Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T06:40:40.088Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Civil disobedience and constituent power

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 November 2015

David Schiff
Affiliation:
Professors of Law, Department of Law, Queen Mary University of London. Email: d.schiff@qmul.ac.uk.

Abstract

This paper uses the example of civil disobedience to explore Luhmann's description of the constitution as structural coupling between law and politics. Civil disobedience highlights the paradox of constituent and constituted power. The claims made for constituent power provide a basis for challenging the current configuration and expression of constituted power. This paradox is first avoided in the legal system through that system's inability to recognise a legal right to disobey law. In turn, a political system that has, under conditions of modernity, increasingly second coded power as legality, has an ever decreasing capacity to include communications that acknowledge a right to disobey law. Civil disobedience is only able to operate within the political system in the form of protest, and is accommodated through the exercise of discretionary powers. However, juridification of those powers has the capacity to threaten this accommodation.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Agamben, Giorgio (2005) State of Exception. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Amstutz, Marc (2009) ‘The Constitution of Contractual Networks’, in Amstutz, Marc and Teubner, Gunther (eds), Networks: Legal Issues of Multilateral Co-operation. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 309346.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah (1973) ‘Civil Disobedience’, in Crises of the Republic. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 49–102.Google Scholar
Brownlee, Kimberley (2012) Conscience and Conviction: The Case for Civil Disobedience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Christodoulidis, Emilios (1998) Law and Reflexive Politics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
DOBNER, Petra and Loughlin, Martin (eds) (2010) The Twilight of Constitutionalism? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald (1977) Taking Rights Seriously. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald (1985) A Matter of Principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Dyzenhaus, David (1997) Legality and Legitimacy: Carl Schmitt, Hans Kelsen and Herman Heller in Weimar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Griffith, John (1979) ‘The Political Constitution’, The Modern Law Review 42: 121.Google Scholar
Herstein, Ori (2012) ‘Defending the Right to Do Wrong’, Law and Philosophy 31: 343365.Google Scholar
Herstein, Ori (2014) ‘A Legal Right to Do a Legal Wrong’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 34: 2146.Google Scholar
Jacobson, Arthur and Schlink, Bernhard (eds) (2002) Weimar: A Jurisprudence of Crisis. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans (2013) The Essence and Value of Democracy, trans. Graf, B., ed. Urbinati, N. and Accetti, C.. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
King, Michael and Thornhill, Chris (2005) Niklas Luhmann's Theory of Politics and Law. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Lindahl, Hans (2007) ‘Constituent Power and Reflexive Identity: Towards an Ontology of Collective Selfhood’, in Loughlin and Walker (2007), 9–24.Google Scholar
Loizidou, Elena (ed.) (2013) Disobedience: Concept and Practice. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Loughlin, Martin and Walker, Neil (eds) (2007) The Paradox of Constitutionalism: Constituent Power and Constitutional Form. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (1982) Protest: Systemtheorie und Soziale Bewegungen. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (1988) ‘The Third Question: The Creative Use of Paradoxes in Law and Legal History’, Journal of Law and Society 15: 153165.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (1989) Ecological Communication. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (1990) Political Theory in the Welfare State, trans. Bednarz, J. Jr.Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (2004) Law as a Social System, trans. Ziegert, K.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (2012) Theory of Society, Vol. 1, trans. Barrett, Rhodes. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (2013a) Introduction to Systems Theory, trans. Gilgen, P.. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Luhmann, Niklas (2013b) Theory of Society, Vol. 2, trans. Barrett, Rhodes. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Mac Amhlaigh, Cormac (2013) ‘Constitutionalism as Paradigm: A Prospectus for Political Legitimacy in the New World Order’. Paper presented at International Network on Transnational Legal and Political Theory, Queen Mary University, London, 7 November 2013 (on file with author).Google Scholar
Nobles, Richard and Schiff, David (2006) A Sociology of Jurisprudence. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Nobles, Richard and Schiff, David (2009) ‘Why Do Judges Talk the Way They Do?’, International Journal of Law in Context 5: 2549.Google Scholar
Nobles, Richard and Schiff, David (2013) Observing Law through Systems Theory. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Perez, Oren (2006) ‘Law in the Air: A Prologue to the World of Legal Paradoxes’, in Perez, Oren and Teubner, Gunther (eds), Paradoxes and Inconsistencies in the Law. Oxford: Hart Publishing, 338.Google Scholar
Přibáň, Jiří (2007) Legal Symbolism. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Přibáň, Jiří (2011) ‘Self-reference of the Constitutional State: A Systems Theory Interpretation of the Kelsen–Schmitt Debate’, Jurisprudence 2: 309328.Google Scholar
Quint, Peter (2008) Civil Disobedience and the German Courts: The Pershing Missile Protests in Comparative Perspective. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Rawls, John (1973) A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph (2009) The Authority of Law, 2nd edn.Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, Adam and Garton Ash, Timothy (2009) (eds) Civil Resistance and Power Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sarat, Austin (2014) ‘Keeping Civility in its Place: Dissent, Injustice and the Lessons of History’, in Nobles, R. and Schiff, D. (eds), Law, Society and Community: Socio-Legal Essays in Honour of Roger Cotterrell. Aldershot: Ashgate, 293308.Google Scholar
Schmitt, Carl (2006) The Concept of the Political, trans. by Schwab, G.. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Teubner, Gunther (2012) Constitutional Fragments: Societal Constitutionalism and Globalization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thornhill, Chris (2011) A Sociology of Constitutions: Constitutions and State Legitimacy in Historical-Sociological Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Verschraegen, Gert (2002) ‘Human Rights and Modern Society: A Sociological Analysis from the Perspective of Systems Theory’, Journal of Law and Society 29: 258281.Google Scholar
Vinx, Lars (2007) Hans Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law: Legality and Legitimacy. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar