Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-29T02:09:42.151Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

COMPLETE BIPARTITE PARTITION RELATIONS IN COHEN EXTENSIONS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 June 2023

DÁVID UHRIK*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF ALGEBRA FACULTY OF MATHEMATICS AND PHYSICS CHARLES UNIVERSITY SOKOLOVSKÁ 83 186 75 PRAHA 8, CZECH REPUBLIC and INSTITUTE OF MATHEMATICS OF THE CZECH ACADEMY OF SCIENCES ŽITNÁ 25, 115 67 PRAGUE 1 CZECH REPUBLIC E-mail: uhrik@karlin.mff.cuni.cz
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We investigate the effect of adding $\omega _2$ Cohen reals on graphs on $\omega _2$, in particular we show that $\omega _2 \to (\omega _2, \omega : \omega )^2$ holds after forcing with $\mathsf {Add}(\omega , \omega _2)$ in a model of $\mathsf {CH}$. We also prove that this result is in a certain sense optimal as $\mathsf {Add}(\omega , \omega _2)$ forces that $\omega _2 \not \to (\omega _2, \omega : \omega _1)^2$.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

Since Ramsey’s result [Reference Ramsey10] that every infinite graph contains an infinite clique or an infinite independent set the area of partition relations has been very active. However, any straightforward generalizations of his result are bound to fail; the classical result of Sierpiński [Reference Sierpiński11] states that: ${2^\kappa } \not \to ({\kappa ^+})^2$ . Nevertheless there are ways to generalize Ramsey’s result.

Dushnik and Miller showed in [Reference Dushnik and Miller2] that the relation ${\kappa } \to ({\kappa }, {\omega })^2$ always holds. Our notation for partition relations is standard; the reader unfamiliar with the arrow notation can find definitions in Section 1.1.

Most questions concerning partition relations on ${\omega _1}$ have been answered. Considering the order type of the clique Erdős and Rado [Reference Erdős and Rado3] improved the previous result to ${{\omega _1}} \to ({{\omega _1}}, {\omega +1})^2$ . By a result of Hajnal [Reference Hajnal4] their result is optimal as $\mathsf {CH}$ implies ${{\omega _1}} \not \to ({{\omega _1}}, {\omega +2})^2$ . The best possible relation ${{\omega _1}} \to ({{\omega _1}}, {\alpha })^2$ for any countable ordinal $\alpha $ may consistently hold as shown by Todorčević in [Reference Todorčević12].

The case of ${\omega _2}$ is far from being resolved. Erdős and Rado’s previous result extends also to ${\omega _2}$ , i.e., ${{\omega _2}} \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega + 1})^2$ in $\mathsf {ZFC}$ , but they also showed [Reference Erdős and Rado3] that $\mathsf {CH}$ implies ${{\omega _2}} \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega _1 + 1})^2$ ; on the other hand ${{\omega _2}} \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega _1})^2$ already implies $\mathsf {CH}$ . If on top of $\mathsf {CH}$ we further assume $2^{\omega _1}={\omega _2}$ , we are limited by $\omega _1 + 1$ , i.e., ${{\omega _2}} \not \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega _1 + 2})^2$ holds. Rather surprisingly Laver [Reference Laver8] showed that $\mathsf {MA} + 2^\omega = {\omega _2}$ implies ${{\omega _2}} \not \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega + 2})^2$ .

If we weaken the assumption on the homogeneous set there are further results. Baumgartner [Reference Baumgartner1] showed that after adding ${\omega _2}$ Silver reals via countable support product to a model of $\mathsf {CH}$ we obtain a model where ${{\omega _2}} \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega : {\omega _2}})^2$ .

Our results are in a similar vein as Baumgartner’s, instead of looking for a clique in a graph with no cofinal independent set we will be searching only for bipartite graphs. Our results can be seen as showing how much of the partition relation ${{\omega _2}} \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega _1})^2$ remains after adding Cohen reals. We will prove that ${{\omega _2}} \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega : \omega })^2$ holds after forcing with $\mathsf {Add}(\omega , {{\omega _2}})$ in a model of $\mathsf {CH}$ . On the other hand the same conclusion as in the Silver model cannot hold after adding Cohen reals as $\mathsf {Add}(\omega , {{\omega _2}}) \Vdash {\omega _2} \not \to ({\omega : \omega _1})^2$ .

Our main results are in a more general setting covering also the case of adding $\lambda ^+$ many Cohen subsets of $\kappa $ for $\kappa , \lambda $ regular and its effect on the analogous partition relations. In particular we also get that ${\omega _3} \to ({\omega _3}, {\omega _1 : \omega _1})^2$ holds after adding $\omega _3$ Cohen subsets of ${\omega _1}$ to a model of $\mathsf {GCH}$ .

Notation

We use standard set theoretic notation. If X is a set and $\mu $ a cardinal, then $[X]^\mu := \left \{ {Y \subseteq X \mid |Y| = \mu } \right \}$ . For two sets $X,Y$ we define $X \otimes Y := \left \{ {\{x,y\} \mid x \in X \land y \in Y} \right \}$ . If $X,Y$ are subsets of some ordered set, then $X<Y$ means that each element of X lies below each element of Y. $\mathsf {H}(\kappa )$ denotes the collection of all sets hereditarily of cardinality less than $\kappa $ ; these sets will be used for constructing suitable elementary submodels; for more on this subject we refer the reader to [Reference Just and Weese5, Chapter 24]. A collection of sets forms a $\Delta $ -system if there is a fixed set r such that the intersection of any two sets in the collection is exactly r. By $\mathrm {ot}(X)$ we mean the order type of a well-ordered set X.

A graph G is a pair $(V,E)$ , where V is an arbitrary set and $E \subseteq [V]^2$ . A subset $X \subseteq V$ is complete if $[X]^2 \subseteq E$ . An independent set in G is a subset X of V such that $[X]^2 \cap E$ is empty. If the vertex set of the graph is well-ordered and $\alpha $ and $\beta $ are ordinals, then a subgraph (sometimes referred to as configuration) of type $(\alpha : \beta )$ is one whose vertex set is $A \cup B$ , where A has order type $\alpha $ and B has order type $\beta $ , $A<B$ and $A \otimes B \subseteq E$ .

Given ordinals $\alpha , \beta , \gamma $ the partition relation ${\alpha } \to ({\beta }, {\gamma })^2$ is the statement that given a function $c: [\alpha ]^2 \to 2$ there is a subset X of $\alpha $ such that either the order type of X is $\beta $ and $c"[X]^2 = \{0\}$ or the order type of X is $\gamma $ and $c"[X]^2 = \{1\}$ . The weaker relation ${\alpha } \to ({\beta }, {\gamma : \delta })^2$ says that for every function $c: [\alpha ]^2 \to 2$ either there is an $X \subseteq \alpha $ such that the order type of X is $\beta $ and $c"[X]^2 = \{0\}$ or there are sets $X,Y \subseteq \alpha $ such that $X<Y$ , the order type of X is $\gamma $ , the order type of Y is $\delta $ , and $c"[X \otimes Y] = \{1\}$ .

By a slight abuse of notation we will write $c(\alpha , \beta )$ instead of $c(\{\alpha , \beta \})$ and when writing $c(\alpha , \beta )$ we also tacitly assume that $\alpha < \beta $ if a natural ordering is present. The notation ${\alpha } \to ({\beta }, {\gamma })^2$ is shortened to ${\alpha } \to ({\beta })^2$ , when $\beta = \gamma $ .

Each function $c : [\alpha ]^2 \to 2$ defines a graph on $\alpha $ , namely $(\alpha , c^{-1}[\{1\}])$ . Thus it will sometimes be convenient to talk about arbitrary functions on $\alpha $ and instead of looking for homogeneous sets for the coloring we can consider independent sets and cliques, i.e., we can rephrase the notion of partition relations as follows: for ordinals $\alpha , \beta , \gamma $ the partition relation ${\alpha } \to ({\beta }, {\gamma })^2$ says that given any graph whose vertex set is $\alpha $ and there is no independent set of order type $\beta $ we can find a complete subgraph of order type $\gamma $ . The relation ${\alpha } \to ({\beta }, {\gamma : \delta })^2$ says that every graph on $\alpha $ either has an independent set of order type $\beta $ or a subgraph of type $(\gamma : \delta )$ .

Suppose $\kappa \le \lambda $ are cardinals, the forcing for adding $\lambda $ many Cohen subsets of $\kappa $ will be denoted $\mathsf {Add}({\kappa }, {\lambda })$ , its underlying set is $\left \{ {p : \lambda \to 2 \mid |p|<\kappa } \right \}$ , and the ordering is reverse inclusion (see [Reference Kunen6] for an introduction to independence proofs in set theory).

2 Positive result

As the central tool of this section will be double $\Delta $ -systems let us review a classical result about the existence of $\Delta $ -systems. The proof can be found in [Reference Kunen6].

Theorem 2.1 ( $\Delta $ -system lemma).

Suppose $\kappa $ is an infinite cardinal, $\lambda> \kappa $ is regular, for each $\alpha < \lambda $ we have $|\alpha ^{<\kappa }| < \lambda $ , and $\mathcal {A}$ is a collection of sets such that $|\mathcal {A}| \ge \lambda $ . If for all $x \in \mathcal {A}$ we have $|x|<\kappa $ , then there is a $\mathcal {B} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ , such that $|\mathcal {B}| = \lambda $ and $\mathcal {B}$ forms a $\Delta $ -system.

Double $\Delta $ -systems were introduced by Todorčević in [Reference Todorčević13] and utilized also in other papers. For an application in a similar context see [Reference Todorčević14, Theorem 3.3]. A nice exposition on double $\Delta $ -systems and their higher analogues can be found in [Reference Lambie-Hanson7].

Definition 2.2. Let $\Gamma $ be a set of ordinals and $D := \left \{ {p_{\alpha \beta } \mid \left \{ {\alpha , \beta } \right \} \in [\Gamma ]^2} \right \}$ a collection of sets. We say that D is a double $\Delta $ -system with root $p^0 \cup p^1$ if the following holds:

  1. (1) For every $\alpha \in \Gamma \left \{ {p_{\alpha \beta } \mid \beta \in \Gamma \setminus (\alpha + 1)} \right \}$ is a $\Delta $ -system with root $p^0_\alpha $ .

  2. (2) For every $\beta \in \Gamma \left \{ {p_{\alpha \beta } \mid \alpha \in \Gamma \cap \beta } \right \}$ is a $\Delta $ -system with root $p^1_\beta $ .

  3. (3) $\{p^0_\alpha \mid \alpha \in \Gamma \}$ is a $\Delta $ -system with root $p^0$ .

  4. (4) $\{p^1_\beta \mid \beta \in \Gamma \}$ is a $\Delta $ -system with root $p^1$ .

Remark. In our case the sets $p_{\alpha \beta }$ will be conditions in the Cohen forcing. The notation $p_{\alpha \beta }$ implicitly assumes that $\alpha < \beta $ . Note also that the conditions on the double $\Delta $ -system ensure that $\bigcap \{p_{\alpha \beta } \mid \{\alpha ,\beta \} \in [\Gamma ]^2\} = p^0 = p^1$ .

We will define the notion of isomorphism between forcing conditions.

Definition 2.3. Given $p,q \in \mathsf {Add}({\kappa }, {\lambda })$ we define the set $\mathrm {type}(p)$ as the sequence $(p_i)_{i < \mu }$ , where $\mu = \mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(p))$ and $(p_i)_{i < \mu }$ is an enumeration of the values of p as a sequence respecting the ordering of its domain. Conditions $p,q$ are isomorphic, $p \simeq q$ , if $\mathrm {type}(p) = \mathrm {type}(q)$ .

The type of a pair, $\mathrm {type}(p,q)$ , is defined again as a sequence $(s_i)_{i < \eta }$ , where $\eta = \mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(p) \cup \mathrm {dom}(q))$ and if $(r_i)_{i < \eta }$ is an enumeration of $\mathrm {dom}(p) \cup \mathrm {dom}(q)$ respecting the ordering, then $s_i = (v_p^i, v_q^i)$ , where if $r_i \in \mathrm {dom}(p)$ , then $v_p^i = p(r_i)$ , else $v_p^i = 2$ ; analogously for $v_q^i$ . Two pairs of conditions $(p,q), (r,s)$ are isomorphic, $(p,q) \simeq (r,s)$ , if $\mathrm {type}(p,q) = \mathrm {type}(r,s)$ .

Remark. The sets $\mathrm {type}(p)$ and $\mathrm {type}(p,q)$ just record all information about a condition (a pair of conditions). In other words it codes them as structures. Also note that $\mathrm {type}(p,q) = \mathrm {type}(r,s)$ implies the equality of types coordinate-wise, i.e., $\mathrm {type}(p) = \mathrm {type}(r)$ and $\mathrm {type}(q) = \mathrm {type}(s)$ .

In further applications we will need a more uniform version of $\Delta $ -systems of conditions.

Lemma 2.4. Suppose $\kappa < \lambda $ are regular cardinals, $|2^\mu | < \lambda $ for all $\mu < \kappa $ , and $\left \{ {p_\alpha \mid \alpha < \lambda } \right \}$ is a set of conditions in $\mathsf {Add}({\kappa }, {\lambda ^+})$ forming a $\Delta $ -system. There are an $X \in [\lambda ]^\lambda $ and an $s \subseteq \mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(p_0))$ such that $:$

  1. (1) for all $\alpha , \beta \in X$ we have $\mathrm {type}(p_\alpha ) = \mathrm {type}(p_\beta )$ , and

  2. (2) for all $\alpha \in X$ if $(d_i \mid i < \mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(p_\alpha )))$ is an increasing enumeration of the domain of $p_\alpha $ , then $\{ (d_i, p_\alpha (d_i)) \mid i \in s \}$ is exactly the root of the original $\Delta $ -system.

