Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T14:33:21.486Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Closed sets and chain conditions in stable theories

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Anand Pillay
Affiliation:
McGill University, Montréal, Québec, Canada
Gabriel Srour
Affiliation:
McGill University, Montréal, Québec, Canada

Extract

An impressive theory has been developed, largely by Shelah, around the notion of a stable theory. This includes detailed structure theorems for the models of such theories as well as a generalized notion of independence. The various stability properties can be defined in terms of the numbers of types over sets, or in terms of the complexity of definable sets. In the concrete examples of stable theories, however, one finds an important distinction between “positive” and “negative” information, such a distinction not being an a priori consequence of the general definitions. In the naive examples this may take the form of distinguishing between say a class of a definable equivalence relation and the complement of a class. In the more algebraic examples, this distinction may have a “topological” significance, for example with the Zariski topology on (the set of n-tuples of) an algebraically closed field, the “closed” sets being those given by sets of polynomial equalities. Note that in the latter case, every definable set is a Boolean combination of such closed sets (the definable sets are precisely the constructible sets). Similarly, stability conditions in practice reduce to chain conditions on certain “special” definable sets (e.g. in modules, stable groups). The aim here is to develop and present such notions in the general (model-theoretic) context. The basic notion is that of an “equation”. Given a complete theory T in a language L, an L-formula φ(x̄, ȳ) is said to be an equation (in ) if any collection Φ of instances of φ(i.e. of formulae φ(x̄, ā)) is equivalent to a finite subset Φ′Φ.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

[1]Berline, C., Déviation dans les corps algébriquement clos, Groupe d'Étude: Théories Stables, 3e annee: 1979/80 (Poizat, B., editor), Secrétariat Mathématique, Paris, 1982, Exposé 3.Google Scholar
[2]Chang, C. C. and Keisler, H. J., Model theory, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1973.Google Scholar
[3]Cherlin, G., Stable algebraic theories, Logic Colloquium '78, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1979, pp. 5374.Google Scholar
[4]Cherlin, G., Harrington, L. and Lachlan, A. H., 0-categorical, ℵ0-stable structures (to appear).Google Scholar
[5]Harrington, L. and Harnik, V., Fundamentals of forking (to appear).Google Scholar
[6]Lachlan, A. H., Two conjectures regarding the stability of ℵ0-categorical theories, Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 81 (1974), pp. 133145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[7]Lachlan, A. H., Dimension and totally transcendental theories of rank 2, Set theory and hierarchy theory (Proceedings of the second conference, Bierutowice, 1975), Lecture Notes in Mathematics, Vol. 537, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1976, pp. 153183.Google Scholar
[8]and, D. LascarPoizat, M., Introduction to forking, this Journal, vol. 44 (1979), pp. 330350.Google Scholar
[9]Pillay, A. and Prest, M., Forking and pushouts in modules, Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, ser. 3, vol. 46 (1983), pp. 365384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[10]Pillay, A., Countable models of stable theories, Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 89 (1983), pp. 666672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[11]Pillay, A., Introduction to stability theory, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1983.Google Scholar
[12]Shelah, S., Classification theory and the number of nonisomorphic models, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1978.Google Scholar
[13]Srour, G., Some immediate clarifications to the theory of modules, preprint, Hebrew University, Jerusalem, 1981.Google Scholar
[14]Srour, G., Some clarifications to the theory of modules, preprints, Hebrew University, Jerusalem, 1981/81. (Extensions of [13].)Google Scholar
[15]Srour, G., Equations and equational theories (in preparation).Google Scholar
[16]Ziegler, M., Model theory of modules, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 26 (1984), pp. 149213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar