If the religious societies do not avail themselves of their right, the state may create and offer a similar subject.Footnote 94 Nonetheless, due to its obligation of neutrality in religious and ideological matters, the state must neither teach the doctrine of a particular religious society nor present it as the only truth.Footnote 95 On the contrary, the state might offer a non-denominational, comparative reflection on religious doctrines or a history of different religions. The difficulties of this substitute will be outlined later.Footnote 96

II. Governmental Supervision

As part of the public school curriculum, religious education is subject to governmental supervision. But in this case, the usual governmental supervision is modified and limited.Footnote 97 As has already been said, the religious societies basically decide the content of the religious education on their own. They influence the curriculum, the teaching method, and the contents of schoolbooks and of other teaching aids. They are free to present their religious doctrine as the only truth. The state must accept a new teaching method if the religious societies choose to change the content or intention of the education they offer.Footnote 98 Consequently, governmental supervision is limited to issues not related to questions of faith and religious doctrine, such as pupils’ discipline. Governmental supervision also is admissible in so far as it aims to ensure that the organizational and personal requirements for proper religious education are satisfied.Footnote 99

E. Scope of Application—So-Called LER in Brandenburg

To be clear, Article 7, paragraph 3 of the German Constitution does not apply throughout Germany. According to Article 141 of the Constitution, Article 7, paragraph 3 does not apply to a Land where on January 1, 1949, religious education was governed by a different legal regime. Article 141 refers to a Land that did not guarantee religious education as a regular subject at public schools at the beginning of 1949. This rule was originally included in the German Constitution to account for regional particularities that at the time applied to Bremen and Berlin. Therefore, Article 141 became known as the Bremen clause. In Berlin, the consequence of Article 141 was that the government decided in 2006 to introduce compulsory non-denominational teaching about religion—“ethics”—into the regular curriculum. Thus, while Germany in general follows the approach of denominational teaching of religion, Article 141 of the Constitution allows the Länder, where the Bremen clause applies, to follow a different approach. This, again, demonstrates that even in Germany, the denominational approach of religious education is not self-evident.

In addition, it is controversial whether Article 141 applies to all Länder in Eastern Germany as well. This largely theoretical question rose to prominence in 1996, when the Land Brandenburg decided to include a compulsory subject called “living-ethics-religion” (“LER”) into its public school curriculum instead of religious education. Religious education was instead offered as an elective subject. LER was to be taught in a non-denominational way. Brandenburg relied on Article 141 of the Constitution to justify its decision. The merits of this argument depend on the interpretation of the word “Land” in Article 141 of the Constitution. If that term refers to the regional identity of the territory,Footnote 100 then Article 141 applies to Brandenburg: At the beginning of 1949, religious education was not guaranteed as a regular subject at public schools in the territory of what is now known as the Land Brandenburg. Religious education was rather considered an exclusive concern of the religious societies. If the term “Land,” refers to the legal identity of a certain territory,Footnote 101 then Brandenburg could not rely on Article 141. Brandenburg was not created until the German reunification in 1990. Furthermore, the legal regime Article 141 speaks of must comply with basic democratic principles and the rule of law. Due to the influence of the former Soviet Union, it can hardly be said that the rules in 1949 in the territory now known as Brandenburg were passed in accordance with these principles. Members of Parliament, pupils, parents, and ecclesiastic institutions have appealed to the German Federal Constitutional Court in order to prevent the enforcement of the law and demanded that religious education should be instituted as a compulsory subject at Brandenburg’s public schools. The Federal Constitutional Court, however, neither decided upon the proper interpretation of Article 141 nor did it issue a verdict on the constitutionality of the law. Instead, the court proposed a compromise between the different parties: LER may be offered by the Land Brandenburg, but there needs to be the possibility to opt-out and choose religious education for the students.Footnote 102

F. Side Note: Alternative Subjects

Most schools include an alternative subject in the curriculum for those pupils who do not participate in religious education. Pupils who have decided against taking part in religious education usually have to attend classes in moral philosophy or ethics.Footnote 103 These are compulsory subjects too. In these subjects, pupils are taught about general moral values, but also about different religions.Footnote 104 According to the decisions of the highest courts in Germany, the provision of such an obligatory, alternative subject is constitutional.Footnote 105 The school system is subject to governmental supervision according to Article 7, paragraph 1 of the German Constitution. Because the state is responsible for its citizens’ education and formation, the state is entitled to create new and additional school subjects. The state has to impart both knowledge and values in order to educate the children to become responsible members of society. Therefore, the state may refer to moral questions and problems in public schools.Footnote 106 Nevertheless, moral philosophy has to be taught in strict respect of the principle of neutrality in ideological and religious matters and, with regard to its contents, has to comply with the precept of pluralism. The state must not dictate a particular moral concept as the truth.Footnote 107 As far as moral philosophy is an alternative subject to religious education, it is important to note that the attendance of religious education is voluntary. Moral philosophy, therefore, must not be organized in a way that—indirectly—pressures pupils to attend religious education against their will merely to avoid moral philosophy. Otherwise, the right to attend religious education on a voluntary basis would be violated. The state can enforce a compulsory alternative for religious education to substitute the time students abstaining from religious education miss, but the state has to organize it as an equivalent subject with regard to its contents and rank in order to prevent a violation of the right of religious freedom.Footnote 108 The state may even introduce it as an additional compulsory subject for all students, including the ones already attending religious education. The double burden for the students also attending religious education is justified by the educational mission of the state.Footnote 109

Legal scholars disagree whether moral philosophy—as an alternative, obligatory subject to religious education—is constitutional.Footnote 110 Some writers object to the contents of the subject and its link to religious education. Insofar as the state is committed to the neutrality in ideological and religious matters, the state must not take a binding view on moral questions or even dictate a particular moral concept as the truth. This raises difficult issues in education: Some writers wonder how the state can instill values in the pupils without, at the same time, violating its obligation of neutrality in matters of religion and ideology.Footnote 111 To ensure that a course about religion is neutral and objective is a very delicate issue.Footnote 112 Even where good faith and great effort is present in attempting to ensure neutral teaching, problems may arise because some pupils or parents might have a different understanding of neutrality.Footnote 113 For instance, in relation to Norway’s Christian Knowledge and Religious Ethical Education course, both the European Court of Human Rights and the United Nations Human Rights Committee concluded that the course was not sufficiently neutral and that the provided opt-out option was insufficient.Footnote 114

Another problem might be the close link that exists between moral philosophy and religious education. This problem corresponds to the reflections of the highest court. Religious education is attended voluntarily; there is no duty to participate. The parents, and subsequently their children, can invoke their right of religious freedom when they abstain from religious education. But where these children are made to attend a compulsory alternative subject, this sets up their religious freedom against a state mandate that is not explicitly required under the Constitution.Footnote 115 In other words, the decision to opt–out of religious education results in the duty to take part in an alternative subject, which is neither required by Article 7 of the Constitution nor another provision of the Constitution. Furthermore, the court indicates that this duty might not be compatible with the Constitution in relation to Article 3, paragraph 3, whereupon nobody is to be discriminated against on the ground of his or her faith.Footnote 116

G. Islamic Religious Education

Besides these difficult issues surrounding the implementation of religious education in Germany, one particularly thorny issue that has arisen in the context Germany’s increased religious plurality is the provision of Islamic religious education. At the moment, three Länder offer Islamic religious education, namely North-Rhine Westphalia (“NRW”) since 2012, and Hesse and Lower Saxony since 2013.Footnote 117 Berlin offers Islamic religious education as well but in a non-compulsory way, and the religious society is responsible for it on its own.Footnote 118 This is possible because Article 141 applies to Berlin,Footnote 119 and hence, it is not organized in accordance with Article 7, paragraph 3. In the other Länder, Islamic religious education is only offered as a pilot project—in other words, not ubiquitous.Footnote 120

When it comes to religious education for Muslims, a crucial issue is the identification of a representative for the religious society. As religious education has to be taught in accordance with the principles of the religious society, the state, as mentioned above, needs a contact person on the part of the religion.Footnote 121 The constitutional law concerning religions has been established according to a social condition dominated by the two big Christian churches, which have well-structured internal organizations.Footnote 122 In contrast, the Islamic community is more loosely organized and does not have a singular identifiable form of organization.Footnote 123 The majority of Muslims are not even members of any Islamic organization, and even the big Islamic umbrella associations (Dachverbände) do not represent the majority of Muslims.Footnote 124 This has led to the core problem of establishing Islamic religious education. With whom should the state cooperate? If nobody can be identified the project must fail, as the state is not able to define the content of the Islamic religious education itself due to its obligation of neutrality in religious and ideological matters.Footnote 125

The core of the legal debate is thus the question: Which Islamic organizations may be qualified as a religious society in order to nominate an authorized contact person for introducing Islamic religious education?Footnote 126

Besides that, the missing organization of Islam has left the state with the difficult task of determining which children are supposed to take part in Islamic religious education lessons. According to Article 7, paragraph 3 of the Constitution, to be established as a regular subject, registration to participate is generally not necessary.Footnote 127 Nevertheless, the state should be able to determine who is taking part in the lessons. If it is not possible to determine whether a child belongs to an Islamic religious society or not, the introduction of Islamic religious education should not be questioned generally—as this seems too formal and contradicts the objectives of Article 7, paragraph 3.Footnote 128 On the one hand, Article 7, paragraph 3 highlights the high significance of religious education by explicitly guaranteeing it. On the other hand, the religious society—as part of their right of self-determination—may decide whether it allows people of a related, or even a different confession, to take part in their religious education lessons.Footnote 129 Consequently, if the Islamic religious society decides to do so, it must be possible for the pupils—which regard themselves as belonging to the creed or a related creed—to take part in these lessons without having an official membership certificate. This could be realized by registering at school for taking part in Islamic religious education. Therefore, denying the introduction of Islamic religious education just because Islam is not based on membership and thus requiring the parents or the pupils—if they are older than 14 years—to register in order to take part in Islamic religious education seems unconvincing.Footnote 130

A further problem is the availability of qualified teachers. As the state is responsible for the institutional framework, it needs to make sure that there are enough qualified teachers.Footnote 131 Therefore, the state has started to establish Islamic Theology at Universities and colleges.Footnote 132 In doing so, it needs to cooperate with the Islamic religious societies once more because it needs to observe the right of self-determination of the religious societies and its obligation of neutrality in religious and ideological matters.Footnote 133 Thus, the state faces the same problems as it faces during the implementation of Islamic religious education.Footnote 134

The plurality of schools of thought and sects within Islam is another issue, a full treatment of which goes beyond the scope of this Article.Footnote 135 Whether all the different groups would agree to establishing a unified Islamic religious education remains to be seen.

I. Requirements for Qualifying as a Religious Society

A religious society is an association which brings people of the same creed or several related creeds together in order to fulfil all tasks required by the creed in a comprehensive manner.Footnote 136 Therefore, three conditions have to be fulfilled by a religious organization in order to be regarded as a religious society: First, there needs to be a union of people—personal base; second, the people have to share a creed or related creeds; and third, the association has to fulfil the tasks required by the creed in a comprehensive manner. As already mentioned, the prevailing view is that the association does not necessarily have to be organized as a corporation under public law in order to qualify as a religious society.Footnote 137 Besides meeting the requirements for qualifying as a religious society, Article 7, paragraph 2 of the Constitution imposes some further conditions in order to be able to establish religious education. First, the religious society must guarantee the continuity of its existence.Footnote 138 This is due to the fact that the introduction of religious education involves high expenditures of costs and organization for the state, so the state needs the warranty of a continuous cooperation partner.Footnote 139 Second, there is agreement that the religious society must meet a certain allegiance to the Constitution.Footnote 140

II. Do the Current Islamic Religious Organizations Meet the Constitutional Requirements for Qualifying as a Religious Society?

It is possible that local Mosque associations may fulfil the criteria of a religious society, but they are far too small to justify the introduction of Islamic religious education. Religious education may depend on whether a particular quorum of pupils wishing to take part, and a particular quorum of members of the religious society, is met.Footnote 141 In contrast, the big umbrella associations—for example “Zentralrat der Muslime in Deutschland e.V.” and “Islamrat für die Bundesrepublik Deutschland e.V.”—consisting of several Islamic associations, which themselves unite Mosque associations as well as other associations that promote such things as youth or culture,Footnote 142 seem to meet the necessary quorum. Therefore, the legal debate focuses on them.

For a long time, a controversial issue was whether umbrella associations have the necessary personal base, as they consist of associations instead of individuals.Footnote 143 The Federal Administrative Court decided in 2005 that the umbrella associations have the necessary personal base, as they actually represent the members of the associations, which joined the umbrella associations. This representation is given—according to the court—due to the division of labor existing in the whole organization.Footnote 144 To bolster this argument, the court stressed that Article 140 of the German Constitution in conjunction with Article 137, paragraph 5, sentence 3 of the former Constitution of 1919 allow religious societies under public law to unite into a single organization without losing its status as a religious society under public law.Footnote 145 This has to apply analogously to the merger of religious societies. Therefore, umbrella associations fulfil the criteria of a necessary personal base.

A religious society is not obliged to combine all people of the same religion. This is neither possible for an Islamic organization nor for a Christian organization, as both of them split up into different denominations or churches.Footnote 146 As already conveyed by the definition of the religious society, a religious society may combine people of different but related creeds. It is part of the religious freedom of the individuals to decide whether they are entitled by their religion to join with a related creed.Footnote 147 Consequently, people of the same creed must be free to join different organization, without this leading to a denial of qualifying as a religious society.Footnote 148 Therefore, it is not an obstacle for Islamic umbrella associations that people of the same creed are split up into different umbrella associations.

In order to meet the requirement of the comprehensive fulfillment of the tasks required by the creed, it is important that the umbrella association does not compromise on the majority associations which do not, or only partially, fulfil religious tasks.Footnote 149 Furthermore, according to the Federal Administrative Court, it is mandatory that the umbrella association itself fulfills tasks which are essential for the identity of the community, otherwise the necessary division of labor is missing.Footnote 150 At the level of the umbrella association, this may only be management tasks with regard to the care of the religious creed.Footnote 151 Under the care of the religious creed, the Federal Administrative Court understands statements about the content of faith and the religious convictions.Footnote 152 Subsequently, the umbrella association needs to have the relevant authority and competence (Sachautorität und kompetenz)Footnote 153 to enforce these essential tasks against the local Mosque Associations. It is not sufficient that the umbrella association has identically essential tasks, for they must also enjoy actual validity down to the level of the local Mosque Associations.Footnote 154

Whereas 2017 the Higher Administrative Court of North-Rhine Westphalia construed the criteria of authority—established by the Federal Administrative Court in its ruling in 2005—rather strictly and required that the local Mosque Associations or its members treat the statements of the umbrella association as actually binding,Footnote 155 the Federal Administrative Court made clear in its ruling in 2018Footnote 156 that this goes too far. According to the Federal Administrative Court, only the following three criteria need to be fulfilled in order to enjoy the necessary authority:Footnote 157 First, the umbrella association or the competent body needs to make statements with respect to the doctrine of faith to a certain extent. Second, the members of the umbrella associations need to have easy and reliable access to these statements. And third, the members need to respect these statements and behavioral requirements—for example they either adjust their conduct to them, or they take them seriously into account at least. Therefore, the Federal Administrative Court made clear, in contrast to the understanding of the Higher Administrative Court,Footnote 158 that it is sufficient to set guidelines which are being respected by the members. Thus, the solution of the Federal Administrative Court represents a middle course between a mere recommendation and a binding rule. The decisive point for the relevant authority is the necessary respect.

Consequently, in its 2017 decision, the Higher Administrative Court of North-Rhine Westphalia had denied that the relevant umbrella organizations—“Zentralrat der Muslime in Deutschland e.V.” and “Islamrat für die Bundesrepublik Deutschland e.V.”—have the necessary authority to qualify as a religious society, as they only set non-binding guidelines.Footnote 159 As a result, there was hardly any possibility for Islamic umbrella organizations to qualify as a religious society because a binding doctrine contradicts—more or less—the self-conception of Islam.Footnote 160 In general, the strict interpretation of authority by the Higher Administrative Court of North-Rhine Westphalia led to a conflict with the right of self–determination of a religious society.Footnote 161 The question, whether a binding doctrine is required by the creed of a religious society or not, belongs to the right of self–determination.Footnote 162 Therefore, interpreting the requirement of authority in such a way that it cannot be met if a binding doctrine does not existFootnote 163 would contradict the right of self–determination of the religious society. The latest decision of the Federal Administrative Court in December 2018 resolved this conflict. The new comprehension of the criteria of the necessary authority seems also to be met by religious organizations, which deny a binding doctrine. Thus, it should be possible for Islamic umbrella associations to fulfill this criterion, too.

It remains to be seen how the Higher Administrative Court of North-Rhine Westphalia, to whom the case has been remanded, will decide. Even if the Higher Administrative Court of North-Rhine Westphalia should qualify the Islamic umbrella associations as a religious society, they still need to meet a specific degree of loyalty to the Constitution in order to be able to determine a contact person for the state with regard to the implementation of Islamic religious education. On this question, the Federal Administrative Court explicitly didn’t rule.

III. Advisory Body—Constitutional Problems

Due to the lack of a religious society with the necessary quorum of members and political will to introduce Islamic religious education as a matter of integration, the state has introduced the model of an advisory body (Beirat) in the meantime.Footnote 164 The advisory body shall substitute the lack of an Islamic religious society.Footnote 165 The advisory body consists of half representatives of the organized Muslims—for example, representatives of the Islamic associations—and half Muslim public figures.Footnote 166 With regard to the Constitution, several legal problems arise, particularly with regard to the obligation of neutrality in religious and ideological matters of the state and—as the other side of the coin—to the right of self-determination of the religious societies according to Article 140 of the Constitution in conjunction with Article 137, paragraph 3 of the former Constitution of 1919.Footnote 167

With respect to the aspect of neutrality, it seems problematic that the state takes the initiative to form an advisory body.Footnote 168 Granted, it is not constitutionally forbidden that the state play an active role as long as it observes its neutrality.Footnote 169 In practical terms, this means that the state may take the initiative as long as it does not discriminate against any of the Islamic associations.Footnote 170 During the formation of the advisory body, it needs to invite all relevant Islamic associations.Footnote 171 As long as this is ensured, the state would not violate its neutrality.

A second problem is the representation of Muslim public figures. They actually do not represent anybody, and they exercise rights which actually belong to the religious societies.Footnote 172 Thus, their participation collides with the right of self-determination of the religious societies coordinated by the religious associations.Footnote 173 Therefore, the participation of these public figures can only be constitutional if their rights are limited compared to the rights of the representatives of organized Islam. Some argue that they may only have an advisory voice,Footnote 174 others demand that they merely must not outvote the representatives of organized Islam.Footnote 175 Last, it may be argued that the rights of the religious societies are preserved anyhow, because such a construction wouldn’t be possible against their will at all.Footnote 176

Nonetheless, the model of an advisory body may only be a temporary solution.Footnote 177 As the advisory body functions as a substitution for the missing organization of Islam, it may become illegal as soon as the organization of Islam proceeds and Islamic religious societies are formed.Footnote 178

H. Résumé

The Federal Administrative Court has shown in its 2005 decision that, in principle, the recognition of an umbrella association as a religious society is possible. Therefore, the introduction of Islamic religious education according to Article 7, paragraph 2 of the Constitution is possible, too. Nonetheless, the decision of the Higher Administrative Court of North-Rhine Westphalia led to the assumption that it is unlikely for Islamic Umbrella associations to fulfill the criteria of the relevant authority and thus to qualify as a religious society within the near future.Footnote 179 Therefore, the introduction of Islamic religious education analogous to Christian religious education seems unlikely. Critics decry the German Constitution as being too focused on the well-structured Christian Churches and as incapable of adapting to the new diversity.Footnote 180 The ruling of the Federal Administrative Court in 2018 changed this impression because it tried to find a middle ground. On the one hand, the court requires some kind of respect in order to fulfill the criteria of the relevant authority. This seems necessary, as the religious society needs to nominate a contact person with whom the state may coordinate all questions with regard to the content of the religion. It is important for the state that the contact person’s opinion and decisions are respected by its members. Otherwise, the state would be confronted with different opinions on what is supposed to be the “correct” content of the religion. But due to its obligation of neutrality in religious and ideological matters, the state wouldn’t be able to just choose one of them. Hence, the relevant content of the state based religious education could not be determined.Footnote 181 Thus, the implementation of the specific religious education seems doomed to fail. Besides that, one can hardly argue that a person or organization whose statements are not respected is able to represent the individuals. Thus, it cannot be regarded as the bearer of the collective freedom of believe or as a religious society.Footnote 182 On the other hand, the court does not require such a strict and binding hierarchy as existing in the Christian Churches. The court has tried to perform a balancing act between the necessary organizational requirements for a state-based religious education, and the necessary flexibilities different self-conceptions of religions, may require. Whether this balancing act works remains to be seen.

In the meantime, the federal governments found a solution in order to introduce Islamic religious education, even if organizational measures are missing. The temporary introduction of the advisory body model is, as argued above,Footnote 183 in accordance with the Constitution, as long as it remains a temporary solution.