Proof The proof is a routine counting argument.

To ensure that the types of all the conditions are the same note that the order type of the domain of any condition from $\mathsf {Add}({\kappa }, {\lambda ^+})$ is an ordinal below $\kappa $ . Let $f:\lambda \to \kappa $ be a function such that $f(\alpha )=\mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(p_\alpha ))$ . As $\kappa < \lambda $ and $\lambda $ is regular we get a $\gamma _0 < \kappa $ and an $A \in [\lambda ]^\lambda $ such that the order type of the domain of $p_\alpha $ is $\gamma _0$ for all $\alpha \in A$ . Next consider each function from $\gamma _0$ to $2$ . As $2^{\gamma _0} < \lambda $ , there is less than $\lambda $ many such functions. Given a condition $p_\alpha $ for $\alpha \in A$ let $\varphi _{\alpha }: \gamma _0 \to \mathrm {dom}(p_\alpha )$ be the unique increasing bijection and define a function $g: \lambda \to 2^{\gamma _0}$ such that $g(\alpha ) = p_\alpha \circ \varphi _\alpha $ . As before there are an $A' \in [A]^\lambda $ and a fixed function $q: \gamma _0 \to 2$ such that $\mathrm {type}(p_\alpha ) = q$ for each $\alpha \in A'$ .

To make sure that the relative position of the root of the $\Delta $ -system stays the same across all conditions define another function $h: \lambda \to 2^{\gamma _0}$ such that $h(\alpha )(\beta ) = 1$ if and only if $(\varphi _\alpha (\beta ), p_\alpha (\varphi _\alpha (\beta ))$ is in the root of the $\Delta $ -system. Analogously as before we find a function $r: \gamma _0 \to 2$ such that for $\lambda $ many $\alpha $ we have $h(\alpha ) = r$ , and this ensures the second condition.

Lemma 2.5. Suppose $\gamma _0 \le \gamma _1$ are ordinals and $\left \{ {p_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma _0} \right \}$ , $\left \{ {q_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma _1} \right \}$ are sets of conditions in $\mathsf {Add}({\kappa }, {\lambda })$ . If $\left \{ {q_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma _1} \right \}$ forms a $\Delta $ -system and for each $\alpha < \beta < \gamma _0$ we have $(p_\alpha , p_\beta ) \simeq (q_\alpha , q_\beta )$ , then $\left \{ {p_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma _0} \right \}$ also forms a $\Delta $ -system.

Proof First enumerate in increasing order the domain of $q_0$ as $(d_i \mid i < \mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(q_0)))$ . As the conditions $\left \{ {q_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma _1} \right \}$ are isomorphic and form a $\Delta $ -system let s be the set of indices $i < \mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(q_0))$ such that $\left \{ {(d_i, q_0(d_i)) \mid i \in s} \right \}$ is exactly the root.

If we similarly enumerate the domain of $p_0$ as $(e_i \mid i < \mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(p_0)))$ (note that $\mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(q_0)) = \mathrm {ot}(\mathrm {dom}(p_0))$ ), we claim that $\left \{ {(e_i, p_0(e_i)) \mid i \in s} \right \}$ is the root of the $\Delta $ -system formed by the conditions $\left \{ {p_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma _0} \right \}$ .

Given any $p_\alpha $ and $p_\beta $ as this pair is isomorphic to the pair $(q_\alpha , q_\beta )$ we have that $d_i \in \mathrm {dom}(q_\alpha ) \cap \mathrm {dom}(q_\beta )$ if and only if $e_i \in \mathrm {dom}(p_\alpha ) \cap \mathrm {dom}(p_\beta )$ and this happens exactly when $i \in s$ , also when $d_i \in \mathrm {dom}(q_\alpha ) \cap \mathrm {dom}(q_\beta )$ then $d_i$ is also the i-th element of the domain of both $q_\alpha $ and $q_\beta $ and the same holds for $e_i$ and any $p_\alpha $ and $p_\beta $ . Finally as the conditions $\left \{ {q_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma _1} \right \}$ are isomorphic so are $\left \{ {p_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma _0} \right \}$ so in particular $p_\alpha \simeq p_0 \simeq p_\beta $ and we are done.

The main theorem follows.

