Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-cx56b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-26T07:43:00.741Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

FORBIDDEN INDUCED SUBGRAPHS AND THE ŁOŚ–TARSKI THEOREM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 January 2024

YIJIA CHEN*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF COMPUTER SCIENCE SHANGHAI JIAO TONG UNIVERSITY SHANGHAI, CHINA
JÖRG FLUM
Affiliation:
MATHEMATISCHES INSTITUT UNIVERSITÄT FREIBURG FREIBURG, GERMANY E-mail: joerg.flum@math.uni-freiburg.de
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Let $\mathscr {C}$ be a class of finite and infinite graphs that is closed under induced subgraphs. The well-known Łoś–Tarski Theorem from classical model theory implies that $\mathscr {C}$ is definable in first-order logic by a sentence $\varphi $ if and only if $\mathscr {C}$ has a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs. This result provides a powerful tool to show nontrivial characterizations of graphs of small vertex cover, of bounded tree-depth, of bounded shrub-depth, etc. in terms of forbidden induced finite subgraphs. Furthermore, by the Completeness Theorem, we can compute from $\varphi $ the corresponding forbidden induced subgraphs. This machinery fails on finite graphs as shown by our results:

  • There is a class $\mathscr {C}$ of finite graphs that is definable in first-order logic and closed under induced subgraphs but has no finite set of forbidden induced subgraphs.

  • Even if we only consider classes $\mathscr {C}$ of finite graphs that can be characterized by a finite set of forbidden induced subgraphs, such a characterization cannot be computed from a first-order sentence $\varphi $ that defines $\mathscr {C}$ and the size of the characterization cannot be bounded by $f(|\varphi |)$ for any computable function f.

Besides their importance in graph theory, the above results also significantly strengthen similar known theorems for arbitrary structures.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

Many classes of graphs can be defined by a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs. One of the simplest examples is the class of graphs of bounded degree. Let $d\ge 1$ and let the set $\mathscr {F}_d$ consist of all graphs with vertex set $\{1, \ldots , d+2\}$ and maximum degree $d+1$ . Then a graph G has degree at most d if and only if no graph in $\mathscr {F}_d$ is isomorphic to an induced subgraph of G. Less trivial examples include classes of graphs of small vertex cover (attributed to Lovász [Reference Fellows12]), of bounded tree-depth [Reference Ding7], and of bounded shrub-depth [Reference Ganian, Hlinený, Nesetril, Obdrzálek, de Mendez and Ramadurai16]. As a matter of fact, understanding forbidden induced subgraphs for those graph classes is an important question in structural graph theory [Reference Dvorák, Giannopoulou and Thilikos10, Reference Gajarský and Kreutzer14, Reference Ganian, Hlinený, Nesetril, Obdrzálek and Ossona de Mendez15, Reference Zaslavsky28]. However, a straightforward adaptation of a result in [Reference Fellows and Langston13] shows that it is in general impossible to compute the forbidden induced subgraphs from a description of classes of finite graphs by Turing machines.

Łoś [Reference Łoś19] and Tarski [Reference Tarski26] proved the first so-called preservation theorem of classical model theory. In its simplest form it says for classes of graphs that the class of finite and infinite graphs that are models of a sentence $\varphi $ of first-order logic (FO) is closed under induced subgraphs (or, that $\varphi $ is preserved under induced subgraphs) if and only if there is a universal FO-sentence $\mu $ with . Recall that a universal sentence $\mu $ is a sentence of the form $\forall x_1 \ldots \forall x_k\, \mu _0$ , where $\mu _0$ is quantifier-free.

For a class $\mathscr {F}$ of graphs let consist of all graphs that do not contain an induced subgraph isomorphic to a graph in $\mathscr {F}$ . For any class $\mathscr {C}$ of graphs closed under isomorphism and under induced subgraphs we have where $\mathscr {F}$ consists of all graphs not in $\mathscr {C}$ . Observe that $\mathscr {F}$ is an infinite class that contains infinite graphs if $\mathscr {C}$ is not the class of all graphs (later on we only will consider for sets $ \mathscr {F}$ ).

It is folklore (see, e.g., [Reference McKee20]) that for a class $\mathscr {C}$ of graphs its definability by a universal sentence of first-order logic is equivalent to its characterization by finitely many forbidden induced finite subgraphs, i.e., equivalent to for some finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of finite graphs. In fact, for a universal sentence $\mu :=\forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\,\mu _0$ with quantifier-free $\mu _0$ we have (see Proposition 2.2)

(1)

Here for any FO-sentence $\varphi $ and $k\ge 1$ by $\mathscr {F}_k(\varphi )$ we denote the class of graphs that are models of $\neg \varphi $ and whose universe is $\{1, \ldots , \ell \}$ for some $\ell $ with $1\le \ell \le k$ . Clearly, $\mathscr {F}_k(\varphi )$ is finite.

We say that a class $\mathscr {C}$ of finite and infinite graphs is definable by a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs if there is a finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of finite graphs such that . Hence the Łoś–Tarski Theorem (for classes of graphs) can be restated in the form:

For a class $\mathscr {C}$ of finite and infinite graphs the following are equivalent:

  1. (i) $\mathscr {C}$ is closed under induced subgraphs and FO-axiomatizable.

  2. (ii) $\mathscr {C}$ is axiomatizable by a universal sentence.

  3. (iii) $\mathscr {C}$ is definable by a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs.

This version of the Łoś–Tarski Theorem is already contained, at least implicitly, in the article [Reference Vaught27] of Vaught published in 1954.

Clearly (1) implies where and denote the class of finite graphs in and in , respectively. Hence the equivalence between (ii) and (iii) holds too if we only consider classes of finite graphs.

Note that we have repeatedly mentioned that in the Łoś–Tarski Theorem graphs are allowed to be infinite. This is not merely a technicality. In [Reference Chen and Flum3], to obtain the forbidden induced subgraph characterization of graphs of bounded shrub-depth using the Łoś–Tarski Theorem, one simple but vital step is to extend the notion of shrub-depth to infinite graphs. Indeed, Tait [Reference Tait25] exhibited a class $\mathscr {C}$ of finite structures (which might be understood as colored directed graphs) that is closed under induced substructures and FO-axiomatizable. Yet, $\mathscr {C}$ is not definable by any universal sentence, thus cannot be characterized by a finite set of forbidden induced finite substructures. In [Reference Alechina and Gurevich1] the authors present a class $\mathscr {C}$ of finite directed graphs with loops with the same properties, i.e., $\mathscr {C}$ is closed under induced substructures and FO-axiomatizable (even by a sentence without equality) but not axiomatizable by a universal sentence. Of course, the class $\mathscr {C}'$ of graphs in $\mathscr {C}$ is closed under induced subgraphs but $\mathscr {C}'$ is axiomatizable by a universal sentence (as $\mathscr {C}'$ is empty).

The first result of this paper strengthens the preceding “negative results” to graphs; more precisely we show the following theorem:

Theorem 1.1. There is a class $\mathscr {C}$ of finite graphs that is closed under induced subgraphs and $\mathrm{FO}$ -axiomatizable but not definable by a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs (i.e., there is no finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of finite graphs such that ).

Even though we are interested in structural and algorithmic results for classes of finite graphs, we see that in order to apply the Łoś–Tarski Theorem for such purposes we have to consider classes of finite and infinite graphs. Hence, in this paper “graph” means finite or infinite graph. As in the preceding result we mention it explicitly if we only consider finite graphs.

Complementing Theorem 1.1 we show that it is even undecidable whether a given FO-definable class of finite graphs that is closed under induced subgraphs can be characterized by a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs. More precisely, we prove:

Theorem 1.2. There is no algorithm that for any $\mathrm{FO}$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that is closed under induced subgraphs decides whether $\varphi $ is equivalent to a universal sentence on finite graphs.

For a first-order definable class of graphs closed under induced subgraphs, often it is preferable to have an explicit construction of a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs. This however turns out to be difficult for many natural classes of graphs. Let us consider the k-vertex cover problem for a constant $k\ge 1$ . It asks whether a given graph has a vertex cover (i.e., a set of vertices that contains at least one endpoint of every edge) of size at most k. The class of all yes-instances of this problem, finite and infinite, is closed under induced subgraphs and FO-axiomatizable by the FO-sentence

where axiomatizes the class of graphs. Hence, by the Łoś–Tarski Theorem there is a universal sentence $\mu $ equivalent to $\varphi ^k_{\text {VC}}$ . As the reader will notice, it is by no means trivial to find such a $\mu $ . On the other hand, using the Completeness Theorem, we eventually will get such a $\mu $ . Then we can extract corresponding forbidden induced subgraphs from $\mu $ as in (1). For the reader familiar with parameterized complexity [Reference Downey and Fellows8], to get a $\mu $ we can alternatively use that a graph with vertex cover of size at most k admits a kernel with at most $k^2$ edges. Observe that this approach involves the co-NP-hard problem of deciding whether an input graph does not contain a vertex cover of size at most k.

By [Reference Ding7], also the class of finite graphs of tree-depth at most k is definable by a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs. However, forbidden induced subgraphs are only known for $k\le 3$ [Reference Dvorák, Giannopoulou and Thilikos10].

We prove two “negative” results that explain the hardness of constructing forbidden induced subgraphs.

Theorem 1.3. There is no algorithm that for any $\mathrm{FO}$ -sentence $\varphi $ which is equivalent to a universal sentence $\mu $ on finite graphs computes such a $\mu $ . Or equivalently, there is no algorithm that for any $\mathrm{FO}$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that

for a finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of finite graphs computes such an $\mathscr {F}$ .

Theorem 1.4. Let $f: \mathbb N\to \mathbb N$ be a computable function. Then there is a class $\mathscr {C}$ of finite graphs and an $\mathrm{FO}$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that $:$

  1. (i) .

  2. (ii) for some universal sentence $\mu $ , in particular $\mathscr {C}$ is closed under induced subgraphs.

  3. (iii) For every universal sentence $\mu $ with we have $|\mu |\ge f(|\varphi |)$ .

Theorem 1.3 significantly strengthens the aforementioned result of [Reference Fellows and Langston13]: even if a class $\mathscr {C}$ of finite graphs definable by a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs is given by an $\mathrm{FO}$ -sentence $\varphi $ with , instead of a (much more powerful) Turing machine deciding $\mathscr {C}$ , we still cannot compute an appropriate finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs for $\mathscr {C}$ from $\varphi $ . On top of it, Theorem 1.4 implies that the size of forbidden subgraphs for $\mathscr {C}$ cannot be bounded by any computable function in terms of the size of $\varphi $ . There is an important precursor for Theorem 1.4:

Theorem 1.5 (Gurevich’s Theorem [Reference Gurevich17]).

Let $f:\mathbb N\to \mathbb N$ be computable. Then there is an $\mathrm{FO}$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that the class of models of $\varphi $ is closed under induced substructures but for every universal sentence $\mu $ with we have $|\mu |\ge f(|\varphi |)$ .

Hence, Theorem 1.4 can be viewed as the graph-theoretic version of Theorem 1.5.

Besides its importance in graph theory, Theorem 1.4 is also relevant in the context of algorithmic model theory. For algorithmic applications, the Łoś–Tarski theorem provides a normal form (i.e., a universal sentence) for any FO-sentence preserved under induced substructures. In [Reference Dawar, Grohe, Kreutzer and Schweikardt5, Theorem 6.1], it is shown that on labelled trees there is no elementary bound on the length of the equivalent universal sentence in terms of the original one. We should point out that Theorem 1.4 is not comparable to this result, since our lower bound is uncomputable (and thus, much higher than non-elementary) while the classes of graphs we construct in the proof are dense (thus very far from trees).

Our technical contributions

For every vocabulary it is well-known that the class of structures of this vocabulary is FO-interpretable in the class of graphs (see, for example, [Reference Ebbinghaus and Flum11]). Hence one might expect that Theorems 1.1 and 1.4 can be derived easily from Tait’s Theorem and Gurevich’s Theorem using the standard FO-interpretations. However, an easy analysis shows that those interpretations yield classes of graphs that are not closed under induced subgraphs. So we introduce the notion of strongly existential interpretation that translates any class of structures preserved under induced substructures and relevant to our investigations to a class of graphs closed under induced subgraphs. A lot of care is needed to construct strongly existential interpretations.

Related research

Let us briefly mention some further results related to the Łoś–Tarski Theorem. Essentially one could divide them into three categories (a), (b), and (c).

  1. (a) The positive results showing that for certain classes $\mathscr {C}$ of finite structures the analogue of the Łoś–Tarski Theorem holds if we restrict to structures in $\mathscr {C}$ . For example, this is the case if $\mathscr {C}$ is the class of all finite structures of tree-width at most k for some $k\in \mathbb N$ [Reference Atserias, Dawar and Grohe2] or if $\mathscr {C}$ is the class of all finite structures whose hypergraph satisfies certain properties [Reference Duris9].

  2. (b) Both just mentioned papers contain also negative results, i.e., classes for which the analogue of the Łoś–Tarski Theorem fails. For example, in [Reference Atserias, Dawar and Grohe2] this is shown for the class of finite planar graphs, a class not axiomatizable in FO (cf. Remark 5.7(b)).

  3. (c) The third category contains generalizations of the Łoś–Tarski Theorem or of its failure on finite structures. For example, in [Reference Sankaran, Adsul and Chakraborty24] the authors for every $k\in \mathbb N$ derive a preservation theorem for $\Sigma _2$ -sentences of the form $\exists x_1\ldots \exists x_k\,\mu $ with universal $\mu $ . For $k= 0$ it coincides with the Łoś–Tarski Theorem; see Remark 3.5 for the precise statement. The paper [Reference Lopez18] contains a further extension of the Łoś–Tarski Theorem. In [Reference Dawar and Sankaran6] the authors show that for every $n\ge 1$ there is a $\Pi _{2n+ 1}$ -sentence whose class of finite models is closed under induced substructures and that is not equivalent to a $\Sigma _{2n+ 1}$ -sentence in the finite.

Most classical preservation theorems fail in the finite (see [Reference Rossman21] for an exception). The question whether a preservation theorem fails for finite graphs is specially relevant for the Łoś–Tarski Theorem due to its connection to forbidden induced subgraphs.

Organization of this paper

In Section 2 we fix some notation and recall or derive some results about universal sentences we need in this paper. In Section 3 we include a proof of Tait’s result (essentially as done in [Reference Alechina and Gurevich1]). Moreover, we prove a technical result (Proposition 3.11) that is an important tool in the proof of Gurevich’s Theorem. We introduce the concept of strongly existential interpretation in Section 4 and show that the results of the preceding section remain true under such interpretations. We present an appropriate strongly existential interpretation for graphs (in Section 5). Hence, we get the results of Section 3 for graphs. In Section 6 we first derive Gurevich’s Theorem and apply our interpretations to get the corresponding results for graphs. Finally, in Section 7, we prove that various problems related to our results are undecidable.

This paper is the full version of our conference paper [Reference Chen and Flum4].

2 Preliminaries

We denote by $\mathbb N$ the set of natural numbers greater or equal to 0. For $n\in \mathbb N$ let $[n]:= \{1, 2, \ldots , n\}$ .

2.1 First-order logic FO

A vocabulary $\tau $ is a finite set of relation symbols. Each relation symbol has an arity. A structure $\mathcal A$ of vocabulary $\tau $ , or $\tau $ -structure, consists of a (finite or infinite) nonempty set A, called the universe of $\mathcal A$ , and of an interpretation $R^{\mathcal A}\subseteq A^r$ of each r-ary relation symbol $R\in \tau $ . If $\mathcal A$ and $\mathcal B$ are $\tau $ -structures, then $\mathcal A$ is a substructure of $\mathcal B$ , denoted by $\mathcal A\subseteq \mathcal B$ , if $A\subseteq B$ and $R^{\mathcal A}\subseteq R^{\mathcal B}$ , and $\mathcal A$ is an induced substructure of $\mathcal B$ , denoted by $\mathcal A\subseteq _{\text {ind}} \mathcal B$ , if $A\subseteq B$ and $R^{\mathcal A}= R^{\mathcal B}\cap A^r$ , where r is the arity of R. A substructure $\mathcal A$ of $\mathcal B$ is proper if $\mathcal A \ne \mathcal B $ . By we denote the class of all (of all finite) $\tau $ -structures.

If we speak of a class of structures, we assume that it is closed under isomorphism. On the other hand, note that every nonempty set of structures does not have this closure property.

Formulas $\varphi $ of first-order logic FO of vocabulary $\tau $ are built up from atomic formulas $x_1= x_2$ and $Rx_1 \ldots x_r$ (where $R\in \tau $ is of arity r and $x_1, x_2, \ldots , x_r$ are variables) using the boolean connectives $\neg $ , $\wedge $ , and $\vee $ and the universal $\forall $ and existential $\exists $ quantifiers. A relation symbol R is positive (negative) in $\varphi $ if all atomic subformulas $R\ldots $ in $\varphi $ appear in the scope of an even (odd) number of negation symbols. By the notation $\varphi (\bar x)$ with $\bar x= x_1, \ldots , x_e$ we indicate that the variables free in $\varphi $ are among $x_1, \ldots , x_e$ . If $\mathcal A$ is a $\tau $ -structure and $a_1, \ldots , a_e\in A$ , then $\mathcal A\models \varphi (a_1, \ldots , a_e)$ means that $\varphi (\bar x)$ holds in $\mathcal A$ if $x_i$ is interpreted by $a_i$ for $i\in [e]$ .

A sentence is a formula without free variables. For a sentence $\varphi $ we denote by the class of models of $\varphi $ and is its subclass consisting of the finite models of $\varphi $ . Sentences $\varphi $ and $\psi $ are equivalent if and finitely equivalent if .

2.2 Graphs

Let $\tau _E:= \{E\}$ with binary E. For all $\tau _E$ -structures we use the notation $G= (V(G), E(G))$ common in graph theory. Here $V(G)$ , the universe of G, is the set of vertices, and $E(G)$ , the interpretation of the relation symbol E, is the set of edges. The $\tau _E$ -structure $G = (V(G), E(G))$ is a directed graph if $E(G)$ does not contain loops, i.e., $(v,v)\notin E(G)$ for all $v\in V(G)$ . If moreover $(u,v)\in E(G)$ implies $(v,u)\in E(G)$ for all pairs $(u,v)$ , then G is an (undirected) graph. We denote by and the class of graphs and the class of finite graphs, respectively. Furthermore, for an ${\text {FO}}[\tau _E]$ -sentence $\varphi $ by and we denote the class of graphs (and the class of finite graphs) that are models of $\varphi $ .

2.3 Universal sentences and forbidden induced substructures

An FO-formula is universal if it is built up from atomic and negated atomic formulas by means of the connectives $\wedge $ and $\vee $ and the universal quantifier $\forall $ . Often we say that a formula containing, for example, the connective $\to $ is universal if by replacing $\varphi \to \psi $ by $\neg \varphi \vee \psi $ (and “simple manipulations”) we get an equivalent universal formula. Every universal sentence $\mu $ is equivalent to a sentence $\mu '$ of the form $\forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\, \mu ^{\prime }_0$ for some $k\ge 1$ and some quantifier-free $\mu ^{\prime }_0$ ; moreover the length $|\mu '|$ of $\mu '$ is at most $|\mu |$ . If in the definition of universal formula we replace the universal quantifier by the existential one, we get the definition of an existential formula.

One easily verifies that the class of models of a set of universal sentence is closed under induced substructures. As already mentioned in the Introduction for classes of graphs, Łoś [Reference Łoś19] and Tarski [Reference Tarski26] proved the following theorem:

Theorem 2.1 (Łoś–Tarski Theorem).

Let $\tau $ be a vocabulary and $\varphi $ an ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau ]$ -sentence. Then is closed under induced substructures if and only if $\varphi $ is equivalent to a universal sentence.

We first recall the relationship between the axiomatizability of a class of structures by a universal sentence and its definability by a finite set of forbidden finite induced substructures. We fix a vocabulary $\tau $ . Let $\mathscr {F}$ be a set of $\tau $ -structures and denote by and the class of structures (of finite structures) that do not contain an induced substructure isomorphic to a structure in $\mathscr {F}$ . Clearly for sets $\mathscr {F}$ and $\mathscr {F}'$ of $\tau $ -structures we have

(2)

Furthermore, for a class $\mathscr {C}$ of $\tau $ -structures closed under induced substructures one easily verifies that

(3)

We have put the corresponding $\mathscr {F}$ ’s in brackets as they are not sets but classes. However for $\mathscr {C}_{\text {fin}} $ we can repair this by considering only structures whose universe is an initial segment of natural numbers, i.e.,

So we see that for every class of finite structures a denumerable set $ \mathscr {F}$ suffices. When is a finite $ \mathscr {F}$ enough?

We say that a class $\mathscr {C}$ of $\tau $ -structures (of finite $\tau $ -structures) is definable by a finite set of forbidden induced finite substructures if there is a finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of finite structures such that . Recall that $\tau _E= \{E\}$ with binary E. The sentences

axiomatize the classes of directed graphs and of graphs, respectively. Define the $\tau _E$ -structures $H_0=\big (V(H_0), E(H_0)\big )$ and $H_1= \big (V(H_1), E({H_1})\big )$ by

$$ \begin{align*} V(H_0):= \{1\}, \ E(H_0):= \big\{(1, 1)\big\} \ \text{and} \ V(H_1):= \{1, 2\}, \ E(H_1):= \big\{(1, 2)\big\}. \end{align*} $$

Then and are the class of directed graphs and the class of graphs, respectively, i.e., and .

The following result (Proposition 2.2) generalizes this simple fact and establishes the equivalence between axiomatizability by a universal sentence and definability by a finite set of forbidden induced finite substructures. For an arbitrary vocabulary $\tau $ , an ${\text {FO}}[\tau ]$ -sentence $\varphi $ , and $k\ge 1$ let

Thus, $\mathscr {F}_k(\varphi )$ is, up to isomorphism, the class of structures with at most k elements that fail to be a model of $\varphi $ . Note that $\mathscr {F}_1(\varphi _{\text {DG}})= \{H_0\}$ . By (2) and (3) we have

(4)

Proposition 2.2. For a class $\mathscr {C}$ of $\tau $ -structures and $k\ge 1$ the statements (i) and (ii) are equivalent.

  1. (i) for some universal sentence $\mu := \forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\, \mu _0$ with quantifier-free $\mu _0$ .

  2. (ii) for some finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of structures, all of at most k elements.

If (i) holds for $\mu $ , then .

The main step of the proof of (ii) $\Rightarrow $ (i) is contained in the following lemma.

Lemma 2.3. Let $\mathcal A$ be a finite $\tau $ -structure and $k:= |A|$ . There is a universal sentence $\mu _{\mathcal A\not \to }= \forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\, \mu _0$ with quantifier-free $\mu _0$ such that for every $\tau $ -structure $\mathcal B$ ,

$$\begin{align*}\mathcal B\models \mu_{\mathcal A\not\to}\iff \mathcal B\ \text{has no induced substructure isomorphic to}\ \mathcal A, \end{align*}$$

i.e.,

(5)

Proof Let $A= \{a_1,\ldots , a_k\}$ . Let $\delta (x_1,\ldots , x_k)$ be the conjunction of all literals (i.e., atomic or negated atomic formulas) $\lambda (x_1, \ldots , x_k)$ such that $\mathcal A\models \lambda (a_1, \ldots , a_k)$ . Then for every $\tau $ -structure $\mathcal B$ and $b_1, \ldots , b_k\in B$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal B\models \delta(b_1, \ldots, b_k) \iff & \text{ the clauses}\ \pi(a_i)= b_i\ \text{for}\ i\in[k]\ \text{define} \\ & \qquad \text{an isomorphism from}\ \mathcal A\ \text{onto}\ [b_1,\ldots, b_k]^{\mathcal B} \end{align*} $$

(recall that $[b_1,\ldots , b_k]^{\mathcal B}$ denotes the substructure of $\mathcal B$ induced on $\{b_1,\ldots , b_k \}$ ). Thus we can set

$$\begin{align*}\mu_{\mathcal A\not\to}:= \forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\neg\delta(x_1,\ldots, x_k).\\[-32pt] \end{align*}$$

Proof of Proposition 2.2

(ii) $\Rightarrow $ (i): Let for some finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of structures, all of at most k elements. If $\mathscr {F}$ is empty, then . Otherwise, by (ii) and (5),

As the conjunction of finitely many universal sentences of the form $\forall x_1\ldots \forall x_\ell \,\mu _0$ with quantifier-free sentence $\mu _0$ and with $\ell \le k$ is equivalent to such a sentence, we get the desired result.

(i) $\Rightarrow $ (ii): Let for $\mu $ as in (i). Then is closed under induced substructures and hence, by (4). Now assume that $\mathcal A\notin \mathscr {C}$ . Then $\mathcal A\models \neg \mu $ and hence there are $a_1, \ldots , a_k\in A$ with $\mathcal A\models \neg \mu _0(a_1, \ldots , a_k)$ . For $\mathcal B:= [a_1, \ldots , a_k]^{\mathcal A}$ we have $\mathcal B\models \neg \mu _0(a_1,\ldots , a_k)$ (as $\mu _0$ is quantifier-free) and thus, $\mathcal B\models \neg \mu $ . Therefore, $\mathcal B$ is isomorphic to a structure in $\mathscr {F}_k(\mu )$ and therefore, .

Corollary 2.4. Let $\varphi $ be a $\tau $ -sentence and $k\ge 1$ . Then

By (2) and (4) we get the following corollaries:

Corollary 2.5. If for some universal $\mu $ and some $k\ge 1$ , then for all $\ell \ge k$ .

Corollary 2.6. It is decidable whether two universal sentences are equivalent.

Proof Let $\mu $ and $\mu '$ be universal sentences. W.l.o.g. we may assume that $\mu = \forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\, \mu _0$ and $\mu '= \forall x_1\ldots \forall x_\ell \, \mu ^{\prime }_0$ with $1\le k\le \ell $ and quantifier-free $\mu _0$ and $\mu ^{\prime }_0$ . By Corollaries 2.4 and 2.5, we have

Thus $\mu $ and $\mu '$ are equivalent if and only if $\mathscr {F}_\ell (\mu )= \mathscr {F}_\ell (\mu ')$ . The right-hand side of this equivalence is clearly decidable.

The last equivalence of the preceding proof shows the following:

Corollary 2.7. For universal sentences $\mu $ and $\mu '$ we have

$$\begin{align*}\mu\ \text{and}\ \mu'\ \text{are equivalent} \iff\ \mu\ \text{and}\ \mu'\ \text{are finitely equivalent.} \end{align*}$$

The next result generalizes this corollary.

Lemma 2.8. Let $\Phi $ be a set of universal sentences and $\nu $ a $\Pi _2$ -sentence, i.e., a sentence of the form $\forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\exists y_1\ldots \exists y_\ell \, \nu _0$ for some $k, \ell \in \mathbb N$ and some quantifier-free $\nu _0$ .

If $\Phi \models _{\text {fin}} \nu $ , then $\Phi \models \nu $ and thus there exists a finite $\Phi _0\subseteq \Phi $ with $\Phi _0\models _{\text {fin}} \nu $ .

Proof If not $\Phi \models \nu $ , then there is a (finite or infinite) structure $\mathcal A$ with $\mathcal A\models \Phi \cup \{\neg \nu \}$ . Note that $\neg \nu $ is equivalent to a sentence of the form

$$\begin{align*}\exists x_1\ldots \exists x_k\,\mu \end{align*}$$

with universal $\mu $ . Choose elements $a_1,\ldots , a_k$ with $\mathcal A \models \mu (a_1,\ldots , a_k)$ . Then $\mathcal B:=[a_1,\ldots , a_k]^{\mathcal A}$ is a model of $\Phi \cup \{\neg \nu \}$ and thus shows $\Phi \not \models _{\text {fin}} \nu $ .

As the class of all at most countable $\tau $ -structures shows, not every class closed under induced substructures is the class of models of a set of universal sentences. In contrast, for classes of finite structures, we have the following:

Lemma 2.9. Let $\mathscr {C}$ be a class of finite $\tau $ -structures closed under induced substructures and define the set of universal sentences $\Phi _{\mathscr {C}}$ by

Then,

Proof The first equality immediately follows from (3) using the closure of $\mathscr {C}$ under induced substructures and the second equality follows from (5).

We use the two preceding results to prove (see [Reference Gurevich17]):

Theorem 2.10 (Compton’s Theorem).

Let $\mathscr {C}$ be a class of finite $\tau $ -structures closed under induced substructures and $\mathrm{FO}$ -axiomatizable by a $\Pi _2$ -sentence $\nu $ . Then $\mathscr {C}$ is already axiomatizable by a universal sentence.

Proof By assumption and the preceding lemma, we have , in particular, $\Phi _{\mathscr {C}}\models _{\text {fin}}\nu $ . By Lemma 2.8 there is a finite subset $\Phi _0$ of $\Phi _{\mathscr {C}}$ such that $\Phi _0\models _{\text {fin}} \nu $ . Thus,

Hence, $\mathscr {C}$ is axiomatizable by the conjunction of the sentences in $\Phi _0$ , a universal sentence.

Recall that our main goal is to find a class of finite graphs with the properties (a)–(c).

  1. (a) The class is closed under induced subgraphs.

  2. (b) The class is FO-axiomatizable (by a single sentence).

  3. (c) The class is not FO-axiomatizable by a universal sentence.

Compton’s Theorem tells us that w.r.t. the quantifier prefix the simplest possible FO-axiomatization of such a class is by a $\Sigma _2$ -sentence, i.e., by a sentence of the form $\exists x_1\ldots \exists x_k\forall y_1\ldots \forall y_\ell \, \rho $ with $k,\ell \in \mathbb N$ and quantifier-free $\rho $ .

The following consequence of Corollary 2.2 will be used in the next section.

Corollary 2.11. Let $m,k\in \mathbb N$ with $m> k$ and let $\psi _0$ and $\psi _1$ be ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau ]$ -sentences. Assume that $\mathcal A$ is a finite model of $\psi _0\wedge \psi _1$ with at least m elements and all its induced substructures with at most k elements are models of $\psi _0\wedge \neg \psi _1$ . Then $\psi _0\wedge \neg \psi _1$ is not finitely equivalent to a universal sentence of the form $\mu := \forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\,\mu _0$ with quantifier-free $\mu _0$ .

Proof As there is no universal sentence $\mu $ as above for $k= 0$ , we can assume $k\ge 1$ . For a contradiction assume for $\mu := \forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\,\mu _0$ with quantifier-free $\mu _0$ . As by Proposition 2.2, we get (applying the finite equivalence of $\psi _0\wedge \neg \psi _1$ and $\mu $ to obtain the last equality)

However, by the assumptions the structure $\mathcal A$ is not contained in but in the class .

Remark 2.12. Let $\mathscr {C}$ be a class of $\tau $ -structures closed under induced substructures. For an ${\text {FO}}[\tau ]$ -sentence $\varphi $ we set . We say that the Łoś-Tarski Theorem holds for $\mathscr {C}$ if for every ${\text {FO}}[\tau ]$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that the class is closed under induced substructures there is a universal sentence $\mu $ such that . The following holds:

Let $\mathscr {C}$ and $\mathscr {C}'$ be classes of $\tau $ -structures closed under induced substructures with $\mathscr {C}'\subseteq \mathscr {C}$ . Furthermore assume that there is a universal sentence $\mu _0$ such that . If the Łoś–Tarski Theorem holds for $\mathscr {C}$ , then it holds for $\mathscr {C}'$ , too.

In fact, for every ${\text {FO}}[\tau ]$ -sentence $\varphi $ we have . Hence, if is closed under induced substructures, then by assumption there is a universal $\mu $ such that . Therefore, .

However, as examples mentioned in the Introduction show, in general the failure of the Łoś–Tarski Theorem on a class does not imply its failure on every subclass.

3 Basic ideas underlying the classical results

This section contains a proof of Tait’s Theorem telling us that the analogue of the Łoś–Tarski-Theorem fails if we only consider finite structures. Afterwards we refine the argument to derive a generalization, namely Proposition 3.11, which is a key result to get Gurevich’s Theorem.

Our counterexample to the Łoś–Tarski-Theorem on finite structures essentially is the one given by Alechina and Gurevich in [Reference Alechina and Gurevich1], which in turn simplifies the one given by Gurevich and Shelah in [Reference Gurevich17]. All these counterexamples use the main idea of the original counterexample due to Tait [Reference Tait25].

We consider the vocabulary $\tau _0:= \{<, U_{\text {min}}, U_{\text {max}}, S\}$ , where $<$ and S (the “successor relation”) are binary relation symbols and $U_{\text {min}}$ and $U_{\text {max}}$ are unary.

Let $\varphi _0$ be the conjunction of the universal sentences:

  • $\forall x \neg x< x$ , $\forall x\forall y (x<y\vee x=y\vee y<x)$ , $\forall x\forall y\forall z ((x<y\wedge y<z)\to x<z)$ , i.e., “ $<$ is an ordering.”

  • $\forall x\forall y\big (U_{\text {min}}\, x\to (x=y\vee x<y)\big )$ , i.e., “every element in $U_{\text {min}}$ is a minimum w.r.t. $<$ .”

  • $\forall x\forall y\big (U_{\text {max}}\, x\to (x=y\vee y<x)\big )$ , i.e., “every element in $U_{\text {max}}$ is a maximum w.r.t. $<$ .”

  • $\forall x\forall y(Sxy\to x<y).$

  • $\forall x\forall y\forall z((x<y\wedge y<z)\to \neg Sxz)$ .

Note that in models of $\varphi _0$ there is at most one element in $U_{\text {min}}$ , at most one in $U_{\text {max}}$ , and that S is a subset of the successor relation w.r.t. $<$ . We call the models of $\varphi _0\ \tau _0$ -orderings.

For a vocabulary $\tau $ with $<\in \tau $ and $\tau $ -structures $\mathcal A$ and $\mathcal B$ we write $\mathcal B\subseteq _< \mathcal A$ and say that $\mathcal B$ is a $<$ -substructure of $\mathcal A$ if $\mathcal B$ is a substructure of $\mathcal A$ with $<^{\mathcal B}= <^{\mathcal A}\cap \, (B\times B)$ .

We remark that the relation symbols $U_{\text {min}}, \ U_{\text {max}}$ , and S are negative in $\varphi _0$ . Therefore we have the following:

Lemma 3.1. Let $\mathcal A$ and $\mathcal B$ be $\tau _0$ -structures with $\mathcal B\subseteq _< \mathcal A$ . If $\mathcal A\models \varphi _0$ , then $\mathcal B\models \varphi _0$ .

Let

(6) $$ \begin{align} \varphi_1:=\exists x\, U_{\text{min}}\, x \wedge \exists x U_{\text{max}}\, x\wedge \forall x\forall y(x<y \to \exists z Sxz). \end{align} $$

We call models of $\varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1$ complete $\tau _0$ -orderings. Clearly, for every $k\ge 1$ there is a unique, up to isomorphism, complete $\tau _0$ -ordering with exactly k elements. The next lemma shows that all its proper $<$ -substructures are models of $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ .

Lemma 3.2. Let $\mathcal A$ and $\mathcal B$ be $\tau _0$ -structures. Assume that $\mathcal A\models \varphi _0$ and $\mathcal B$ is a finite $<$ -substructure of $\mathcal A$ that is a model of $\varphi _1$ . Then $\mathcal B= \mathcal A$ (in particular, $\mathcal A\models \varphi _1$ ).

Proof By the previous lemma we know that $\mathcal B\models \varphi _0$ . Let $B:= \{b_1, \ldots , b_n\}$ . As $<^{\mathcal B}$ is an ordering, we may assume that

$$\begin{align*}b_1<^{\mathcal B} b_2<^{\mathcal B}\dots <^{\mathcal B} b_{n-1}<^{\mathcal B} b_n. \end{align*}$$

As $\mathcal B\models (\varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1)$ , we have $U_{\text {min}}^{\mathcal B} b_1$ , $U_{\text {max}}^{\mathcal B} b_n$ , and $S^{\mathcal B} b_ib_{i+1}$ for $i\in [n-1]$ . As $\mathcal B\subseteq \mathcal A$ , everywhere we can replace the upper index $^{\mathcal B}$ by $^{\mathcal A}$ .

We show $A= B$ (then $\mathcal A= \mathcal B$ follows from $\mathcal A\models \varphi _0$ ): Let $a\in A$ . By $\mathcal A\models \varphi _0$ , we have $b_1\le ^{\mathcal A} a\le ^{\mathcal A} b_n$ . Let $i\in [n]$ be maximal with $b_i \le ^{\mathcal A} a$ . If $i= n$ , then $b_n= a$ . Otherwise, $b_i\le ^{\mathcal A} a<^{\mathcal A} b_{i+1}$ . As $S^{\mathcal A} b_ib_{i+1}$ , we see that $b_i= a$ (by the last conjunct of $\varphi _0$ ).

Corollary 3.3. Every finite proper $<$ -substructure of a model of $\varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1$ is a model of $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ .

The Łoś–Tarski Theorem does not remain valid when restricted to finite structures. In fact, the class of finite $\tau _0$ -orderings that are not complete is closed under induced substructures but not axiomatizable by a universal sentence:

Theorem 3.4 (Tait’s Theorem).

The class is closed under $<$ -substructures (and hence, closed under induced substructures) but $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ is not finitely equivalent to a universal sentence.Footnote 1

By Compton’s Theorem (Theorem 2.10) the sentence $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ is not even equivalent to a $\Pi _2$ -sentence. However, note that $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ is (equivalent to) a $\Sigma _2$ -sentence.

Proof of Theorem 3.4

is closed under $<$ -substructures: If $\mathcal A\models \varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ and $\mathcal B$ is a finite $<$ -substructure of $\mathcal A$ , then $\mathcal B\models \varphi _0$ (by Lemma 3.1). If $\mathcal B\models \neg \varphi _1$ , we are done. If $\mathcal B\models \varphi _1$ , then $\mathcal A\models \varphi _1$ by Lemma 3.2, which contradicts our assumption $\mathcal A\models \neg \varphi _1$ .

Let $k\in \mathbb N$ . It is clear that there is a finite model $\mathcal A$ of $\varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1$ with at least $k+1$ elements. By Corollary 3.3 every proper induced substructure of $\mathcal A$ is a model of $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ . Therefore, by Corollary 2.11, the sentence $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ is not finitely equivalent to a universal sentence of the form $\forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\,\mu _0$ with quantifier-free $\mu _0$ . As k was arbitrary, we get our claim.

Remark 3.5. As is closed under induced substructures but $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ is not finitely equivalent and hence not equivalent to a universal sentence, the class of finite and infinite models of $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ is not closed under induced substructures. Nevertheless, as $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1$ is equivalent to a $\Sigma _2$ -sentence, a result in [Reference Sankaran, Adsul and Chakraborty24] tells us that this class has a “local Łoś–Tarski property.” More precisely, for $k\in \mathbb N$ we say that a class $\mathscr {C}$ of $\tau $ -structures has k-cores if for every $\mathcal A\in \mathscr {C}$ there is a subset C of A of at most k elements such that every induced substructure $\mathcal B$ of $\mathcal A$ with $C\subseteq B$ is in the class $\mathscr {C}$ . Note that has 2-cores. In fact, let $\mathcal A$ be in this class. If $\mathcal A\models \neg \forall x\forall y(x<y \to \exists z Sxz)$ , then set $C= \{a,b \}$ where $a<^{\mathcal A}b$ and for all $a'\in A$ not $S^{\mathcal A}aa'$ . If $\mathcal A\models \forall x\forall y(x<y \to \exists z Sxz)$ , then choose as C the empty set.

In [Reference Sankaran, Adsul and Chakraborty24] the authors showed: Let $k\in \mathbb N$ and $\mathscr {C}$ be an FO-axiomatizable class of $\tau $ -structures. Then $\mathscr {C}$ has k-cores if and only if $\mathscr {C}$ is axiomatizable by a $\Sigma _2$ -sentence of the form $\exists x_1\ldots \exists x_k\,\mu $ with universal $\mu $ . Note that for $k= 0$ we get the Łoś–Tarski Theorem.

We turn to a refinement of Theorem 3.4 that will be helpful to get Gurevich’s Theorem.

Definition 3.6.

  1. (a) Let $\tau $ be obtained from the vocabulary $\tau _0$ by adding finitely many relation symbols “in pairs,” the standard R together with its complement $R^{{\text {comp}}}$ (intended as the complement of R). The symbols R and $R^{{\text {comp}}}$ have the same arity and for our purposes we can restrict ourselves to unary or binary relation symbols (even though all results can be generalized to arbitrary arities). We briefly say that $\tau $ is obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs.

  2. (b) Let $\tau $ be obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs. We say that $\varphi _{0\tau }\in {\text {FO}}[\tau ]$ is an extension of $\varphi _0$ (where $\varphi _0$ is as above) if it is a universal sentence such that:

    1. (i) the sentence $\varphi _0$ is a conjunct of $\varphi _{0\tau }$ ,

    2. (ii) the sentence $\bigwedge _{R \text { standard}}\forall \bar x(\neg R\bar x\vee \neg R^{{\text {comp}}}\bar x)$ is a conjunct of $\varphi _{0\tau }$ ,

    3. (iii) besides $<$ all relation symbols are negative in $\varphi _{0\tau }$ (if this is not the case for some new R or $R^{{\text {comp}}}$ , the idea is to replace any positive occurrence of R or $R^{{\text {comp}}}$ by $\neg R^{{\text {comp}}}$ and $\neg R$ , respectively). For instance, we replace a subformula

      $$ \begin{align*} x<y \wedge R xy \ \ \ \text{by} \ \ x<y \wedge \neg R^{{\text{comp}}} xy. \end{align*} $$
  3. (c) Let $\tau $ be obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs. Then we set

    $$ \begin{align*} \varphi_{1\tau}:= \varphi_1\wedge\bigwedge_{R \text{ standard}} \forall \bar x(R\bar x\vee R^{{\text{comp}}}\bar x), \end{align*} $$
    where $\varphi _1$ is as above see (6).

For a $\tau $ -structure $\mathcal B$ with $\mathcal B\models \varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }$ we have

$$\begin{align*}\mathcal B\models\bigwedge_{R \text{ standard}} \Big(\forall \bar x(\neg R\bar x\vee \neg R^{{\text{comp}}}\bar x) \wedge \forall \bar x(R\bar x\vee R^{{\text{comp}}}\bar x)\Big). \end{align*}$$

Hence, for standard $R\in \tau $ of arity r, we have

(7) $$ \begin{align} \text{if}\ \mathcal B\models \varphi_{0\tau}\wedge \varphi_{1\tau}, \text{then}\ (R^{{\text{comp}}})^{\mathcal B}=B^r\setminus R^{\mathcal B}. \end{align} $$

Now we derive the analogues of Lemma 3.1—Theorem 3.4 essentially by the same proofs. In all these results the vocabulary $\tau $ is obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs and $\varphi _{0\tau }$ is an extension of $\varphi _0$ .

Lemma 3.7. If $\mathcal B\subseteq _< \mathcal A$ and $\mathcal A\models \varphi _{0\tau }$ , then $\mathcal B\models \varphi _{0\tau }$ .

Proof By Definition 3.6, the sentence $\varphi _{0\tau }$ is universal and all relation symbols distinct from $<$ are negative in $\varphi _{0\tau }$ .

Lemma 3.8. Assume that $\mathcal A\models \varphi _{0\tau }$ and that a finite $<$ -substructure $\mathcal B$ of $\mathcal A$ is a model of $\varphi _{1\tau }$ . Then $\mathcal B= \mathcal A$ in particular, $\mathcal A\models \varphi _{1\tau }$ .

Proof Let $\mathcal A\upharpoonright \tau _0$ and $\mathcal B\upharpoonright \tau _0$ be the $\tau _0$ -structures obtained from $\mathcal A$ and from $\mathcal B$ by removing all relations in $\tau \setminus \tau _0$ . By Lemma 3.2 we know that $\mathcal B\upharpoonright \tau _0= \mathcal A\upharpoonright \tau _0$ . Furthermore, $\mathcal B\models \varphi _{0\tau }$ by the previous lemma; thus, $\mathcal B\models \varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }$ . Hence, by (7), $(R^{{\text {comp}}})^{\mathcal B}$ is the complement of $R^{\mathcal B}$ for standard R. Clearly, $R^{\mathcal B}\subseteq R^{\mathcal A}$ and $(R^{{\text {comp}}})^{\mathcal B}\subseteq (R^{{\text {comp}}})^{\mathcal A}$ . As $A= B$ and $\mathcal A$ is a model of the sentence $\bigwedge _{R \text { standard}}\forall \bar x(\neg R\bar x\vee \neg R^{{\text {comp}}}\bar x)$ , we get $R^{\mathcal B}= R^{\mathcal A}$ and $(R^{{\text {comp}}})^{\mathcal B}= (R^{{\text {comp}}})^{\mathcal A}$ .

Corollary 3.9. Every proper $<$ -substructure of a finite model of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }$ is a model of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \neg \varphi _{1\tau }$ .

By replacing in the proof of Tait’s Theorem the use of Lemma 3.1, Lemma 3.2, and Corollary 3.3 by Lemma 3.7, Lemma 3.8, and Corollary 3.9, respectively, we get the following:

Lemma 3.10. The class is closed under $<$ -substructures (and hence, closed under induced substructures) but $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \neg \varphi _{1\tau }$ is not finitely equivalent to a universal sentence.

Perhaps the reader will ask why we do not introduce for $<$ the “complement relation symbol” $<^{\text {comp}}$ and add the corresponding conjuncts to $\varphi _{0\tau }$ and $\varphi _{1\tau }$ (or, to $\varphi _0$ and $\varphi _1$ ) in order to get a result of the type of Lemma 3.8 (or already of the type of Lemma 3.2) where we can replace “ $ <$ -substructure” by “substructure.” The reader will realize that corresponding proofs of $B= A$ break down.

The next proposition, the core of the proof of Gurevich’s Theorem, provides a uniform way to construct FO-sentences that are only equivalent to universal sentences of large size.

Proposition 3.11. Again let $\tau $ be obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs and $\varphi _{0\tau }$ be an extension of $\varphi _0$ . Let $m\ge 1$ and $\gamma $ be an ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau ]$ -sentence such that

(8) $$ \begin{align} \varphi_{0\tau}\wedge \varphi_{1\tau}\wedge \gamma\ \text{has no infinite model but a finite model with at least}\ m\ \text{elements}. \end{align} $$

For $ \chi := \varphi _{0\tau }\wedge (\varphi _{1\tau }\to \neg \gamma ) $ the statements (a) and (b) hold.

  1. (a) The class is closed under $<$ -substructures.

  2. (b) If $\mu :=\forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\,\mu _0$ with quantifier-free $\mu _0$ is finitely equivalent to $\chi $ , then $k\ge m$ .

Proof (a) Let $\mathcal A\models \chi $ and $\mathcal B\subseteq _< \mathcal A$ . Thus, $\mathcal B\models \varphi _{0\tau }$ . If $\mathcal B\not \models \varphi _{1\tau }$ , we are done. Assume $\mathcal B \models \varphi _{1\tau }$ . In case B is infinite, by (8) we know that $\mathcal B$ is a model of $\neg \gamma $ and hence of $\chi $ . Otherwise, B is finite; then $\mathcal B= \mathcal A$ (by Lemma 3.8) and thus, $\mathcal B\models \chi $ .

(b) According to (8) there is a finite model $\mathcal A$ of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }\wedge \gamma $ , i.e., of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \neg (\varphi _{1\tau }\to \neg \gamma )$ , with at least m elements. By Corollary 3.9 every proper induced substructure of $\mathcal A$ is not a model of $\varphi _{1\tau }$ and therefore, it is a model of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge (\varphi _{1\tau }\to \neg \gamma )$ . Hence by Corollary 2.11, $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge (\varphi _{1\tau }\to \neg \gamma )$ is not finitely equivalent to a universal sentence of the form $\mu :=\forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\,\mu _0$ with $k< m$ and quantifier-free $\mu _0$ .

Remark 3.12. We can strengthen the statement (b) of the preceding proposition to:

If the $\Pi _2$ -sentence $\nu = \forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\exists y_1\ldots \exists y_\ell \; \nu _0$ with quantifier-free $\nu _0$ is finitely equivalent to $\chi $ , then $k\ge m$ .

In fact, assume that with $\nu $ as above. We first show that k cannot be 0. In fact, if $k= 0$ , then $\nu $ is an existential sentence. By assumption there is a finite model $\mathcal A$ of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }\wedge \gamma $ with at least m elements. Obtain the $\tau $ -structure $\mathcal B$ from $\mathcal A$ by setting $U_{\text {min}}^{\mathcal B}= U_{\text {max}}^{\mathcal B}=\emptyset $ . Clearly, then $\mathcal B\models \neg \varphi _{1\tau }$ and $\mathcal B\models \varphi _{0\tau }$ as $U_{\text {min}}$ and $U_{\text {max}}$ are negative in $\varphi _{0\tau }$ . Hence, $\mathcal B\models \chi $ and thus, $\mathcal B\models \nu $ . Let $\mathcal C$ be a finite extension of $\mathcal B$ (i.e., $\mathcal B$ is an induced substructure of $\mathcal C$ ) with an element c such that $(c,c)\in <^{\mathcal C}$ . Then, $\mathcal C\models \nu $ as $\nu $ is existential. However, $\mathcal C\models \neg \varphi _{0\tau }$ as $<^{\mathcal C}$ is not an ordering. Thus, $\mathcal C\models \neg \chi $ , a contradiction.

So we know that $k\ge 1$ and now show that implies $k\ge m$ . For a contradiction assume $k< m$ . By (8) there is a finite model $\mathcal A$ of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }\wedge \gamma $ with at least m elements. Then $\mathcal A\not \models \nu $ . Hence there are $a_1,\ldots , a_k\in A$ with $\mathcal A\models \neg \exists y_1\ldots \exists y_\ell \, \nu _0(a_1, \ldots , a_k)$ . Then $\mathcal B\models \neg \exists y_1 \ldots \exists y_\ell \, \nu _0(a_1,\ldots , a_k)$ , where $\mathcal B:= [a_1, \ldots , a_k]^{\mathcal A}$ is the substructure of $\mathcal A$ induced by $a_1, \ldots , a_k$ . Hence, $\mathcal B\not \models \nu $ and therefore, $\mathcal B\not \models \varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \neg \varphi _{1\tau }$ . As $k< m$ , the structure $\mathcal B$ is a proper induced substructure of $\mathcal A$ . Thus, $\mathcal B\models \varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \neg \varphi _{1\tau }$ by Corollary 3.9, a contradiction.

4 The general machinery: strongly existential interpretations

We show that appropriate interpretations preserve the validity of Tait’s theorem and of the statement of Proposition 3.11. Later on these interpretations will allow us to get versions of the results for graphs.

Let $\tau _E:= \{E\}$ with binary E. As already remarked in the Preliminaries for all $\tau _E$ -structures we use the notation $G= (V(G), E(G))$ common in graph theory.

Let $\tau $ be obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs. Furthermore, let $I:=(\varphi _{\text {uni}}, (\varphi _T)_{T\in \tau })$ be an interpretation of width $2$ (we only need this case) of $\tau $ -structures in $\tau _E$ -structures. This means that $\varphi _{\text {uni}}$ and the $\varphi _T $ ’s are ${\text {FO}}[\tau _E]$ -formulas with $\varphi _{\text {uni}} =\varphi _{\text {uni}}(x_1, x_2)$ , $\varphi _T= \varphi _T(x_1, x_2)$ for every unary relation symbol $T\in \tau $ , and ${\varphi _T=\varphi _T(x_1, x_2, y_1, y_2)}$ for every binary relation symbol $T\in \tau $ .

Then for every $\tau _E$ -structure G we set

$$\begin{align*}O_I(G):= \big\{\bar a\in V(G)\times V(G) {\;\big|\;} G\models \varphi_{\text{uni}}(\bar a) \big\}. \end{align*}$$

If $O_I(G)\ne \emptyset $ , i.e., if $G\models \exists \bar x\varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)$ , then the interpretation I assigns to G a $\tau $ -structure with universe $O_I(G)$ , which we denote by $\mathcal O_I(G)$ Footnote 2 , given by:

  • $T^{O_I(G)}:= \big \{\bar a\in O_I(G) {\;\big |\;} G \models \varphi _T(\bar a) \big \}$ for unary $T\in \tau .$

  • $T^{O_I(G)}:= \big \{(\bar a,\bar b)\in O_I(G)\times O_I(G) {\;\big |\;} G \models \varphi _T(\bar a, \bar b)\big \}$ for binary $T\in \tau $ .

As the interpretation I is of width $2$ , we have

(9) $$ \begin{align} |O_I(G)|\le |V(G)|^2. \end{align} $$

Recall that for every sentence $\varphi \in {\text {FO}}[\tau ]$ there is a sentence $\varphi ^I \in {\text {FO}}[\tau _E]$ such that for all $\tau _E$ -structures G with $G\models \exists \bar x\varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)$ we have

(10) $$ \begin{align} \mathcal O_I(G)\models \varphi \iff G\models \varphi^I. \end{align} $$

For example, for the sentence $\varphi = \forall x\forall y\, Txy$ we have

$$\begin{align*}\varphi^I= \forall \bar x \Big(\varphi_{{\text{uni}}}(\bar x) \to \forall \bar y \big(\varphi_{{\text{uni}}}(\bar y) \to \varphi_T(\bar x, \bar y)\big)\Big). \end{align*}$$

Furthermore there is a constant $c_I\in \mathbb N$ such that for all $\varphi \in {\text {FO}}[\tau ]$ ,

(11) $$ \begin{align} |\varphi^I|\le c_I\cdot |\varphi|. \end{align} $$

From time to time we will make use of the following lemma.

Lemma 4.1. Let $I:= \big (\varphi _{\text {uni}}, (\varphi _T)_{T\in \tau }\big )$ be an interpretation of $\tau $ -structures in $\tau _E$ -structures. For $\tau $ -sentences $\psi _1$ and $\psi _2$ ,

(12)

and the same implication holds if we restrict to finite structures, i.e.,

(13)

If for every finite $\tau $ -structure $\mathcal A$ there is a finite graph G with $\mathcal O_I(G)\cong \mathcal A$ , then

(14)

Proof The implications in (12) and (13) follow immediately from (10). We still have to show the implication from right to left in (14). So let $\mathcal A$ be a finite $\tau $ -structure. By assumption there is a finite graph G with $\mathcal O_I(G)\cong \mathcal A$ . As $A\ne \emptyset $ , we have $G\models \neg \forall \bar x\neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)$ . By the equality on the right-hand side, thus we know that $\big (G\models {\psi _1}^I\iff G\models {\psi _2}^I\big )$ . Hence, by (10), .

Definition 4.2. Let $\tau $ be obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs. An interpretation I of $\tau $ -structures in $\tau _E$ -structures is strongly existential if all formulas of I (i.e., $\varphi _T$ for $T\in \tau $ and $\varphi _{\text {uni}}$ ) are existential and in addition $\varphi _<$ is quantifier-free.

Lemma 4.3. Let $\tau $ be obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs and let $\varphi _{0\tau }$ be an extension of $\varphi _0$ . Then for every strongly existential interpretation I the sentence ${\varphi _{0\tau }}^I$ is (equivalent to) a universal sentence.

Proof The claim holds as all relation symbols distinct from $<$ are negative in $\varphi _{0\tau }$ . For example, for $\varphi := \forall x\forall y \big (U_{\text {min}}\, x\to (x=y\vee x<y)\big )$ , we have

$$\begin{align*}\varphi^I=\forall \bar x \Big(\varphi_{\text{uni}}(\bar x)\to \forall \bar y \big(\varphi_{\text{uni}}(\bar y) \to (\varphi_{U_{\text{min}}}(\bar x)\to ((x_1= y_1\wedge x_2= y_2) \vee \varphi_<(\bar x,\bar y)))\big)\Big). \end{align*}$$

The following result shows that strongly existential interpretations transform induced subgraphs into $<$ -substructures; this will be crucial to transfer the results of the preceding section to graphs.

Lemma 4.4. Assume that I is strongly existential. Then for all $\tau _E$ -structures G and H with $H\subseteq _{\text {ind}} G$ and $O_I(H)\ne \emptyset $ , we have $\mathcal O_I(H) \subseteq _< \mathcal O_I(G)$ .

Proof As $\varphi _{\text {uni}}$ is existential, we have $O_I(H)\subseteq O_I(G)$ . Let $T\in \tau $ be distinct from $<$ and $\bar b\in T^{\mathcal O_I(H)}$ . Then $H\models \varphi _T(\bar b)$ . As $\varphi _T$ is existential, $G\models \varphi _T(\bar b)$ and thus, $\bar b\in T^{\mathcal O_I(G)}$ . Moreover, for $\bar b, \bar b'\in O_I(H)$ we have

$$ \begin{align*} \bar b<^{\mathcal O_I(H)}\bar b' & \iff H\models \varphi_<(\bar b,\bar b') \\ & \iff G\models \varphi_<(\bar b,\bar b') \qquad \text{(as}\ H\subseteq_{\text{ind}} G\ \text{and}\ \varphi_<\ \text{is quantifier-free)} \\ & \iff \bar b<^{\mathcal O_I(G)}\bar b'. \end{align*} $$

Putting all together we see that $\mathcal O_I(H)\subseteq _< \mathcal O_I(G)$ .

Corollary 4.5. Assume I is strongly existential and let $\psi $ be a $\tau $ -sentence. If (resp. ) is closed under $<$ -substructures, then (resp. ) is closed under induced substructures.

Proof Let G and H be $\tau _E$ -structures, $H\subseteq _{\text {ind}} G$ , and $G\models \forall \bar x\neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)\vee \psi ^I$ . If $H\models \forall \bar x\neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)$ , we are done. Otherwise, also $G\not \models \forall \bar x\neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)$ and thus, $G\models \psi ^I$ . Hence, $\mathcal O_I(G)\models \psi $ and $\mathcal O_I(H) \subseteq _< \mathcal O_I(G)$ by the previous lemma. Therefore, by assumption, $\mathcal O_I(H)\models \psi $ and thus, $H\models \psi ^I$ .

We obtain from Lemma 3.8 the corresponding result in our framework.

Lemma 4.6. Let I be strongly existential and let $\varphi _{0\tau }$ be an extension of $\varphi _0$ . Assume that the $\tau _E$ -structure G is a model of ${\varphi _{0\tau }}^I$ and that $H\subseteq _{\text {ind}} G$ with finite $O_I(H)$ , is a model of ${\varphi _{1\tau }}^I$ . Then $\mathcal O_I(H)= \mathcal O_I(G)$ and $G\models {\varphi _{1\tau }}^I$ .

Proof As $H\models {\varphi _{1\tau }}^I$ , we have $H\models (\exists x\, U_{\text {min}}\, x)^I$ holds and thus, $O_I(H)\ne \emptyset $ . Therefore, $\mathcal O_I(H)\subseteq _< \mathcal O_I(G)$ by Lemma 4.4. By assumption and (10), $\mathcal O_I(G)\models \varphi _{0\tau }$ and $\mathcal O_I(H)\models \varphi _{1\tau }$ . As $O_I(H)$ is finite, Lemma 3.8 implies $\mathcal O_I(H)= \mathcal O_I(G)$ , and in particular $\mathcal O_I(G)\models \varphi _{1\tau }$ . Hence, $G\models {\varphi _{1\tau }}^I$ by (10).

We now prove for strongly existential interpretations two results, Proposition 4.7 corresponds to Tait’s Theorem (Theorem 3.4) and Proposition 4.8 corresponds to Proposition 3.11 (relevant to Gurevich’s Theorem).