Thus, we can conclude that even though the new diversification has challenged the Constitution and its rules, on the one hand, the state has found a constitutional way of providing Islamic religious education. On the other hand, the judiciary has tried to find a way of interpreting the term religious society in a way that is open to be fulfilled by religions that do not have such a strict internal organization as the Christian churches. Therefore, the Constitution has proven to be compatible with the diversification of religions, even though it was historically established with regard to the two well-organized Christian churches.Footnote 184

Clearly, the new religious pluralism in German society has created a difficult tension. The state’s duty in such circumstances should not be to remove the plurality, but to ensure that the competing groups tolerate each other.Footnote 185 The introduction of Islamic religious education is therefore a move in the right direction. Nonetheless, some scholars worry that the introduction of additional, different religious lessons would result in a segregation of students, because they will be split into different religious classes.Footnote 186 The introduction of Islamic religious education, especially, may lead to a further segmentation due to the different divisions existing within Islam itself, each of which could request for their own religious lessons.Footnote 187 Therefore, some have argued for the introduction of interdenominational and inter-religious education.Footnote 188 Under the current constitutional provisions, interdenominational religious education can only be introduced if the religious societies themselves are willing to offer it.Footnote 189 They cannot be forced to offer an interdenominational religious education. In this regard, Hamburg has taken a pioneering–role in offering interdenominational religious education, for which the Protestant church is responsible.Footnote 190

As the interdenominational approach cannot be established by the state without the consent of the religious societies themselves, scholars suggest as an alternative a non–denominational educational approach towards religion.Footnote 191 As shown, this would legally be possible in Germany even if it would be established as a compulsory subject in addition to the denominational religious education. Yet, this leads to the sensitive issue of teaching about religions and values in a neutral way. A complete abolishment of denominational religious education, as a consequence of this approach, would deny the historical characteristics and advantages—such as acceptance and public control of religions—of the German church-state relations. Thus, despite the fact that it wouldn’t be possible without a change of Article 7, paragraph 3 which seems rather unlikely to happen,Footnote 192 it is not favorable.Footnote 193

Nevertheless, it seems reasonable to combine both approaches—the non–denominational and the historical denominational approach.Footnote 194 As seen above, this combination of both approaches exists due to the exception of Article 141 already in the Constitution. But it is important that the possibility of denominational teaching is not selectively granted to only some of the religions.Footnote 195 By making it possible for Islam to offer religious education at public schools, the state has proven to be open to the values of pluralism and non-discrimination. This can be seen as an important step to ensure tolerance within a plural society, and tolerance is vital for the existence and function of a free democratic constitution.Footnote 196 Bearing Böckenförde in mind, it is in the state’s own interest to impart—especially through religious education—the pluralistic values, which it needs as a precondition for its existence.Footnote 197

Footnotes

*

Research Fellow at the Humboldt-University, Berlin. Email: fabius.wittmer@rewi.hu-berlin.de.

**

Prof. Dr. iur., Chair of Public and Financial Law at the Humboldt-University, Berlin.

References

1 W. Cole Durham, Jr., Introduction, in The Routledge International Handbook of Religious Education 1, 2 (Derek H. Davis & Elena Miroshnikova eds., 2013).

2 Juan G. Navarro Floria, Religious Education in Latin America, in The Routledge international handbook of religious education, supra note 1, at 197.

3 Grundgesetz [GG] [Basic Law] art. 7, translation at http://www.gesetze-im-internet.de/englisch_gg/index.html., which states:

  1. (1)

    (1) The entire school system shall be under the supervision of the state.

  2. (2)

    (2) Parents and guardians shall have the right to decide whether children shall receive religious instruction.

  3. (3)

    (3) Religious instruction shall form part of the regular curriculum in state schools, with the exception of non-denominational schools. Without prejudice to the state’s right of supervision, religious instruction shall be given in accordance with the tenets of the religious community concerned. Teachers may not be obliged against their will to give religious instruction.

4 See Weimarer Verfassung [WV] [Weimar Constitution] Aug. 11 1919, art. 149 (Weimar Republic) [hereinafter Weimar Const. 1919], which states:

Religious instruction shall form part of the regular school curriculum, except in the non-confessional (secular) schools. Its form will be regulated by laws relating to schools. Religious instruction shall be given in conformity with the principles of the religious society concerned, without prejudice to the State’s right of supervision.

The imparting of religious instruction and the performance of religious acts is left to the decision of the teacher, while the participation in religious lessons, acts, and ceremonies is a matter for the decision of those who have the right to determine the religious education of the child.

The theological faculties in the universities shall be maintained.

5 Udo Friedrich Schmälzle, Religious Education in Germany, in The Routledge international handbook of religious education, supra note 1, at 122.

6 See id.

7 Id.

8 See id. at 122–123.

9 See id. at 123.

10 Id.

11 Id.

12 See id. at 124. See also Verfassung für den Preußischen Staat [VPS] [Constitution] Jan. 31, 1850, art. 21 (Prussia).

13 Schmälzle, supra note 5, at 123–124.

14 For details on the Kulturkampf, see Peter Unruh, Religionsverfassungsrecht para. 35 (2018).

15 Id. at para. 35.

16 Schmälzle, supra note 5, at 124.

17 See Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 37.

18 See Weimar Const. 1919, supra note 4, at art. 137, para. 1 (“There shall be no state church.”).

19 See also Schmälzle, supra note 5, at 124.

20 See Weimar Const. 1919, supra note 4, at art. 146, para. 2, which states:

Within the Communes, however, on the petition of parents and guardians, popular schools professing their own faith or philosophy of life shall be established, insofar as this does not interfere with an organized school system in the sense, also, of paragraph 1, supra. As far as possible the will of the parents and guardians shall be taken into consideration. Details shall be regulated by Lands legislation based on principles prescribed by a Reich law.

21 See Schmälzle, supra note 5, at 124. For details on the so-called Weimar school compromise (Schulkompromiss), see Peter Badura, Art. 7, in Grundgesetz Kommentar para. 40 (Theodor Maunz & Günter Dürig eds., 2018).

22 Badura, supra note 21, at para. 40.

23 See Schmälzle, supra note 5, at 124.

24 See for the impact the Kulturkampf had on the current form of theological faculties at public universities Christian Waldhoff, Theologie an staatlichen Hochschulen, in Handbuch des Staatskirchenrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland para. 6 (Dietrich Pirson, Wolfgang Rüfner, Michael Germann & Stefan Muckel eds., forthcoming).

25 For the impact history has on current policies about religious education, see Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 2.

26 Silvio Ferrari, Religious Education in the European Union, in The Routledge international handbook of religious education, supra note 1, at 101.; Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 7–8.

27 For an overview about the specific characteristics of denominational religious education in European countries, see Ferrari, supra note 26, at 101.

28 Unruh, supra note 14, at paras. 37, 578.

29 Ferrari, supra note 26.

30 Ferrari, supra note 26.

31 Ferrari, supra note 26.

32 Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 5.

33 For a general overview about the three models of religious education in the public sector, see Ferrari, supra note 26; Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 4–9.

34 Ferrari, supra note 26.

35 See generally Rex J. Ahdar & Ian Leigh, Religious Freedom in the Liberal State 243 (2015).

36 Gerhard Robbers, Art. 7, in Grundgesetz Kommentar para. 115 (Hermann von Mangoldt, Friedrich Klein & Christian Starck eds., 7th ed. 2018).

37 Ernst-Wolfgang Böckenförde, Staat, Gesellschaft, Freiheit. Studien zur Staatstheorie und zum Verfassungsrecht 60 (1976).

38 See Schmälzle, supra note 5, at 125; Ahdar & Leigh, supra note 35, at 270.

39 For more information, see Unruh, supra note 14, at paras. 53–62.

40 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court], 74 Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts [BVerfGE] 244, 251, https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/SharedDocs/Entscheidungen/DE/1999/02/lk19990217_1bvl002697.html; Bernd Jeand’Heur & Stefan Korioth, Grundzüge des Staatskirchenrechts para. 306 (2000).

41 More information to the so-called “limping” separation of church and state in Germany can be found in Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at paras. 159–165. The term “limping separation” was imposed by Ulrich Stutz in Die päpstliche Diplomat, ie unter Leo XIII. 54 n.2 (1926).

42 Perry L. Glanzer & Konstantin Petrenko, Religion and Education in Post-Communist Russia: Russia’s Evolving Church-State Relations, 49 J. Church & State 53 (2007) (providing further references).

43 Bernd Grzeszick, Islamischer Religionsunterricht an öffentlichen Schulen, in Zeitschrift für evangelisches Kirchenrecht [ZeVKR] 362, 363 (2017).

44 Id. at 363.

45 For the statistical data here and below, see id. at 365.

46 See id. at 365–366; Guy Beaucamp & Karin Wißmann, Islamischer Religionsunterricht—Warum ist das eine unendliche Geschichte?, 2017 Deutsches Verwaltungsblatt 1517 (2017).

47 Grundgesetz art. 7, para. 3, which states:

Religious instruction shall form part of the regular curriculum in state schools, with the exception of non-denominational schools. Without prejudice to the state’s right of supervision, religious instruction shall be given in accordance with the tenets of the religious community concerned. Teachers may not be obliged against their will to give religious instruction.

48 Stefan Mückl, Staatskirchenrechtliche Regelungen zum Religionsunterricht, 122 Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 513, 520 (1997).

49 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 307.

50 Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 8; see Schmälzle, supra note 5, at 124–128.

51 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 311; Thorsten Kingreen & Ralf Poscher, Grundrechte para.786 (2018); Mückl, supra note 48, at 521.

52 Mückl, supra note 48, at 521–522; Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 123.

53 Mückl, supra note 48, at 521–522.

54 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 311; Frauke Brosius-Gersdorf, Art. 7, in Grundgesetz Kommentar para. 90 (Horst Dreier ed., 3rd ed. 2013).

55 Brosius-Gersdorf, supra note 54, at para. 90.

56 Id.

57 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 311; Brosius-Gersdorf, supra note 54, at para. 90.

58 Brosius-Gersdorf, supra note 54, at para. 90.

59 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 118.

60 Badura, supra note 21, at para. 70.

61 74 BVerfGE 244, at 252–253.

62 Ferrari, supra note 26.

63 Ferrari, supra note 26.

64 74 BVerfGE 244, at 252–253 (citing Gerhard Anschütz, Art. 149 WRV, in Die Verfassung des Deutschen Reiches para. 4 (Gerhard Anschütz ed., 14th ed. 1933)).

65 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 127.

66 Badura, supra note 21, at para. 70.

67 Mückl, supra note 48, at 523.

68 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 128.

69 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 129.

70 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 130.

71 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 308.

72 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 312.

73 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 312.

74 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 312.

75 See Gesetz über die religiöse Kindererziehung [KErzG] [Law on Religious Parenting], July 15, 1921, Reichsgesetzblatt [RGBl], at § 5.

76 Bernhard Schlink, Religionsunterricht in den neuen Ländern, 1992 Neue Juristische Wochenschrift [NJW] 1008, 1009.

77 Mückl, supra note 48, at 525.

78 Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 8.

79 Schlink, supra note 76, at 1009.

80 Schlink, supra note 76, at 1009.

81 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 135.

82 Robbers, supra note 36, at paras. 133–134.

83 Mückl, supra note 48, at 528.

84 For more details, see infra Section G.I.

85 Christoph Link, Religionsunterricht, in II Handbuch des Staatskirchenrechts der Bundesrepublik Deutschland 439, 500 (Joseph Listl & Dietrich Pirson eds., 1995); Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 151.

86 Mückl, supra note 48, at 529.

87 Mückl, supra note 48, at 529.

88 Ferrari, supra note 26, at 101.

89 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 308.

90 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 162.

91 Mückl, supra note 48, at 530.

92 Ferrari, supra note 26.

93 Ferrari, supra note 26.

94 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 160.

95 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 160.

96 See infra Section F.

97 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 309; Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 146.

98 74 BVerfGE 244, at 252.

99 Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 147.

100 Markus Thiel, Art. 141, in Grundgesetz Kommentar para. 13 (Michael Sachs ed., 8th ed. 2018); Schlink, supra note 76, at 1010–1013.

101 Peter Unruh, Art. 141, in Grundgesetz Kommentar, supra note 36, at para. 8; Arnd Uhle, Die Verfassungsgarantie des Religionsunterrichts und territoriale Reichweite, 1997 Die öffentliche Verwaltung 409, 410 (1997).

102 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfGE] [Federal Contitutional Court], Case No. 1 BvF 1/96, 104 Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts [BVerfGE] 305–310 (Oct. 31, 2002), https://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/SharedDocs/Entscheidungen/DE/2002/10/fs20021031_1bvf000196.html.

103 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 313; Badura, supra note 21, paras. 77.

104 See Badura, supra note 21, at para. 77.

105 Bundesverwaltungsgericht [BVerwG] [Federal Administrative Court], June 17, 1998, Deutsches Verwaltungsblatt [DVBl] 1344–1350 [hereinafter Judgment of June 17, 1998].

106 Id. at 1345.

107 Id. at 1345–1346.

108 Id. at 1347–1348.

109 Id. at 1347–1348; Badura, supra note 21, at para. 79.

110 Gerhard Czermak, Das Pflicht-Ersatzfach Ethikunterricht als Problem der Religionsfreiheit, des Elternrechts und der Gleichheitsrechte, 1996 Neue Zeitschrift für Verwaltungsrecht 450, 452–455 (1996); Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 314; Ludwig Renck, Verfassungsprobleme des Ethikunterrichts, 38 Bayerische Verwaltungsblätter 519, 521 (1992).

111 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 314.

112 See Ahdar & Leigh, supra note 35, at 271.

113 Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 6; Ahdar & Leigh, supra note 35, at 267–269, 271–276.

114 See Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 6.

115 Czermak, supra note 110, at 452–453; Renck, supra note 110, at 520–521; but see Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 432.

116 Czermak, supra note 110, at 453–455; Renck, supra note 110, at 521.

117 Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1517; Antje von Ungern-Sternberg, Islamischer Religionsunterricht und islamische Theologie—die Suche nach verfassungskonformen Lösungen, 64 Recht der Jungend und des Bildungswesens 30 (2016).

118 Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 31–32; Riem Spielhaus & Zrinka Stimac, Schulischer Religionsunterricht im Kontext religiöser und weltanschaulicher Pluralität, 68 Aus Politik und Zeitgeschichte 41, 42 (2018).

119 See Bundesverwaltungsgericht [BVerwG] [Federal Administrative Court], 110 Entscheidungen des Bundesverwaltungsgerichts [BVerwGE] 326, 335–336, https://dejure.org/dienste/vernetzung/rechtsprechung?Gericht=BVerwG&Datum=23.02.2000&Aktenzeichen=6%20C%205%2E99; but see Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 445.

120 For more details, see Havva Engin, Die Institutionalisierung des Islams an staatlichen und nichtstaatlichen Bildungseinrichtungen, in Handbuch Christentum und Islam in Deutschland. Grundlagen, Erfahrungen und Perspektiven des Zusammenlebens 369, 370–391 (Mathias Rohe ed., 2017).

121 Hartmut Kreß, Islamischer Religionsunterricht zwischen Grundsatzproblemen und neuen Rechtsunsicherheiten, 2010 Zeitschrift für Rechtspolitik 14 (2010); Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 368; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 37.

122 Kreß, supra note 121, at 14–15.

123 Kreß, supra note 121, at 14–15; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 371; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 37.

124 Kreß, supra note 121, at 14-15; Spielhaus & Stimac, supra note 118, at 44; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 371–372; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 37.

125 See with regard to Islamic Theological Faculties, Waldhoff, supra note 24, at § 46 n.67; for an overview of alternative concepts of religious education existing currently in Germany, see Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 34.

126 See Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 37; Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 459.

127 Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 429.

128 See Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1520; Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 459; Barbara Gartner, Der Islam im religionsneutralen Staat 255 (2005); Wolfgang Bock, Islamischer Religionsunterricht oder Religionskunde?, in Islamischer Religionsunterricht? 3, 30 (Wolfgang Bock ed., 2007).

129 See Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1521.

130 Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1521.; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 38.

131 See supra Section C.III. See also Waldhoff, supra note 24, at § 46 n.66.

132 See Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 30; Waldhoff, supra note 24, at § 46 n.18, 62–65.

133 See Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 32; Waldhoff, supra note 24, at § 46 n.67.

134 See also Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 31–42.

135 Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 8–9.

136 Bundesverwaltungsgericht [BVerwG] [Federal Administrative Court], 123 Entscheidungen des Bundesverwaltungsgerichts [BVerwGE] 49, https://www.bverwg.de/230205U6C2.04.0123; Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1519; Stefan Korioth, Art. 137 WRV, in Grundgesetz Kommentar, supra note 21, at para. 14.

137 Link, supra note 85, at 500; Robbers, supra note 36, at para. 151.

138 Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1519–1520; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 369.

139 Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1520.

140 123 BVerwGE 49, at 72–75; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 379–380; Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1520.

141 Jeand’Heur & Korioth, supra note 40, at para. 324; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 369–370. See also Vera Niestegge, Dachverbandsorganisationen als Religionsgemeinschaften?, 2018 Kunst und Recht 140, 161 (2018).

142 Niestegge, supra note 141, at 149.

143 Oberverwaltungsgericht Nordrhein Westphalen [OVG NRW] [Higher Administrative Court of North-Rhine Westphalia], Neue Zeitschrift für Verwaltungsrecht—Rechtsprechungs-Report [NVwZ-RR] 2004, 492, 493-494.

144 123 BVerwGE 49, at 58; Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 459.

145 123 BVerwGE 49, at 58–59. See also Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1519.

146 123 BVerwGE 49, at 56.

147 Id.; Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 459.

148 123 BVerwGE 49, at 56–57 et seq.

149 123 BVerwGE 49, at 60–61 et seq. See also Niestegge, supra note 141, at 153; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 373.

150 123 BVerwGE 49, at 59–60, 66–67. See also Niestegge, supra note 141, at 153.

151 Bundesverwaltungsgericht [BVerwG] [Federal Administrative Court], Case No. 6 B 94.18, para. 16 (Dec. 20, 2018), https://www.bverwg.de/201218B6B94.18.0.

152 Id.

153 123 BVerwGE 49, at 67.

154 Id. at 59, 67; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 370, 373; see also Niestegge, supra note 141, at 153.

155 Oberverwaltungsgericht Nordrhein Westfalen [OVG NRW] [Higher Administrative Court of North-Rhine Westphalia], Case No. 19 A 997/02, paras. 36–37 (Nov. 9, 2017), https://dejure.org/dienste/vernetzung/rechtsprechung?Text=19%20A%20997/02.

156 BVerwG, Case No. 6 B 94/18.

157 Id. at paras. 18–19.

158 OVG NRW, Case No. 19 A 997/02, at paras. 36–37.

159 Id. See also Niestegge, supra note 141, at 154–155.

160 Niestegge, supra note 141, at 160–161. This is because Islam has no teaching authority comparable to Christianity, see Ulrich Willems, Stiefkind Religionspolitik, 68 Aus Politik und Zeitgeschichte 9, 9 (2018).

161 BVerwG, Case No. 6 B 94/18, at para. 19; Kreß, supra note 121, at 14–15; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 38; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 370.

162 BVerwG, Case No. 6 B 94/18, at para. 19.

163 Niestegge, supra note 141, at 155–156 (stating clearly that a religious society that has no institutional teaching authority cannot meet the requirements laid down by the Federal Administrative Court).

164 See Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 460; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 374–375.

165 Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 374–375. See also Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 460.

166 For detailed information about the composition of the advisory body, see Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 460; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 39–40.

167 See Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 39–42.

168 Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 40; Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 461.

169 Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 41.

170 Moritz Indenhuck, Islamische Theologie im staatlichen Hochschulsystem 210–211, 216–217 (2016).

171 See Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 378–379; Hendrik Munsonius, Institutionalisierung Islamischer Theologie, in Göttinger E-Papers zu Religion und Recht [GöPRR] 1, 10 (2017).

172 Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 461.

173 Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 41; Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 461.

174 Unruh, supra note 14, at para. 461.

175 Munsonius, supra note 171, at 10; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 41–42.

176 See Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 41; Indenhuck, supra note 170, at 206.

177 Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 377; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 42.

178 Heinrich de Wall, Das Verhältnis von Staat und Religionsgemeinschaften in Deutschland, in Handbuch Christentum und Islam in Deutschland. Grundlagen, Erfahrungen und Perspektiven des Zusammenlebens 189, 213 (Mathias Rohe ed., 2017).

179 See Niestegge, supra note 141, at 160–161.

180 Niestegge, supra note 141, at 160–161; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 370; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 37–38.

181 See Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 370.

182 Niestegge, supra note 141, at 155.

183 See supra Section G.III.

184 See Kreß, supra note 121, at 14; Grzeszick, supra note 43, at 387–388.

185 Durham, Jr., supra note 1, at 10.

186 Kreß, supra note 121, at 16; Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1522.

187 Kreß, supra note 121, at 16.

188 Ferrari, supra note 26, at 101–102; Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 36–37.

189 See also Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 36–37.

190 Ungern-Sternberg, supra note 117, at 36.

191 Kreß, supra note 121, at 17. See also Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1522; Ferrari, supra note 26, at 102.

192 See Beaucamp & Wißmann, supra note 46, at 1522.

193 See also Ferrari, supra note 26, at 102.

194 Ferrari, supra note 26, at 102.

195 Ferrari, supra note 26, at 101.

196 See Ahdar & Leigh, supra note 35, at 270.

197 See Schmälzle, supra note 5, at 125.