Theorem 2.6. Suppose $\kappa < \lambda $ are regular cardinals. If $\lambda ^{<\lambda } = \lambda $ and for each $\alpha < \lambda $ we have $|\alpha ^{<\kappa }| < \lambda $ , then $\mathsf {Add}({\kappa }, {\lambda ^+})$ forces the relation ${\lambda ^+} \to ({\lambda ^+}, {\mu : \mu })^2$ for any $\mu < \kappa ^+$ .

Proof Consider the extension by the Cohen forcing adding $\lambda ^+$ subsets of $\kappa $ . Fix a condition q and a name $\dot {c}$ such that q forces that in the extension c is a function from $[\lambda ^+]^2$ to $2$ . Without loss of generality we will assume that $q=\emptyset $ . If it is the case that

$$ \begin{align*}\emptyset \Vdash \exists X \in [\lambda^+]^{\lambda^+} : \dot{c}"[X]^2 = \{0\}\end{align*} $$

we are done, so suppose this is not the case. Now an improved double $\Delta $ -system can be found.

The proof of the following claim closely resembles the argument in [Reference Todorčević14, Theorem 3.3], where Todorčević constructs a double $\Delta $ -system of Cohen conditions with analogous properties but he considers colorings with range $\omega $ . Todorčević used this technique already in [Reference Todorčević13].

Claim 1. There are a set $X \in [\lambda ^+]^{\lambda }$ of order type $\lambda $ and a set of conditions $D := \left \{ {p_{\alpha \beta } \in \mathsf {Add}({\kappa }, {\lambda ^+}) \mid \left \{ {\alpha , \beta } \right \} \in [X]^2} \right \}$ such that the following holds $:$

  1. (1) $p_{\alpha \beta } \Vdash \dot {c}(\alpha , \beta ) = 1$ .

  2. (2) D forms a double $\Delta $ -system.

Proof In the ground model for every $\alpha < \beta $ in $\lambda ^+$ either $\emptyset \Vdash \dot {c}(\alpha , \beta ) = 0$ or there is a condition p such that $p \Vdash \dot {c}(\alpha , \beta ) = 1$ . For every pair fulfilling the second option fix such a condition $p_{\alpha \beta }$ , otherwise put $p_{\alpha \beta } := \emptyset $ . Consider a regular cardinal $\theta $ large enough so that $\mathsf {H}(\theta )$ contains all the relevant objects we have considered so far. Choose an elementary submodel M of $\mathsf {H}(\theta )$ of size $\lambda $ such that $M^{<\lambda } \subseteq M$ (we assume $\lambda ^{<\lambda } = \lambda $ in the ground model) and $\delta := M \cap \lambda ^+$ has cofinality $\lambda $ . Fix also a $\lambda $ -sequence converging to $\delta $ , say $(d_\alpha \mid \alpha < \lambda )$ .

Subclaim 1. There is a set, B, cofinal in $\delta $ of order type $\lambda $ with the following properties for every $\alpha < \beta < \gamma $ in $B:$

  1. (1) $p_{\alpha \beta } \simeq p_{\alpha \delta }$ .

  2. (2) $p_{\alpha \beta }\restriction \beta = {p_{\alpha \delta }}\restriction {\delta }$ .

  3. (3) $(p_{\alpha \gamma }, p_{\beta \gamma }) \simeq (p_{\alpha \delta }, p_{\beta \delta })$ .

  4. (4) $\mathrm {dom}({p_{\alpha \beta }}) \subseteq \gamma $ .

  5. (5) $p_{\alpha \beta } \Vdash \dot {c}(\alpha , \beta ) = 1$ .

  6. (6) $p_{\alpha \delta } \Vdash \dot {c}(\alpha , \delta ) = 1$ .

Proof The set B cannot be an element of M, but any initial segment of such a set B belongs to M because M is closed under sequences of length $<\lambda $ , and this will be used in the inductive construction. Suppose we have constructed an initial segment of B, a sequence $b := (b_\xi \mid \xi < \beta )$ for some ordinal $\beta < \lambda $ satisfying all the conditions, and $b_\alpha \ge d_\alpha $ for all $\alpha < \beta $ . We want to construct $b_\beta $ above $d_\beta $ . Note that $b \in M$ as the sequence has length $<\lambda $ , and also $d_\beta \in M$ . Consider the following sequences/matrices for every $\eta \in \lambda ^+ \setminus d_\beta $ :

$$ \begin{align*} S_1^\eta &:= (\mathrm{type}(p_{\alpha \eta}) \mid \alpha \in b), \\ S_2^\eta &:= ({p_{\alpha \eta}}\restriction{\eta} \mid \alpha \in b), \\ S_3^\eta &:= (\mathrm{type}(p_{\alpha \eta}, p_{\beta \eta}) \mid \alpha < \beta \in b). \end{align*} $$