Proposition 4.7. Assume that the interpretation I of $\tau _0$ -structures in $\tau _E$ -structures is strongly existential. Furthermore, assume that for every finite complete $\tau _0$ -ordering $\mathcal A$ , i.e., $\mathcal A\models \varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1$ , there is a finite graph G with $\mathcal O_I(G)\cong \mathcal A$ . Then for

$$\begin{align*}\varphi:= \forall \bar x\neg \varphi_{\text{uni}}(\bar x) \vee \big(\varphi_0\wedge \neg \varphi_1\big)^I \end{align*}$$

the class is closed under induced subgraphs, but $\varphi $ is not equivalent to a universal sentence in finite graphs.

Proof By Theorem 3.4, we know that is closed under $<$ -substructures. Hence, is closed under induced subgraphs by Corollary 4.5.

Now we show that for every $k\ge 1$ the sentence $\varphi $ is not equivalent in finite graphs to a sentence of the form $\mu = \forall z_1\ldots \forall z_k\,\mu _0$ with quantifier-free $\mu _0$ . Let $\mathcal A:= \big (A, <^{\mathcal A}, U_{\text {min}}^{\mathcal A}, U_{\text {max}}^{\mathcal A}, S^{\mathcal A}\big )$ be a complete $\tau _0$ -ordering with at least $k^2+1$ elements. In particular, $\mathcal A\models \varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1$ . By assumption there is a finite graph G such that $\mathcal O_I(G)\cong \mathcal A$ . Then $\mathcal O_I(G)\models \varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1$ , hence, $G\models {\varphi _0}^I\wedge {\varphi _1}^I$ . Thus $G\models \neg \varphi $ . As $|O_I(G)|= |A|\ge k^2+ 1$ , the graph G must contain more than k vertices by (9).

We want to show that every induced subgraph of G with at most k vertices is a model of $\varphi $ . Then the result follows from Corollary 2.11 for and $\psi _1:=\exists \bar x \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)\wedge {\varphi _1}^I$ .

So let H be an induced subgraph of G with at most k vertices. Clearly, $H\models {\varphi _{0}}^I$ . If $H\models \forall \bar x \neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)$ or $H\models \neg {\varphi _{1}}^I$ , we are done. Otherwise $O_I(H)\ne \emptyset $ and $H\models {\varphi _{1}}^I$ . Then, Lemma 4.6 implies $O_I(H)=O_I(G)$ . Recall $|V(H)|\le k$ , so $O_I(H)$ has at most $k^2$ elements by (9), a contradiction as $|O_I(G)|\ge k^2+1$ .

Proposition 4.8. Let $\tau $ be obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs and let $\varphi _{0\tau }$ be an extension of $\varphi _0$ . Assume that I is a strongly existential interpretation of $\tau $ -structures in $\tau _E$ -structures with the property that for every finite $\tau $ -structure $\mathcal A$ that is a model of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }$ there is a finite graph G with $\mathcal O_I(G)\cong \mathcal A$ and $G\models \psi $ .

Let $m\ge 1$ and $\gamma $ be an ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau ]$ -sentence such that

(15) $$ \begin{align} \varphi_{0\tau}\wedge \varphi_{1\tau}\wedge \gamma\ \text{has no infinite model but a finite model with at least}\ m\ \text{elements}. \end{align} $$

For

$$ \begin{align*} \rho:= \forall \bar x\neg \varphi_{\text{uni}}(\bar x) \vee \big(\varphi_{0\tau}\wedge (\varphi_{1\tau}\to \neg \gamma)\big)^I, \end{align*} $$

the statements (a) and (b) hold.

  1. (a) The class is closed under induced subgraphs.

  2. (b) If $\mu := \forall x_1\ldots \forall x_k\,\mu _0$ with quantifier-free $\mu _0$ is equivalent in finite graphs to $\rho $ , then $k^2\ge m$ .

Proof Again (a) follows from Proposition 3.11(a) by Corollary 4.5.

(b) By (15) there is a finite model $\mathcal A$ of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }\wedge \gamma $ with at least m elements. By assumption there is a finite graph G with $\mathcal O_I(G)\cong \mathcal A$ and $G\models \psi $ . Clearly, $G\models \neg \forall \bar x\neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)$ and $G\models (\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }\wedge \gamma )^I$ . Hence, $G\models \neg \rho $ . Assume that $k^2< m$ . We want to show that every induced subgraph of G with at most k elements is a model of $\rho $ . Then the claim (b) follows from Corollary 2.11 (with $\psi _0:=\forall x\, x=x$ and $\psi _1:= \neg \rho $ ).

So let H be an induced subgraph of G with at most k elements. Clearly, $H\models {\varphi _{0\tau }}^I$ . If $H\models \forall \bar x\neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x)$ or $H\models \neg {\varphi _{1\tau }}^I$ , we are done. Otherwise $O_I(H)\ne \emptyset $ and $H\models {\varphi _{1\tau }}^I$ . Then, $O_I(H)= O_I(G)$ by Lemma 4.6. This leads to a contradiction, as $O_I(H)$ has at most $k^2$ elements by (10), while $O_I(G)$ has m elements and we assumed $k^2< m$ .

Remark 4.9. (a) The result corresponding to Remark 3.12 is valid for Proposition 4.7 too.

(b) By Compton’s Theorem (Theorem 2.10) the sentence $\forall \bar x\neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x) \vee \big (\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1\big )^I$ is not equivalent to a $\Pi _2$ -sentence. However, $\forall \bar x\neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x) \vee \big (\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1\big )^I$ itself is equivalent to a $\Sigma _2$ -sentence. In fact, as all relation symbols besides $<$ are negative in $\varphi _0$ , the sentence ${\varphi _0}^I$ is universal. Moreover, as $U_{\text {min}}$ , $U_{\text {max}}$ , and S are positive in $\varphi _1$ , the sentence ${\varphi _1}^I$ (as $\varphi _1$ ) is equivalent to a $\Pi _2$ -sentence. Hence $\forall \bar x\neg \varphi _{\text {uni}}(\bar x) \vee \big (\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1\big )^I$ is equivalent to a $\Sigma _2$ -sentence.

5 Tait’s Theorem for finite graphs

We present strongly existential interpretations that allow us to get Tait’s Theorem for graphs in this section and Gurevich’s Theorem for graphs in Section 6.

We first introduce a further concept. Let G be a graph and $a,b\in V(G)$ . For $r,s\ge 3$ a path from vertex a to vertex b of length r with an s-ear is a path between a and b with a cycle of length s; one vertex of this cycle is adjacent to the vertex adjacent to b on the path; path and cycle have no vertex in common. Figure 1 is a path from a to b of length $6$ with a $4$ -ear.

Figure 1 A path of length 6 with a $4$ -ear.

Lemma 5.1. For $r,s\ge 3$ there are quantifier-free formulas $\varphi _{c,r}(x, \bar z)$ and $\varphi _{pe,r,s}(x, y, \bar z, \bar w)$ such that for all graphs G we have $:$

  1. (a) $G\models \varphi _{c,r}(a, \bar u)\iff \bar u$ is a cycle of length r containing a.

  2. (b) $G\models \varphi _{pe,r,s}(a,b,\bar u,\bar v)\iff \bar u$ is path from a to b of length r with the s-ear $\bar v$ .

Proof (a) We can take as $\varphi _{c,r}(x, z_1,\ldots , z_r)$ the formula

$$ \begin{align*} \bigwedge_{1\le i<r} Ez_iz_{i+1} \wedge Ez_rz_1 \wedge \bigwedge_{1\le i<j\le r}\neg z_i= z_j \wedge \bigvee_{i\in[r]} x=z_i. \end{align*} $$

(b) We can take as $\varphi _{pe,r,s}(x, y, z_0,\ldots , z_r, w_1, \ldots , w_s)$ the formula

$$ \begin{align*} x= z_0 \wedge y=z_r\wedge \bigwedge_{0\le i<r-1}Ez_iz_{i+1} \wedge \bigwedge_{0\le i< j\le r}&\neg z_i= z_j \wedge \bigwedge_{0\le i\le r,\ j\in[s]}\neg z_i=w_j \\ & \wedge\bigvee_{i\in [s]} (\varphi_{c,s}(w_i,w_1,\ldots, w_s) \wedge Ez_{r-1}w_i). \end{align*} $$

To understand better how we obtain the desired interpretation we first assign to every complete $\tau _0$ -ordering $\mathcal A$ , i.e., to every model of $\varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1$ , a $\tau _E$ -structure $G:= G(\mathcal A)$ that is a graph.

In a first step we extend $\mathcal A$ to a $\tau ^*_0$ -structure $\mathcal A^*$ , where $\tau ^*_0:= \tau _0\cup \{B,C, L, F\}$ in the following way. Here $B,C$ are unary and $L,F$ are binary relation symbols.

For every original (or, basic) element a, i.e., for every $a\in A$ , we introduce a new element $a'$ , the companion of a. We set

  • $A^*:= A\cup \{a' \mid a\in A\}$ ,

  • $B^{\mathcal A^*}:= A$ , $C^{\mathcal A^*}:= \{a' \mid a\in A\}$ ,

  • $L^{\mathcal A^*}:= \big \{(a,a'){\;\big |\;} a\in A\big \}, \qquad F^{\mathcal A^*}:= \big \{(a',b),(b,a') {\;\big |\;} a,b\in A,\ a<^{\mathcal A} b\big \}$ .

Note that the relation F is irreflexive and symmetric, i.e., $\big (A^*,F^{\mathcal A^*}\big )$ is already a graph, which is illustrated by Figure 2. Observe that F contains the whole information of the ordering $<^{\mathcal A}$ up to isomorphism.

Figure 2 Turning an ordering to the relation F.

We use $\mathcal A^*$ to define the desired graph $G= G(\mathcal A)$ . The vertex set $V(G)$ contains the elements of $A^*$ and the edge relation $E(G)$ contains $F^{\mathcal A^*}$ . Furthermore G contains just all the vertices and edges required by the “gadgets” introduced by the following clauses:

  • To $a\in U_{\text {min}}^{\mathcal A}$ we add a cycle of length $5$ through a, all the other vertices of the cycle are new, i.e., not in $A^*$ .

  • To $a\in U_{\text {max}}^{\mathcal A}$ we add a cycle of length $7$ through a, all the other vertices of the cycle are new.

  • To $a\in B^{\mathcal A^*}$ we add a cycle of length $9$ through a, all the other vertices of the cycle are new.

  • To $a\in C^{\mathcal A^*}$ we add a cycle of length $11$ through a, all the other vertices of the cycle are new.

  • To $(a,b)\in S^{\mathcal A}$ we add a path from a to b of length $17$ with a $13$ -ear consisting of new vertices (besides a and b).

  • To $(a,a')\in L^{\mathcal A^*}$ we add a path from a to $a'$ of length $17$ with a $15$ -ear consisting of new vertices (besides a and $a'$ ).

Hereby we meant by “add a cycle” or “add a path with an ear” that we only add the edges required by the corresponding formulas in Lemma 5.1.

To ease the discussion, we divide cycles in $G\ (= G(\mathcal A))$ into four categories.

[F-cycle] These are the cycles in $\big (A^*,F^{\mathcal A^*}\big )$ , i.e., the cycles using only edges of $F^{\mathcal A^*}$ .

[T-cycle] For every $T\in \big \{U_{{\text {min}}}, U_{{\text {max}}}, B, C\big \}$ and $a\in T^{\mathcal A}$ the cycle introduced for a is a T-cycle.

[ear-cycle] These are the cycles that are the ears on the gadgets introduced for the pairs of the relations $S^{\mathcal A^*}$ and $L^{\mathcal A^*}$ .

[mixed-cycle] All the other cycles are mixed.

For example, we get a mixed cycle if we start with $a_2$ , $a^{\prime }_0$ , $a_1$ in Figure 2 and then add the path introduced for $(a_1, a_2)\in S^{\mathcal A}$ (ignoring the ear).

A number of observations for these types of cycles are in order.

Lemma 5.2.

  1. (i) All the F-cycles are of even length.

  2. (ii) Every $U_{{\text {min}}}$ -, $U_{{\text {max}}}$ -, B-, and C-cycle is of length $5$ , $7$ , $9$ , and $11$ , respectively.

  3. (iii) Every ear-cycle is of length $13$ or $15$ .

  4. (iv) Every mixed-cycle neither uses new vertices of any T-cycle for $T\in \big \{U_{{\text {min}}}, U_{{\text {max}}}, B, C\big \}$ nor any vertex of any ear-cycle.

  5. (v) Every mixed-cycle has length at least $17$ .

Proof (i) follows easily from the fact that $\big (A^*,F^{\mathcal A^*}\big )$ is a bipartite graph; (ii) and (iii) are trivial. For (iv) assume that a mixed-cycle uses a new vertex b of a T-cycle $\mathcal C$ introduced for some $a\in T^{\mathcal A^*}$ , where $T\in \big \{U_{{\text {min}}}, U_{{\text {max}}}, B, C\big \}$ . As $\mathcal C$ is mixed, it must contain a vertex $c\notin T^{\mathcal A^*}$ . To reach b from c the mixed cycle must pass through a and hence must contain one of the two segments of $\mathcal C$ between b and a. Therefore, in order for the mixed-cycle to go back from b to c, it must also use the other segment of $\mathcal C$ between a and b. This means that it must be the T-cycle $\mathcal C$ itself, instead of a mixed one. A similar argument shows that mixed cycles do not contain vertices of any ear-cycle.

To prove (v), let $\mathcal C$ be a mixed-cycle. By (iv), $\mathcal C$ must contain all vertices of a (at least one) path introduced for a pair $(a,a')\in L^{\mathcal A*}$ or $(a,b)\in S^{\mathcal A^*}$ (ignoring the ear). As these paths have length $17$ , we get our claim.

We want to recover $\mathcal A$ (up to isomorphism) from $G(\mathcal A)$ by means of a strongly existential interpretation. Let G be any graph. First we define a $\tau _0$ -structure $\mathcal O(G)$ , possibly the “empty structure” (and then we show that $\mathcal O(G)=\mathcal O_I(G)$ for some strongly existential interpretation I). For the definitions of “cycle” and of “path with ear” see Lemma 5.1.

  • $O(G):= \big \{(a_1,a_2)\in V(G)\times V(G) {\;\big |\;} a_1\ \text {is a member of a cycle of length}\ 9, a_2\ \text {is a member} \text {of a cycle of length}\ 11, \text {and there is a path from}\ a_1\ \text{to}\ a_2\ \text {of}\\ \text{length}\ 17\ \text {with a}\ 15\text {-ear}\big \}$

  • $<^{\mathcal O(G)}:= \big \{((a_1,a_2), (b_1,b_2)) \in O(G)\times O(G) {\;\big |\;} \{a_2,b_1\}\in E(G)\big \}$

  • $U_{\text {min}}^{\mathcal O(G)}:= \big \{(a_1,a_2)\in O(G){\;\big |\;} a_1\ \text {is a member of a cycle of length}\ 5 \big \}$

  • $U_{\text {max}}^{\mathcal O(G)}:= \big \{(a_1,a_2) \in O(G){\;\big |\;} a_1\ \text {is a member of a cycle of length}\ 7\big \}$

  • $S^{\mathcal O(G)}:= \big \{((a_1,a_2),(b_1,b_2))\in O(G)\times O(G) \mid \text {there is a path from}\ a_1\ \text {to}\ b_1 \text {of length}\ 17\ \text {with a}\ 13\text {-ear} \big \}$ .

Lemma 5.3. For every complete $\tau _0$ -ordering $\mathcal A$ we have $\mathcal O(G(\mathcal A))\cong \mathcal A$ .

Proof Let $G:= G(\mathcal A)$ and $\mathcal A^+:= \mathcal O(G)$ . We claim that the mapping $h: A\to A^+$ defined by

$$\begin{align*}h(a):= (a,a') \quad \text{for}\ a\in A \end{align*}$$

is an isomorphism from $\mathcal A$ to $\mathcal A^+$ . To that end, we first prove that

$$\begin{align*}A^+= \big\{(a, a'){\;\big|\;} a\in A\big\}, \end{align*}$$

which implies that h is well defined and a bijection. For every $a\in A$ it is easy to see that $(a, a')\in O(G) \ (= A^+)$ . For the converse, let $(a_1, a_2)\in O(G)$ . In particular, $a_1$ is a member of a cycle of length $9$ . By Lemma 5.2, this must be a B-cycle that contains some $a\in A$ . Using the same argument, $a_2$ is a member of a C-cycle that contains a vertex $b'$ being the companion of some $b\in A$ . Furthermore, there is a path from $a_1$ to $a_2$ of length $17$ with a $15$ -ear. The $15$ -ear is a cycle of length $15$ . Again by Lemma 5.2 this cycle is an ear-cycle that belongs to the gadget we introduced for some $(c,c')\in L^{\mathcal A^*}$ with $c\in A$ . Then it is easy to see that $a= c= b$ . This finishes the proof that h is a bijection from A to $A^+$ .

Similarly, we can prove that h preserves all the relations.

We show that we can obtain $\mathcal O(G)$ from G by a strongly existential FO-interpretation I of width 2. We set

$$\begin{align*}\varphi_{\text{uni}}(x,x'):= \exists \bar x\exists \bar x'\exists \bar z\exists \bar w \, \eta(x,x',\bar x,\bar x',\bar z, \bar w). \end{align*}$$

Here $\eta (x,x',\bar x,\bar x',\bar z, \bar w)$ is the formula

$$\begin{align*}\varphi_{c,9}(x,\bar x)\wedge\varphi_{c,11}(x',\bar x') \wedge \varphi_{pe,17,15}(x,x'\bar z, \bar w) \end{align*}$$

that expresses “ $\bar x$ is a cycle of length $9$ containing x, $\bar x'$ is a cycle of length $11$ containing $x'$ , and $\bar z$ is a path from x to $x'$ of length $17$ with the $15$ -ear $\bar w$ .” Furthermore we define:

  • $\varphi _<(x,x',y,y'):= Ex'y$ ,

  • $\varphi _{U_{\text {min}}}(x,x'):= \exists \bar z\, \varphi _{c,5}(x,\bar z)$ ,

  • $\varphi _{U_{\text {max}}}(x,x'):= \exists \bar z\, \varphi _{c,7}(x,\bar z)$ ,

  • $\varphi _S(x,x',y,y'):= \exists \bar z \exists \bar w \varphi _{pe,17,13}(x,y,\bar z,\bar w)$ .

Then we have the following:

Lemma 5.4. $I:= (\varphi _{\text {uni}}, \varphi _<, \varphi _{U_{\text {min}}}, \varphi _{U_{\text {max}}}, \varphi _S)$ is a strongly existential interpretation of $\tau _0$ -structures in $\tau _E$ -structures. For every complete $\tau _0$ -ordering $\mathcal A$ we have $\mathcal O_I(G(\mathcal A))= \mathcal O(G(\mathcal A))$ and hence, by Lemma 5.3,

$$\begin{align*}\mathcal O_I(G(\mathcal A))\cong \mathcal A. \end{align*}$$

We get from Proposition 4.7:

Theorem 5.5 (Tait’s Theorem for graphs).

There is a $\tau _E$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that , the class of finite graphs that are models of $\varphi $ , is closed under induced subgraphs but $\varphi $ is not equivalent to a universal sentence in finite graphs.

In this section we presented a strongly existential interpretation of $\tau _0$ -structures in $\tau _E$ -structures (more precisely, in graphs) and applied it to finite complete $\tau _0$ -orderings, i.e., to models of $\varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1$ . A straightforward generalization of the preceding proofs allows us to show the following result for vocabularies obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs. We shall use it in Section 6.

Lemma 5.6. Let $\tau $ be obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs. There is a strongly existential interpretation $I\ (=I_\tau )$ that for every extension $\varphi _{0\tau }$ of $\varphi _0$ assigns to every $\tau $ -structure $\mathcal A$ that is a model of $\varphi _{0\tau }\wedge \varphi _{1\tau }$ a graph $G(\mathcal A)$ with $\mathcal O_I(G(\mathcal A))\cong \mathcal A$ . For finite $\mathcal A$ the graph $G(\mathcal A)$ is finite.

Proof We get the graph $G(\mathcal A)$ as in the case $\tau := \tau _0$ : For the elements of new unary relations we add cycles such that the lengths of the cycles are odd and distinct for distinct unary relations in $\tau $ . Let c be the maximal length of these cycles. Then we add paths with ears to the tuples of binary relations as above. For distinct binary relations the ears should have distinct length and again this length should be odd and greater than c. On the other hand, the length of added new paths can be the same for all binary relations but should be greater than the length of all the cycles.

Remark 5.7. (a) Let be the class of finite directed graphs. Then , the class of finite graphs, is a subclass of $\mathscr {C}$ closed under induced substructures and definable in $\mathscr {C}$ by the universal sentence $\forall x \forall y(Exy\to Eyx)$ . As the Łoś–Tarski Theorem fails for the class of finite graphs, it fails for the class of directed graphs by Remark 2.12.

(b) Let be the class of finite planar graphs, a subclass of closed under induced subgraphs. As mentioned in the Introduction, in [Reference Atserias, Dawar and Grohe2] it is shown that the Łoś–Tarski Theorem fails for . As is not axiomatizable in by a universal sentence, not even by a first-order sentence, we do not get the failure of the Łoś–Tarski Theorem for the class of finite graphs (i.e., Theorem 5.5) by applying the result of Remark 2.12. We show that for a finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of finite graphs (or, equivalently, for a universal $\mu $ ) leads to a contradiction. Let k be the maximum size of the set of vertices of graphs in $\mathscr {F}$ . Let G be the graph obtained from the clique $K_5$ of five vertices by subdividing each edge $k+1$ times. Clearly, . However, every subgraph of G induced on at most k vertices is planar. Hence, .

(c) Let $\tau $ be any vocabulary with at least one at least binary relation T. Then the Łoś–Tarski Theorem fails for the class , the class of all finite $\tau $ -structures. By Remark 2.12 it suffices to show the existence of a universally definable subclass $\mathscr {C}'$ of $\mathscr {C}$ which “essentially is the class of graphs.” We set

$$\begin{align*}\mu:=\forall x\forall \bar u\neg Txx\bar u \wedge\forall x\forall y \forall\bar u\forall\bar v (Txy\bar u\to Tyx\bar v) \wedge\bigwedge_{R\in\tau,\ R\ne T}\forall \bar u \neg R\bar u \end{align*}$$

and let $\mathscr {C}'$ be .

If $\tau $ only contains unary relation symbols, the Łoś–Tarski Theorem holds for . It is easy to see for an ${\text {FO}}(\tau )$ -sentence $\varphi $ that the closure under induced substructures of implies that of .

6 Gurevich’s Theorem

The following discussion will eventually lead to a proof of Gurevich’s Theorem, i.e., Theorem 1.5. Our proof essentially follows Gurevich’s proof in [Reference Gurevich17], but it contains some elements of Rossman’s proof of the same result in [Reference Rossman22].Footnote 3 Afterwards we show that it remains true if we restrict ourselves to graphs.

Our main tool is Proposition 3.11: the goal is to construct a formula $\gamma $ satisfying (8) and whose size is much smaller than the number m. Basically $\gamma $ will describe a very long computation of a Turing machine on a short input. We fix a universal Turing machine M operating on a one-way infinite tape, the tape alphabet is $\{0, 1\}$ , where $0$ is also considered as blank and Q is the set of states of M. The initial state is $q_0$ and $q_h$ is the halting state; thus $q_0, q_h\in Q$ and we assume that $q_0\ne q_h$ . An instruction of M has the form

$$\begin{align*}qapbd, \end{align*}$$

where $q, p\in Q$ , $a,b\in \{0, 1\}$ and $d\in \{-1, 0, 1\}$ . It indicates that if M is in state q and the head of M reads an a, then M changes to state p, the head replaces a by b and moves to the left (if $d= -1$ ), stays still (if $d= 0$ ), or moves to the right (if $d= 1$ ). In order to describe computations of M by FO-formulas we introduce binary predicates $H_q(x,t)$ for $q\in Q$ to indicate that at time t the machine M is in state q and the head scans cell x, and a binary predicate $C_0(x,t)$ to indicate that the content of cell x at time t is 0.

The vocabulary $\tau _M$ is obtained from $\tau _0$ by adding pairs (see Definition 3.6(a)),

$$\begin{align*}\tau_M:= \tau_0\cup \big\{H_q, H_q^{\text{comp}} {\;\big|\;} q\in Q\big\} \cup \big\{C_0, C_0^{\text{comp}}\big\}. \end{align*}$$

Intuitively, $H_q^{\text {comp}}(x,t)$ says that “at time t the machine is not in state q or the head does not scan cell x;” and $C_0^{\text {comp}}(x,t)$ says that “at time t the content of cell x is (not 0 and thus is) 1.” Sometimes we write $C_1$ instead of $C_0^{\text {comp}}$ (e.g., below in $\varphi _2$ if $a= 1$ or $b= 0$ ).

Let $\varphi _0$ and $\varphi _1$ be the sentences already introduced in Section 3. For $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ the sentence $\varphi _{0w}$ will be an extension of $\varphi _0$ (compare Definition 3.6(b)). Hence, $\varphi _{0w}$ will be a universal sentence and all relations symbols besides $<$ are negative in $\varphi _{0w}$ ; in particular, it contains as conjuncts $\varphi _0$ and

$$\begin{align*}\forall x\forall t \big(\neg C_0(x,t) \vee \neg C^{\text{comp}}_0(x,t)\big) \wedge \bigwedge_{q\in Q} \forall x\forall t \big(\neg H_q(x,t)\vee \neg H_q^{\text{comp}}(x,t)\big). \end{align*}$$

Finally, $\varphi _{0w}$ will contain the following sentences $\varphi _2$ and $\varphi _w$ as conjuncts. The sentence $\varphi _2$ describes one computation step. It contains for each instruction of M one conjunct. For example, the instruction $qapb1$ contributes the conjunct

$$ \begin{align*} \forall x \forall x'\forall t \forall t' \forall y \Big(\big(H_{q}&(x,t) \wedge C_a (x,t) \wedge S(x,x')\wedge S(t,t')\big) \\ \to \Big( &(\neg C_{1-b}(x,t') \wedge \neg H^{\text{comp}} _{p}(x',t')) \\ & \wedge (y\ne x'\to \bigwedge_{r\in Q}\neg H_r(y,t')) \\ & \wedge (y\ne x\to((C_0(y,t)\to \neg C^{\text{comp}}_0(y,t')) \wedge (C^{\text{comp}}_0(y,t)\to\neg C_0(y,t'))))\Big)\Big). \end{align*} $$

For $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ the sentence $\varphi _w$ describes the initial configuration of M with input w (if $w= w_1\ldots w_{|w|}$ , the first $|w|$ cells (if present) contain $w_1, \ldots , w_{|w|}$ , the remaining cells contain $0$ , and the head scans the first cell in the starting state $q_0$ ). Taking into account that models of $\varphi _0\wedge \varphi _1$ might contain less than $|w|$ elements, as $\varphi _w$ we can take the conjunction of

  • $\forall x_1\ldots \forall x_{|w|}\big ((U_{\text {min}}\, x_1\to \neg C_{1-w_1}(x_1,x_1)) \\[2mm] {\hspace {2.3cm}}\wedge \bigwedge _{i\in [|w|-1]}(S{x_i}x_{i+1} \to \neg C_{1-w_{i+1}}(x_{i+1},x_1)) \big )$

  • $\forall x_1\ldots \forall x_{|w|}\forall x\big ((U_{\text {min}}\, x_1\wedge \bigwedge _{i\in [|w|-1]}S{x_i}x_{i+1}\wedge x_{|w|}<x)\to \neg C^{\text {comp}}_{0}(x,x_1)\big )$

  • $\forall x\forall y\big (U_{\text {min}}\, x\to (\neg H_{q_0}^{\text {comp}}(x,x)\wedge (y\ne x\to \bigwedge _{q\in Q}\neg H_q(y,x)))\big )$ .

Note that besides $<$ all relation symbols of $\tau _M$ are negative in $\varphi _{0w}$ . We set $\varphi _{1M}:=\varphi _{1\tau _M}$ ; recall that by Definition 3.6(c),

(16) $$ \begin{align} \varphi_{1M}= \varphi_1\wedge\forall x\forall t \big(C_0(x,t)\vee C^{\text{comp}}_0(x,t)\big) \wedge \bigwedge_{q\in Q}\forall x\forall t \big(H_q(x,t)\vee H_q^{\text{comp}}(x,t)\big). \end{align} $$

Let $w\in \{0,1\}^*$ and $r\in \mathbb N$ . Furthermore, let $\mathcal A$ be a $\tau _M$ -structure where $<^{\mathcal A}$ is an ordering and $|A|\ge r+1$ . Let $a_0, \ldots , a_r$ be the first $r+1$ elements of $<^{\mathcal A}$ . Assume that M on the input $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ runs at least r steps. We say that $\mathcal A$ correctly encodes r steps of the computation of M on w if for $i,j$ with $0\le i,j\le r$ ,

(17) $$ \begin{align} (a_i,a_j)\in C_0^{\mathcal A} \iff \text{the content of cell}\ i\ \text{after}\ j\ \text{steps is 0} \end{align} $$

and for $q\in Q$ ,

(18) $$ \begin{align} (a_i,a_j)\in H_q^{\mathcal A} \iff \text{after}\ j\ \text{steps}\ M\ \text{is in state}\ q\ \text{and the head scans cell}\ i. \end{align} $$

Lemma 6.1. Let $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ and $r\in \mathbb N$ .

  1. (a) Let $\mathcal A\models \varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi _{1M}$ and $r+1\le |A|$ (this holds if A is infinite). If M on w runs at least r steps, then $\mathcal A$ correctly encodes r steps of the computation of M on w.

  2. (b) There is a finite model of $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi _{1M}$ with $r+1$ elements. If M runs at least r steps, then this model is unique up to isomorphism.

Proof (a) holds by the definitions of $\varphi _{0w}$ and $\varphi _{1M}$ . For (b) let $A=\{a_0, \ldots , a_r\}$ with pairwise distinct $a_i$ ’s. Assume first that M on w runs at least r steps. We can interpret (17) and (18) as defining relations $C_0^{\mathcal A}$ and $H_q^{\mathcal A}$ on A equipped with the “natural” ordering and its corresponding relations $U_{{\text {min}}}$ , $U_{{\text {max}}}$ , and S. If furthermore we let $(C^{\text {comp}}_0)^{\mathcal A}$ and $(H_q^{\text {comp}})^{\mathcal A}$ be the complements in $A\times A$ of $C_0^{\mathcal A}$ and $H_q^{\mathcal A}$ , respectively, we get a model of $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi _{1M}$ with $r+1$ elements. By (a), this model is unique up to isomorphism.

If M on input w halts, say in $h(w)$ steps, with $h(w)< r$ , we get a model $\mathcal A$ of $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi _{1M}$ with $A= \{0, 1, \ldots , r\}$ , for example “by repeating the configuration reached after $h(w)$ steps”. This means, if T is any of the relations $C_0,H_q,C_0^{\text {comp}}, H_q^{\text {comp}}$ , we set for j with $h(w)<j\le r$ and $i=0,\ldots , r$ ,

$$\begin{align*}(i,j)\in T^{\mathcal A}\iff (i,h(w))\in T^{\mathcal A}.\\[-35pt] \end{align*}$$

Let $\gamma _M$ be a sentence expressing that “M reaches the halting state $q_h$ in exactly ‘ ${\text {max}}$ ’ steps,” e.g., we let $\gamma _M$ be

(19) $$ \begin{align} \exists t\exists x \big(U_{\text{max}} t \wedge H_{q_h}(x,t)\wedge \forall t'\forall y (t'< t\to \neg H_{q_h}(y,t'))\big). \end{align} $$

As a consequence of the preceding lemma, we obtain the following:

Corollary 6.2. Let $w\in \{0,1\}^*$ and set

$$ \begin{align*} \pi_w:=\varphi_{0w}\wedge \varphi_{1M}\wedge \gamma_M. \end{align*} $$

  1. (a) If M on w does not halt, then $\pi _w$ has no finite model.

  2. (b) Assume M on w eventually halts, say in $h(w)$ steps. Then $\pi _w$ has a unique model up to isomorphism. This model is finite and has exactly $h(w)+1$ elements.

We set

(20) $$ \begin{align} \chi_w:=\varphi_{0w}\wedge (\varphi_{1M}\to\neg \gamma_M). \end{align} $$

Applying Proposition 3.11 to part (b) of the preceding corollary, we get the following:

Lemma 6.3. Let M on w halt in $h(w)$ steps. Then $:$

  1. (a) is closed under $<$ -substructures.

  2. (b) If $\chi _w$ is finitely equivalent to a universal sentence $\mu $ , then $|\mu | \ge h(w)+1$ .

Now we show the following version of Gurevich’s Theorem.

Theorem 6.4. Let $f: \mathbb N\to \mathbb N$ be a computable function. Then there is a $w\in \{0,1\}^*$ such that is closed under $<$ -substructures (and hence equivalent to a universal sentence) but $\chi _w$ is not finitely equivalent to a universal sentence of length less than $f(|\chi _w|)$ .

Note that by Corollary 2.7 the conclusion of this theorem is only apparently stronger than “ $\chi _w$ is not equivalent to a universal sentence of length less than $f(|\chi _w|)$ .” A similar remark applies to Theorem 6.6.

Proof of Theorem 6.4

By the previous lemma it suffices to find a $w\in \{0,1\}^*$ such that M on input w halts in $h(w)$ steps with

$$\begin{align*}h(w)\ge f( |\chi_w|). \end{align*}$$

W.l.o.g. we assume that f is increasing. An analysis of the formula $\chi _{w}$ shows that for some $c_M\in \mathbb N$ we have for all $w\in \{0,1\}^*$ ,

(21) $$ \begin{align} |\chi_w|\le c_M\cdot |w|. \end{align} $$

We define $g:\mathbb N\to \mathbb N$ by

$$ \begin{align*} g(k):= f(5\cdot c_M\cdot k). \end{align*} $$

Let $M_0$ be a Turing machine computing g, more precisely, the function $1^k\mapsto 1^{g(k)}$ . We code $M_0$ and $1^k$ by a $\{0, 1\}$ -string $\textit {code}(M_0,1^k)$ such that M on $\textit {code}(M_0,1^k)$ simulates the computation of $M_0$ on $1^k$ .

Choose the least k such that for $w:= \textit {code}(M_0,1^k)$ we have

(22) $$ \begin{align} |w|\le 5k. \end{align} $$

The universal Turing machine M on input w computes $1^{g(k)}$ and thus runs at least $g(k)$ steps, say, exactly $h(w)$ steps. By (21) and (22)

$$\begin{align*}h(w)\ge g(k)= f(5\cdot c_M\cdot k)\ge f(c_M\cdot |w|)\ge f(|\chi_w|).\\[-34pt] \end{align*}$$

Finally we prove Gurevich’s Theorem for graphs. For $\tau := \tau _M$ let I be an interpretation according to Lemma 5.6. For $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ we consider the sentence

(23) $$ \begin{align} \rho_w:= \forall \bar x\neg \varphi_{\text{uni}}(\bar x) \vee (\varphi_{0w}\wedge (\varphi_{1M}\to \neg \gamma_M))^I = \forall \bar x\neg \varphi_{\text{uni}}(\bar x)\vee {\chi_w}^I. \end{align} $$

That is, for $G\models \rho _w$ , either the graph G interprets an “empty $\tau _M$ -structure,” or a $\tau _M$ -structure that is a model of $\chi _w$ . If M halts in $h(w)$ steps on input w, then $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi _{1M}\wedge \gamma _M$ has no infinite model but a finite model with $h(w)+1$ elements by Corollary 6.2(b). Hence, by Proposition 4.8 we get the following analogue of Lemma 6.3.

Lemma 6.5. Let M on input w halt in $h(w)$ steps. Then $:$

  1. (a) , the class of graphs that are models of $\rho _w$ , is closed under induced subgraphs.

  2. (b) If $\rho _w$ is equivalent in the class of finite graphs to the universal sentence $\mu $ , then $|\mu |^2 \ge h(w)$ .

Theorem 6.6 (Gurevich’s Theorem for graphs).

Let $f:\mathbb N\to \mathbb N$ be a computable function. Furthermore, let $\rho _w$ be defined by (23), where I is an interpretation for $\tau := \tau _M$ according to Lemma 5.6. Then there is a $w\in \{0,1\}^*$ such that is closed under induced subgraphs (and hence equivalent in the class of graphs to a universal sentence) but $\rho _w$ is not equivalent in the class of finite graphs to a universal sentence of length less than $f(|\rho _w|)$ .

Proof Again we assume that f is increasing. By the previous lemma it suffices to find a $w\in \{0,1\}^*$ such that M on input w halts in $h(w)$ steps with

$$\begin{align*}h(w)\ge f( |\rho_w|)^2. \end{align*}$$

There is a $c\in \mathbb N$ , which depends on I but not on w, such that for $c_I$ as in (11) and $c_M$ as in (21) we have for $d_M:= c+ c_I\cdot c_M$ ,

(24) $$ \begin{align} |\rho_w|\le c+ c_I \cdot |\chi_w|\le c+ c_I\cdot c_M \cdot |w|\le d_M\cdot |w|. \end{align} $$

We define $g:\mathbb N\to \mathbb N$ by

(25) $$ \begin{align} g(k):= f(5\cdot d_M\cdot k)^2 \end{align} $$

and then proceed as in the proof of Theorem 6.4. Let $M_0$ be a Turing machine computing the function $1^k\mapsto 1^{g(k)}$ . We code $M_0$ and $1^k$ by a $\{0, 1\}$ -string $\textit {code}(M_0,1^k)$ such that M on $\textit {code}(M_0,1^k)$ simulates the computation of $M_0$ on  $1^k$ .

Choose the least k such that for $w:= \textit {code}(M_0,1^k)$ we have

(26) $$ \begin{align} |w|\le 5k. \end{align} $$

The universal Turing machine M on input w computes $1^{g(k)}$ and thus runs at least $g(k)$ steps, say, exactly $h(w)$ steps. We have

$$\begin{align*}h(w)\ge g(k)= f(5\cdot d_M\cdot k)^2\ge f(d_M\cdot |w|)^2\ge f( |\rho_w|)^2 \end{align*}$$

by (24)–(26).

Remark 6.7. Using previous remarks (Remarks 3.12 and 4.9) one can even show that for every computable function $f: \mathbb N\to \mathbb N$ the sentence $\chi _w$ is not finitely equivalent to a $\Pi _2$ -sentence of length less than $f(|\chi _w|)$ and the sentence $\rho _w$ is not finitely equivalent in graphs to a $\Pi _2$ -sentence of length less than $f(|\chi _w|)$ . Moreover, $\chi _w$ and $\rho _w$ are equivalent to $\Sigma _2$ -sentences. To verify this note that in models of $\varphi _{0w}$ the sentence $\gamma _M$ is equivalent to

$$\begin{align*}\exists t\exists x \big(U_{\text{max}} t \wedge H_{q_h}(x,t)\big) \wedge \forall t_1\forall t_2\forall y \big(t_1<t_2\to \neg H_{q_h}(y,t_2)\big), \end{align*}$$

and hence equivalent to a $\Sigma _2$ and to a $\Pi _2$ -sentence. One easily verifies that the same holds for $\gamma _M^I$ .

7 Some undecidable problems

In this section we show that various problems related to the results of the preceding sections are undecidable. Among others, these results explain why it might be hard, in fact impossible in general, to algorithmically obtain forbidden induced subgraphs for various classes of graphs.

A simple application of Gurevich’s Theorem for graphs yields:

Proposition 7.1. There is no algorithm that applied to any ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau _E]$ -sentence $\varphi $ decides whether the class is closed under induced subgraphs.

Proof Assume $\mathbb A$ is such an algorithm. By the Completeness Theorem there is an algorithm $\mathbb B$ that assigns to every sentence $\varphi $ such that is closed under induced subgraphs a universal sentence equivalent to $\varphi $ in graphs. Define the function g by

$$\begin{align*}g(\varphi):= \begin{cases} 0, & \text{if}\ \mathbb A\ \text{rejects}\ \varphi, \\ m, & \mathbb B\text{ needs}\ m\text{ steps to produce a universal sentence equivalent to}\ \varphi\ \text{in graphs,} \end{cases} \end{align*}$$

and set $f(k):= {\text {max}}\{g(\varphi )\mid |\varphi |\le k\}$ . Then f would contradict Theorem 6.6.

Corollary 7.2. There is no algorithm that applied to any ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau _E]$ -sentence $\varphi $ either reports that is not closed under induced subgraphs or it computes for a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs.

Proof Otherwise we could use this algorithm as a decision algorithm for the previous result.

The following proposition is the analogue of Proposition 7.1 for classes of finite graphs. We state it for ${\text {FO}}[\tau _E]$ -sentences and graphs even though we prove it for ${\text {FO}}[\tau _M]$ -sentences. One gets the version for graphs using the machinery we developed in previous sections similarly as we get Corollary 7.5 along the lines of the proof of Proposition 7.4.

We write $M: w\mapsto \infty $ for the universal Turing machine M and a word $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ if M on input w does not halt. We make use of the sentences $\varphi _{0w}$ , $\varphi _{1M}$ , and $\gamma _M$ defined in the previous section.

Proposition 7.3. There is no algorithm that applied to any ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau _E]$ -sentence $\varphi $ decides whether the class is closed under induced subgraphs.

Proof For the universal Turing machine M and a word $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ consider the sentence

$$\begin{align*}\pi_w=\varphi_{0w}\wedge \varphi_{1M}\wedge \gamma_M \end{align*}$$

introduced in Corollary 6.2. Then

(27)

In fact, if $M: w\mapsto \infty $ , then (see Corollary 6.2(a)), hence is trivially closed under induced substructures. If M on input w halts after $h(w)$ steps, then, up to isomorphism, there is a unique model $\mathcal A_w$ of $\pi _w$ and it has $h(w)+ 1$ elements (see Corollary 6.2(b)). Take an induced substructure of $\mathcal A_w$ with $h(w)$ elements (note that $h(w)\ge 1$ ). Hence this substructure is not a model of $\pi _w$ and thus is not closed under induced substructures. As the halting problem for every universal Turing machine is not decidable, by (27) we get our claim.

Proposition 7.4. There is no algorithm that applied to any ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau _M]$ -sentence that is finitely equivalent to a universal sentence computes such a universal sentence.

Proof Assume that there exists such an algorithm $\mathbb A$ . It suffices to show for every $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ the statements (a) and (b) for

$$\begin{align*}\chi_w= \varphi_{0w}\wedge (\varphi_{1M}\to \neg \gamma_M) \end{align*}$$

defined in (20).

  1. (a) for some universal $\mu $ .

  2. (b) .

Then we can decide the halting problem for M by checking whether the universal sentence produced by the claimed algorithm $\mathbb A$ is finitely equivalent to the universal sentence $\varphi _{0w}$ . This can be decided effectively by Corollaries 2.6 and 2.7, which leads to a contradiction.

If M halts on w, say in $h(w)$ steps, then we get (a) by Lemma 6.3(a) and the Łoś–Tarski Theorem. Furthermore, by Corollary 6.2(b) we know that there is a finite structure with $h(w)+1$ elements that is a model of $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi _{1M}\wedge \gamma _M$ and thus of $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \neg \chi _w$ . Hence this structure is a model of $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \neg \mu $ . In particular, $\mu $ (and hence, $\chi _w$ ) is not finitely equivalent to $\varphi _{0w}$ . Thus, also (b) holds if M halts on w.

If $M: w\to \infty $ , then we show that (this implies (a) and (b) in this case). Clearly, . Now let $\mathcal A$ be a finite model of $\varphi _{0w} $ . If $\mathcal A\not \models \varphi _{1M}$ , then $\mathcal A\models \chi _w$ . Otherwise $\mathcal A \models \varphi _{1M}$ and then $\mathcal A$ correctly represents the first $|A|-1$ steps of the computation of M on w by Lemma 6.1. Thus $\mathcal A$ is a model of $\neg \gamma _M$ as M does not halt on w. Therefore, $\mathcal A$ is a model of $\chi _w$ .

Corollary 7.5. There is no algorithm that applied to any ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau _E]$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that has a finite set of forbidden induced finite subgraphs computes such a set.

Proof Equivalently we show that there is no algorithm that applied to any ${\text {FO}}[\tau _E]$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that for some universal sentence $\mu $ computes such a $\mu $ .

For graphs let $I\ (=I_{\tau _M})$ be a strongly existential interpretation of $\tau _M$ -structures in graphs according to Lemma 5.6. For $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ we consider the sentence

$$\begin{align*}\rho_w= \forall \bar x\neg \varphi_{\text{uni}}(\bar x)\vee {\chi_w}^I \end{align*}$$

defined in (23) and show (a’) and (b’), the analogues of (a) and (b) of the preceding proof.

  1. (a’) for some universal $\mu $ .

  2. (b’) .

Then we get the claim of the corollary arguing as in the previous proof.

(a’) holds by Lemma 6.5(a).

By Lemma 5.6 for every finite $\tau _M$ -structure $\mathcal A$ there is a finite graph G with $\mathcal O_I(G)\cong \mathcal A$ . Therefore,

Observe that Corollary 7.5 is precisely Theorem 1.3 as stated in the Introduction. Finally we prove Theorem 1.2, which is equivalent to the following result.

Theorem 7.6. There is no algorithm that applied to an ${\mathrm{FO}}[\tau _E]$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that is closed under induced subgraphs decides whether there is a finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of finite graphs such that

Proof Again we prove the corresponding result for $\tau _M$ -sentences and $\tau _M$ -structures and leave it to the reader to translate it to graphs as in the previous proof. That is, we show:

There is no algorithm that applied to an ${\text {FO}}[\tau _M]$ -sentence $\varphi $ such that is closed under induced substructures decides whether there is a finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of $\tau _M$ -structures such that

For $w\in \{0, 1\}^*$ set

$$\begin{align*}\alpha_w:= \varphi_{0w}\wedge (\varphi_{1M}\to \gamma_M). \end{align*}$$

It suffices to show that is closed under induced substructures and that

$$ \begin{align*} M: w\to \infty \iff \alpha_w\ \text{is not finitely equivalent to a universal sentence}. \end{align*} $$

Assume first that $M: w\to \infty $ . Then $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi _{1M}\wedge \gamma _M$ has no finite model by Lemma 6.1(a) and the definition (19) of $\gamma _M$ . Therefore, . By Lemma 6.1(b) the sentence $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \neg \varphi _{1M}$ has arbitrarily large finite models. Recall that $\varphi _{0w}$ is an extension of $\varphi _0$ and $\varphi _{1M}= \varphi _{1\tau _M}$ (see (16)). Hence, by Lemma 3.10, we know that is closed under induced substructures but not finitely equivalent to a universal sentence.

Now assume that M on input w halts in $h(w)$ steps. Then Corollary 6.2(b) guarantees that there is a unique model $\mathcal A_w$ of $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi _{1M}\wedge \gamma _M$ ; moreover, ${|A_w|= h(w)+1}$ . We present a finite set $\mathscr {F}$ of finite $\tau _M$ -structures such that

(28)

As $\varphi _{0w}$ is universal, there is a finite set $\mathscr {F}_0$ of finite $\tau _M$ -structures such that

We define the sets $\mathscr {F}_1$ and $\mathscr {F}_2$ as follows: For every $\tau _M$ -structure $\mathcal B$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal B\in\mathscr{F}_1\qquad \ \text{iff }\qquad \mathcal B\models \varphi_{0w}\wedge\varphi_{1M} \text{\ and}\ B= [\ell]\ \text{for some}\ \ell\le h(w), \end{align*} $$
$$ \begin{align*} \mathcal B\in\mathscr{F}_2 \qquad \text{\ iff\ }\qquad \mathcal B\models \varphi_{0w}\wedge \varphi^*_{1M} \wedge \forall t \forall t'(t< t'\to \forall y \neg H_{q_h}(y,t)) \text{\ and} \ B= [h(w)+2]. \end{align*} $$

Here $\varphi ^*_{1M}$ is obtained from $\varphi _{1M}$ by replacing the conjunct $\varphi _1$ see (6) by

$$\begin{align*}\varphi^*_1:= \exists x U_{\text{min}} x\wedge \forall x\forall y(x<y\to\exists z Sxz). \end{align*}$$

The difference is that $\varphi ^*_1$ does not require the set $U_{{\text {max}}}$ to be nonempty. Hence, $\varphi ^*_{1M}$ is the conjunction of $\varphi ^*_1$ with

$$\begin{align*}\forall x\forall t\big((C_0(x,t)\vee C^{\text{comp}}_0(x,t)) \wedge \bigwedge_{q\in Q}(H_q(x,t)\vee H_q^{\text{comp}}(x,t))\big). \end{align*}$$

Note that Lemma 6.1(a) remains true if in its statement we replace $\varphi _{1M}$ by $\varphi ^*_{1M}$ .

For $\mathscr {F}:= \mathscr {F}_0\cup \mathscr {F}_1\cup \mathscr {F}_2$ we show (28). Assume first that a finite structure $\mathcal C$ is a model of $\alpha _w$ . In particular, $\mathcal C\models \varphi _{0w}$ and therefore, $\mathcal C$ has no induced substructure isomorphic to a structure in $\mathscr {F}_0$ .

Now, for a contradiction suppose that $\mathcal B$ is an induced substructure of $\mathcal C$ isomorphic to a structure in $\mathscr {F}_1$ . Then $\mathcal B\models \varphi _{1M}$ and thus, by Lemma 3.8, $\mathcal C= \mathcal B$ . As $\mathcal C\models \alpha _w$ , we get $\mathcal C\models \varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi _{1M}\wedge \gamma _M$ . Hence, $\mathcal C\cong \mathcal A_w$ , a contradiction, as on the one hand $|C|= |B|\le h(w)$ and on the other hand $|C|= |A_w|= h(w)+1$ .

Next we show that $\mathcal C$ has no induced substructure $\mathcal B$ isomorphic to a structure in $\mathscr {F}_2$ . As $\mathcal B\models \varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi ^*_{1M}$ and has $h(w)+2$ elements, the first $h(w)+1$ elements of $\mathcal B$ correctly encode the first $h(w)$ steps of the computation of M on w, hence the full computation. As $|B|= h(w)+2$ , this contradicts $\mathcal B\models \forall t \forall t' \big (t<t'\to \forall y\neg H_{q_h}(y,t)\big )$ .

As the final step let . We show that $\mathcal C\models \alpha _w$ . As any structure in $\mathcal C$ does not contain structures in $\mathscr {F}_0$ as induced substructures, we see that $\mathcal C\models \varphi _{0w}$ . If $\mathcal C\not \models \varphi _{1M}$ , we are done.

Recall that by Lemma 6.1(a) (more precisely, by the extension of Lemma 6.1(a) mentioned above) for finite models $\mathcal B$ of $\varphi _{0w}\wedge \varphi ^*_{1M}$ we know:

  1. (a) if $|B|\le h(w)+1$ , then $\mathcal B$ encodes $|B|- 1$ steps of the computation of M on w,

  2. (b) if $|B|> h(w)+1$ , then the first $h(w)+1$ elements in the ordering $<^{\mathcal B}$ correctly encode the (full) computation of M on w.

Now assume that $\mathcal C\models \varphi _{1M}$ , then (a) and (b) apply to $\mathcal C$ . As no structure in $\mathscr {F}_1$ is isomorphic to an induced substructure of $\mathcal C$ , we see that $|C|\ge h(w)+1$ . But $\mathcal C$ cannot have more than $h(w)+1$ elements, as otherwise the substructure of $\mathcal C$ induced on the first $h(w)+2$ elements would be isomorphic to a structure $\mathcal B$ in $\mathscr {F}_2$ , a contradiction. Hence, $|C|= h(w)+1$ and thus, $\mathcal C\models \alpha _w$ .

Remark 7.7. Mainly using Remark 6.7 one easily verifies that in all results but Proposition 7.3 of this section we can replace:

$$\begin{align*}\text{There is no algorithm that applied to an}\ {\text{FO}}[\tau_E]\text{-}\text{sentence}\ \varphi \ldots \end{align*}$$

by

$$\begin{align*}\text{There is no algorithm that applied to a}\ {\Sigma}_2\text{-}\text{sentence}\ \varphi\ \ldots. \end{align*}$$

In Proposition 7.3 we have to replace it by:

$$\begin{align*}\text{There is no algorithm that applied to a}\ {\Pi}_2\text{-}\text{sentence}\ \varphi \ldots \end{align*}$$

as $\varphi _{1M}$ (and $\varphi ^I_{1M}$ ) are $\Pi _2$ -sentences.

7.1 Open problem

The main result of this paper shows that the analogue of the Łoś–Tarski Theorem fails for the class of finite graphs. That is, there exist FO-axiomatizable classes of finite graphs closed under induced subgraphs that are not definable by a finite set of forbidden induced subgraphs. Often in graph theory one considers subgraphs instead of induced subgraphs. It is known that FO-axiomatizable classes of finite and infinite graphs are closed under subgraphs if and only if they are definable by a finite set of forbidden finite subgraphs. However, to the best of our knowledge it is still open whether FO-axiomatizable classes of finite graphs closed under subgraphs are definable by a finite set of forbidden subgraphs.

Acknowledgment

We thank Abhisekh Sankaran for mentioning to the first author the question of whether Tait’s Theorem generalizes to graphs (see also [Reference Sankaran23]).

Funding

The collaboration of the authors is funded by the Sino-German Center for Research Promotion (GZ 1518). Yijia Chen is supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (Project 62372291). He also likes to express his gratitude to Hong Xu and Liqun Zhang for offering a very cordial working environment at Fudan through the difficult year of 2020.

Footnotes

1 As already mentioned, Tait showed this result in [Reference Tait25] for a sentence different from $\varphi _0\wedge \neg \varphi _1 $ .

2 As for the interpretations I and the graphs G we are interested in, the structure $\mathcal O_I(G)$ is an ordered structure, we use the notation $\mathcal O_I(G)$

3 The reader of [Reference Gurevich17] will realize that the definition of $\varphi ^n$ on page 190 of [Reference Gurevich17] must be modified in order to ensure that the class of models of $\varphi ^n$ is closed under induced substructures.

References

Alechina, N. and Gurevich, Y., Syntax vs. semantics on finite structures , Structures in Logic and Computer Science, A Selection of Essays in Honor of Andrzej Ehrenfeucht (J. Mycielski, G. Rozenberg, and A. Salomaa, editors), Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 1261, Springer, Berlin, 1997, pp. 1433.Google Scholar
Atserias, A., Dawar, A., and Grohe, M., Preservation under extensions on well-behaved finite structures . SIAM Journal on Computing , vol. 38 (2008), pp. 13641381.10.1137/060658709CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chen, Y. and Flum, J., FO-definability of shrub-depth . 28th EACSL Annual Conference on Computer Science Logic, CSL 2020 , 13–16 January 2020, Schloss Dagstuhl - Leibniz-Zentrum für Informatik, Barcelona, Spain, 2020, pp. 115.Google Scholar
Chen, Y. and Flum, J., Forbidden induced subgraphs and the Łoś–Tarski theorem . 36th Annual ACM/IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, LICS 2021 . IEEE, 2021, pp. 113.Google Scholar
Dawar, A., Grohe, M., Kreutzer, S., and Schweikardt, N., Model theory makes formulas large . Automata, Languages and Programming, 34th International Colloquium, ICALP 2007 , Springer, Wroclaw, Poland, 9–13 July 2007, 2007, pp. 913924.Google Scholar
Dawar, A. and Sankaran, A., Extension preservation in the finite and prefix classes of first order logic . 29th EACSL Annual Conference on Computer Science Logic, CSL 2021 , LIPIcs, 183, Schloss Dagstuhl - Leibniz-Zentrum für Informatik, 2021, pp. 118.Google Scholar
Ding, G., Subgraphs and well-quasi-ordering . Journal of Graph Theory , vol. 16 (1992), no. 5, pp. 489502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downey, R. G. and Fellows, M. R., Parameterized Complexity , Springer, New York, 1999.10.1007/978-1-4612-0515-9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duris, D., Extension preservation theorems on classes of acyclic finite structures . SIAM Journal on Computing , vol. 39 (2010), no. 8, pp. 36703681.10.1137/080744463CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dvorák, Z., Giannopoulou, A. C., and Thilikos, D. M., Forbidden graphs for tree-depth . European Journal of Combinatorics , vol. 33 (2012), no. 5, pp. 969979.10.1016/j.ejc.2011.09.014CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ebbinghaus, H.-D. and Flum, J., Finite Model Theory , Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Springer, Berlin, 1999.Google Scholar
Fellows, M. R., Private communication, 2019.Google Scholar
Fellows, M. R. and Langston, M. A., On search, decision, and the efficiency of polynomial-time algorithms . Journal of Computer and System Sciences , vol. 49 (1994), no. 3, pp. 769779.10.1016/S0022-0000(05)80079-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gajarský, J. and Kreutzer, S., Computing shrub-depth decompositions . 37th International Symposium on Theoretical Aspects of Computer Science, STACS 2020 , Schloss Dagstuhl - Leibniz-Zentrum für Informatik, 2020, pp. 156.Google Scholar
Ganian, R., Hlinený, P., Nesetril, J., Obdrzálek, J., and Ossona de Mendez, P., Shrub-depth: Capturing height of dense graphs . Logical Methods in Computer Science , vol. 15 (2019), no. 1, pp. 7:17:25.Google Scholar
Ganian, R., Hlinený, P., Nesetril, J., Obdrzálek, J., de Mendez, P. Ossona, and Ramadurai, R., When trees grow low: Shrubs and fast ${}_1$ . Mathematical Foundations of Computer Science 2012 – 37th International Symposium, MFCS 2012 , Springer, Bratislava, Slovakia, 27–31 August 2012, 2012, pp. 419430.Google Scholar
Gurevich, Y., Toward logic tailored for computational complexity . Lecture Notes in Mathematics , vol. 1104 (1984), pp. 175216.10.1007/BFb0099486CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lopez, A., When locality meets preservation . LICS’22: 37th Annual ACM/IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, 2022 , ACM, 2022, pp. 146.Google Scholar
Łoś, J., On the extending of models I . Fundamenta Mathematicae , vol. 42 (1955), pp. 3854.10.4064/fm-42-1-38-54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKee, T. A., Forbidden subgraphs in terms of forbidden quantifiers . Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic , vol. 19 (1978), pp. 186188.10.1305/ndjfl/1093888225CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rossman, B., Homomorphism preservation theorems . Journal of the ACM , vol. 55 (2008), no. 3, pp. 115.10.1145/1379759.1379763CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rossman, B., Łoś–Tarski Theorem has non-recursive blow-up , Unpublished manuscript, 2012, pp. 12.Google Scholar
Sankaran, A., Revisiting the generalized Łoś–Tarski Theorem . Logic and Its Applications - 8th Indian Conference, ICLA 2019 , Delhi, 1–5 March 2019, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 11600, Springer, 2019, pp. 7688.Google Scholar
Sankaran, A., Adsul, B., and Chakraborty, S., A generalization of the Łoś–Tarski preservation theorem . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 167 (2016), no. 3, pp. 189210.10.1016/j.apal.2015.11.001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tait, W. W., A counterexample to a conjecture of Scott and Suppes, this Journal, vol. 24 (1959), no. 1, pp. 15–16.Google Scholar
Tarski, A., Contributions to the theory of models I–II . Indagationes Mathematicae , vol. 16 (1954), pp. 572588.10.1016/S1385-7258(54)50074-0CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaught, R., Remarks on universal classes of relational systems . Indagationes Mathematicae , vol. 16 (1954), pp. 589591.10.1016/S1385-7258(54)50076-4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zaslavsky, T., Forbidden induced subgraphs . Electronic Notes in Discrete Mathematics , vol. 63 (2017), pp. 310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 A path of length 6 with a $4$-ear.

Figure 1

Figure 2 Turning an ordering to the relation F.