For any $\eta \in M$ all three sets $S_1^\eta , S_2^\eta $ , and $S_3^\eta $ are definable in M and moreover the entire sequence $(S^\eta _i \mid \eta < \lambda ^+)$ is in M for each i in $\{1,2,3\}$ . Note also that $S_i^\delta $ is an element of M for $i\in \left \{ {1,2,3} \right \}$ even though $\delta \not \in M$ ; this follows from M being closed under sequences of length $<\lambda $ . Now define the set:

$$ \begin{align*} S := \{ \eta < &\ \lambda^+ \mid \eta \ge d_\beta \land S_1^\eta = S_1^\delta \land S_2^\eta = S_2^\delta \land S_3^\eta = S_3^\delta \land \\& \land \eta> \sup\left\{ {\sup\mathrm{dom}(p_{\alpha \beta}) \mid \alpha < \beta \in b} \right\} \land \forall \alpha \in b : p_{\alpha \eta} \Vdash \dot{c}(\alpha, \eta) = 1 \}. \end{align*} $$

It is obvious that S is definable in M and $\delta \in S$ ; thus S is a stationary subset of $\lambda ^+$ .

Finally consider the set

$$ \begin{align*}T := \left\{ {\eta \in S \mid \forall \xi \in S \cap \eta : \emptyset \Vdash \dot{c}(\xi, \eta) = 0} \right\}. \end{align*} $$

If $\delta $ is not an element of T, then there is some $\xi \in S \cap \delta $ for which $\emptyset \not \Vdash \dot {c}(\xi , \delta ) = 0$ so $p_{\xi \delta }$ was defined as some condition p such that $p \Vdash \dot {c}(\xi , \delta ) = 1$ , as $\xi $ is also an element of S we can put $b_\beta := \xi $ . Now each condition of the claim is satisfied as witnessed by $\xi $ belonging to S and the fact that $\xi $ witnesses that $\delta \not \in T$ .

On the other hand if $\delta \in T$ , then T is unbounded in $\lambda ^+$ and clearly $\emptyset \Vdash \dot {c}"[T]^2 = \{0\}$ , a contradiction.

Let B be the set constructed in the previous subclaim. We can also assume that $\left \{ {p_{\alpha \delta } \mid \alpha \in B} \right \}$ is a $\Delta $ -system (we assume that for each $\alpha < \lambda $ we have $|\alpha ^{<\kappa }| < \lambda $ ) so in particular $p_{\alpha \delta } \simeq p_{\beta \delta }$ for $\alpha , \beta \in B$ . We now show that the set B can be refined so that the set of conditions $\left \{ {p_{\alpha \beta } \mid \left \{ {\alpha , \beta } \right \} \in [B]^2} \right \}$ will form a double $\Delta $ -system.

The previous paragraph, condition (3), and Lemma 2.5 imply that for each $\gamma $ also the set $\left \{ {p_{\alpha \gamma } \mid \alpha \in B \cap \gamma } \right \}$ is a $\Delta $ -system with root $p^1_\gamma $ . We can now assume that $\left \{ {p^1_\gamma \mid \gamma \in B} \right \}$ also forms a $\Delta $ -system with root $p^1$ .

Conditions (1), (2), and (4) imply that for each $\alpha \in B$ the set of conditions $\left \{ {p_{\alpha \beta } \mid \beta \in B \setminus (\alpha + 1)} \right \}$ is a $\Delta $ -system with root $p^0_\alpha := {p_{\alpha \delta }}\restriction {\delta }$ . Given any $p_{\alpha \beta }$ and $p_{\alpha \gamma }$ for $\alpha < \beta < \gamma $ in B consider the intersection $p_{\alpha \beta } \cap p_{\alpha \gamma }$ , and clearly ${p_{\alpha \delta }}\restriction {\delta } \subseteq p_{\alpha \beta } \cap p_{\alpha \gamma }$ by condition (2). For the other direction if $(d,v) \in p_{\alpha \beta } \cap p_{\alpha \gamma }$ , then $d < \gamma $ by condition (4), thus $(d,v) \in p_{\alpha \gamma }\restriction \gamma $ and again by condition (2) $(d,v) \in p_{\alpha \delta }\restriction {\delta }$ . Finally we can also assume that $\left \{ {p^0_\alpha \mid \alpha \in B} \right \}$ forms a $\Delta $ -system with root $p^0$ . Let X be the refined set B; this is our desired set.

We will denote the root $p^0 = p^1$ of the double $\Delta $ -system simply as p.

Before we proceed fix an ordinal $\kappa \le \mu < \kappa ^+$ . Choose two sets: $X_0$ and $X_1$ , subsets of X such that $X_0 < X_1$ and the order type of both sets is $\kappa \cdot \mu $ . Fix also a bijection $g: \kappa \to \mu $ .

Claim 2. p forces a $(\mu : \mu )$ configuration in color $1$ .

Proof Let G be a generic set containing p, by induction we will construct sequences $(s_\alpha \mid \alpha < \kappa )$ in $X_0$ and $(t_\alpha \mid \alpha < \kappa )$ in $X_1$ such that $s_\alpha $ is in the $g(\alpha )$ -th section of $X_0$ , i.e., if $f: \kappa \cdot \mu \to X_0$ is the unique increasing bijection then

$$ \begin{align*}s_\alpha \in [f(\kappa \cdot g(\alpha)), f(\kappa \cdot (g(\alpha)+1))),\end{align*} $$

and denote this subset of $X_0$ as $X_0^\alpha $ , analogously for $t_\alpha $ and $X_1$ . We will make sure that for all $\alpha , \beta \in \kappa $ we have $p_{s_\alpha t_\beta } \in G$ ; as $p_{s_\alpha t_\beta }$ forces the color of the pair $\{s_\alpha , t_\beta \}$ to be $1$ this will ensure the conclusion of the claim.

To start the induction note that by genericity for some $\alpha \in X_0^0$ we have $p^0_\alpha \in G$ , this is because $\left \{ {p^0_\alpha \mid \alpha \in X_0^0} \right \}$ is a $\Delta $ -system of size $\kappa $ with root $p^0 \ge p$ and thus this set is predense below p. By the same argument there is some $\beta \in X_1^0$ such that $p_{\alpha \beta }$ is in G, so put $s_0 := \alpha $ and $t_0 := \beta $ .

Suppose we have already constructed $(s_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma )$ and $(t_\alpha \mid \alpha < \gamma )$ such that $p_{s_\alpha t_\beta } \in G$ for all $\alpha , \beta < \gamma $ . We will now find $\sigma \in X_0^\gamma $ such that $\left \{ {p_{\sigma t_\alpha } \mid \alpha < \gamma } \right \} \subseteq G$ and this will be our $s_\gamma $ .

Suppose that no $\sigma $ satisfies our requirements, i.e., there is no $\sigma $ in $X_0^\gamma $ such that $\left \{ {p_{\sigma t_\alpha } \mid \alpha < \gamma } \right \} \subseteq G$ . Then there must exist a condition $r \le p$ forcing this (note that $\left \{ {p_{\sigma t_\alpha } \mid \alpha < \gamma } \right \}$ is an element of the ground model because our forcing is $\kappa $ -closed):

$$ \begin{align*}r \Vdash \forall \sigma \in X_0^\gamma : \{p_{\sigma t_\alpha} \mid \alpha < \gamma\} \not\subseteq \dot{G}.\end{align*} $$

This means that for all $\sigma \in X_0^\gamma $ there exists a $\beta < \gamma $ such that $r \bot p_{\sigma t_\beta }$ . By going to a refinement we can assume that for $\kappa $ many $\sigma $ there is a fixed $\beta ' < \gamma $ such that $r \bot p_{\sigma t_{\beta '}}$ ; call this set C. However note that the set $\{p_{\sigma t_{\beta '}} \mid \sigma \in C\}$ is a $\Delta $ -system with root $p^1_{t_{\beta '}}$ which is contained in the generic set G because $p_{s_0 t_{\beta '}} \le p^1_{t_{\beta '}}$ and $p_{s_0 t_{\beta '}} \in G$ . Since r has size $<\kappa $ and $r \parallel p^1_{t_{\beta '}}$ , it cannot be incompatible with every condition from $\{p_{\sigma t_{\beta '}} \mid \sigma \in C\}$ , a contradiction.

The construction of $t_\gamma $ is almost verbatim.

This concludes the proof.⊣

3 A negative partition relation from Cohen forcing

The result of the previous section cannot be strengthened so that the second partition of the bipartite graph has size $\kappa ^+$ .

Proposition 3.1. If $\kappa < \lambda $ are regular cardinals, then $\mathsf {Add}({\kappa }, {\lambda }) \Vdash {\lambda } \not \to ({\kappa : \kappa ^+})^2$ .

Proof Consider an equivalent form of the forcing notion, specifically the poset $C_{S} : = \left \{ {p : S \to 2 \mid |p| < \kappa } \right \}$ , where $S := [\lambda ]^2$ and the ordering is reverse inclusion. We will prove that the generic graph, the union over the generic set G, added this way does not contain a homogeneous $(\kappa : \kappa ^+)$ configuration.

Suppose, for contradiction, that in the extension there are a set X of size $\kappa $ and a set Y of size $\kappa ^+$ above it so that all edges between them are monochromatic. Use the fact that when forcing with $\mathsf {Add}({\kappa }, {\lambda })$ any set of size $\kappa $ can be decided already when forcing over a domain of size $\kappa $ [Reference Kunen6, Lemma VIII.2.2]. To be more precise denote by M the ground model; there is a set $I \subseteq [\lambda ]^2$ of size $\kappa $ so that $X \in M[G \cap C_{I}]$ (note that $C_{[\lambda ]^2} \cong C_{I} \times C_{[\lambda ]^2 \setminus I}$ ). Now working in the extension by $C_I$ , there must exist a condition p in $ C_{[\lambda ]^2 \setminus I}$ so that $p \Vdash y \in \dot {Y}$ for some $y \not \in \bigcup I$ , otherwise $C_{[\lambda ]^2 \setminus I} \Vdash \dot {Y} \subseteq \bigcup I$ , which is not possible. Now p has size $<\kappa $ and $|X|=\kappa $ ; hence there must be an $x \in X \setminus \bigcup \mathrm {dom}(p)$ . Now p can be extended by the pair $(\left \{ {x, y} \right \}, i)$ for both $i \in \left \{ {0, 1} \right \}$ , which is a contradiction.

4 Possible strengthening of our result

The consistency of the relation ${{\omega _2}} \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega + 2})^2$ with $\neg \mathsf {CH}$ is unknown and seems to be substantially more involved than our result. By a result of Raghavan and Todorčević [Reference Raghavan and Todorčević9] this relation implies the non-existence of ${\omega _2}$ -Suslin trees. Laver showed [Reference Laver8] that in a model where $\mathsf {MA}$ holds and $2^\omega = {\omega _2}$ we have ${{\omega _2}} \not \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega : 2})^2$ .

Question 4.1. Is the relation ${{\omega _2}} \to ({{\omega _2}}, {\omega + 2})^2$ consistent with $\neg \mathsf {CH}$ ?

Acknowledgement

The author is grateful to David Chodounský, Chris Lambie-Hanson, and Stevo Todorčević for helpful discussions on the topic which greatly improved the exposition of this paper.

Funding

This work was supported by Charles University Research Center Program No. UNCE/SCI/022 and by the Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic (RVO 67985840).

References

Baumgartner, J. E., Almost-disjoint sets, the dense set problem and the partition calculus . Annals of Mathematical Logic , vol. 9 (1976), pp. 401439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dushnik, B. and Miller, E. W., Partially ordered sets . American Journal of Mathematics , vol. 63 (1941), no. 3, pp. 600610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erdős, P. and Rado, R., A partition calculus in set theory . Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 62 (1956), no. 5, pp. 427489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hajnal, A., Some results and problems on set theory . Acta Mathematica Academiae Scientiarum Hungaricae , vol. 11 (1960), pp. 277298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Just, W. and Weese, M., Discovering Modern Set Theory. II , Graduate Studies in Mathematics, vol. 18, American Mathematical Society, Providence, 1997.Google Scholar
Kunen, K., Set Theory , Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 102, North-Holland, Amsterdam–New York, 1980.Google Scholar
Lambie-Hanson, C., Higher-dimensional Delta-systems . Order , vol. 40 (2023), pp. 173197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laver, R., Partition relations for uncountable cardinals $\le {2}^{\aleph_0}$ , Infinite and Finite Sets (Colloq., Keszthely, 1973; Dedicated to P. Erdős on his 60th Birthday) , vol. 2, 1975, pp. 10291042.Google Scholar
Raghavan, D. and Todorčević, S., Suslin trees, the bounding number, and partition relations . Israel Journal of Mathematics , vol. 225 (2018), pp. 771796.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramsey, F. P., On the problem of formal logic . Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society , vol. 2 (1930), no. 30, pp. 401439.Google Scholar
Sierpiński, W., Sur Une probleme de la theorie des relations . Ann. Scuola Norm. Sup. Pisa Cl. Sci. , vol. 2 (1933), no. 2, pp. 285287.Google Scholar
Todorčević, S., Forcing positive partition relations . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 280 (1983), pp. 2, pp. 703720.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todorčević, S., Reals and positive partition relations , Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, VII (Salzburg, 1983) , Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 114, 1986, North-Holland, Amsterdam–New York, pp. 159169.Google Scholar
Todorčević, S., Erdős–Kakutani phenomena for paths . Acta Mathematica Hungarica , vol. 163 (2021), no. 1, pp. 168173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar