Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T19:17:17.258Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

PARTITION GENERICITY AND PIGEONHOLE BASIS THEOREMS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 October 2022

BENOIT MONIN
Affiliation:
LACL UNIVERSITÉ DE CRÉTEIL CRÉTEIL, FRANCE E-mail: benoit.monin@computability.fr
LUDOVIC PATEY*
Affiliation:
CNRS, IMJ-PRG, PARIS, FRANCE
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

There exist two main notions of typicality in computability theory, namely, Cohen genericity and randomness. In this article, we introduce a new notion of genericity, called partition genericity, which is at the intersection of these two notions of typicality, and show that many basis theorems apply to partition genericity. More precisely, we prove that every co-hyperimmune set and every Kurtz random is partition generic, and that every partition generic set admits weak infinite subsets, for various notions of weakness. In particular, we answer a question of Kjos-Hanssen and Liu by showing that every Kurtz random admits an infinite subset which does not compute any set of positive effective Hausdorff dimension. Partition genericity is a partition regular notion, so these results imply many existing pigeonhole basis theorems.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Association for Symbolic Logic

1 Introduction

The infinite pigeonhole principle can be considered as the most basic statement from Ramsey’s theory. The infinite pigeonhole principle for two colors can be formulated as “for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ .” From a combinatorial viewpoint, the infinite pigeonhole principle is trivial. On the other hand, the computational analysis of this principle is very subtle and received the attention of the computability community for decades, motivated by the reverse mathematics of Ramsey’s theorem for pairs.

1.1 Pigeonhole basis theorems

The computability-theoretic analysis of a mathematical problem consists in understanding, given an instance, how computably complicated are its solutions. From this perspective, a lower bound is a statement of the form “There exists an instance such that every solution is computationally strong,” while an upper bound is of the form “For every instance, there is a computationally weak solution.” Here, the notions of strength and weaknesses range over many computability-theoretic properties.

A pigeonhole basis theorem is an upper bound for the pigeonhole principle, that is, a statement of the form: “For every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ which is computationally weak.” Several pigeonhole basis theorems have been proven:

  1. 1. If B is a non-computable set, then for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that $B \not \leq _T H$ [Reference Dzhafarov and Jockusch3].

  2. 2. If B is a non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ set, then for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ [Reference Wang21].

  3. 3. If f is hyperimmune, then for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that f is H-hyperimmune [Reference Patey, Beckmann, Mitrana and Soskova16].

  4. 4. For every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ of non-PA degree [Reference Liu12].

  5. 5. For every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ of non-random degree, and which does not compute any set of positive effective Hausdorff dimension [Reference Liu13].

Asking for an infinite subset of A or of $\overline {A}$ is important, as there exist sets A such that every infinite subset is arbitrarily strong. For example, if A is the set of all initial segments of a set B, then every infinite subset of A computes B. In some cases however, one can fix the side of the subset. This happens in particular when the set A is sufficiently typical, where typicality means either randomness or genericity.

1.2 Randomness subset basis theorems

Randomness is a notion of typicality which was originally defined using measure theory. More recently, Algorithmic Randomness gave a formal meaning to the notion of random sequence using effective measure theory and Kolmogorov complexity. This yielded a hierarchy of randomness notions, among which we should mention (in increasing order) Kurtz randomness, Schnorr randomness, Martin-Löf randomness, Schnorr 2-randomness, and 2-randomness.

A randomness subset basis theorem is a statement of the form: “For every sufficiently random sequence $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite subset set $H \subseteq A$ which is computationally weak.” Here, by “sufficiently random,” we mean that the class of all such sets A has positive measure. One can then quantify the amount of randomness needed for such a statement, and obtain a theorem of the form “For every $\boxdot $ random sequence $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite subset set $H \subseteq A$ which is computationally weak,” where “ $\boxdot $ random” should be replaced by the right notion of randomness, such as Martin-Löf randomness for example. Subsets of random sequences were mainly studied as mass problems. For example, the Muchnik degree of the class of infinite subsets of Martin-Löf random sequences (seen as sets of numbers) is the Muchnik degree of DNC functions [Reference Greenberg and Miller4, Reference Kjos-Hanssen8]. However, a few randomness subset basis theorems appeared in the literature:

  1. 1. Every 2-random (or even Schnorr 2-random) has an infinite subset which does not compute a 1-random [Reference Kjos-Hanssen9].

  2. 2. Every 1-random has an infinite subset which does not compute a 1-random, or even which does not compute any set with positive effective Hausdorff dimension [Reference Kjos-Hanssen and Liu10].

Kjos-Hanssen and Liu [Reference Kjos-Hanssen and Liu10] asked whether these results could be improved to weaker notions of randomness, such as Schnorr randomness. In this article, we give a strong positive answer by showing that these results can be improved to Kurtz randomness.

1.3 Genericity subset basis theorems

Genericity is a notion of typicality which can be defined in terms of co-meager sets. The default notion of genericity considered is Cohen genericity. Later, Jockusch studied effectivizations of Cohen genericity, yielding again a hierarchy of genericity notions, among which we mention in increasing order bi-hyperimmunity, weak 1-genericity, and 1-genericity. A genericity subset basis theorem is a statement of the form: “For every sufficiently Cohen generic set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite subset set $H \subseteq A$ which is computationally weak.” Genericity subset basis theorems were not specifically studied per se. One can however mention one such result:

  1. 1. If B is a non-computable set, then every co-hyperimmune set has an infinite subset which does not compute B [Reference Hirschfeldt, Jockusch, Kjos-Hanssen, Lempp and Slaman6].

1.4 Partition genericity

In this article, we define a new notion of genericity, called partition genericity, and prove many statements of the form “Every partition generic set A has an infinite computationally weak subset.” We call these statements partition genericity subset basis theorems. Contrary to Martin-Löf randomness and Cohen genericity, this notion of partition genericity enjoys a property that one would expect of a subset basis theorem, that is, partition genericity is closed under supersets.

Theorem 1.1.

  1. 1. If B is a non-computable set, and A is partition generic, then there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ such that $B \not \leq _T H$ .

  2. 2. If B is a non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ set, and A is partition generic relative to B, then there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ such that B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ .

  3. 3. If f is hyperimmune, and A is partition generic relative to f, then there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ such that f is H-hyperimmune.

  4. 4. If A is partition generic, then there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ of non-PA degree.

  5. 5. If A is partition generic, then there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ of non-Martin-Löf random degree, and furthermore, which does not compute any set of positive effective Hausdorff dimension.

In particular, every co-hyperimmune set and every Kurtz random is partition generic. Moreover, we show that partition genericity is almost a partition regular notion (see Corollary 2.34). It follows that all these partition genericity subset basis theorems imply all the pigeonhole basis theorems mentioned above.

1.5 Organization of this paper

In Section 2, we introduce the central notion of partition regularity, and study it both from a combinatorial and a computability-theoretic viewpoint. We then define the notion of partition genericity. Then, in Section 3, we prove a first range of applications which hold for unrelativized partition genericity. The two next sections, Sections 4 and 5, are devoted to the preservation of hyperimmunity and non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ definitions, respectively. These subset basis theorems require the definition of alternative notions of genericity. Last, we study lowness for various notions related to partition genericity in Section 6.

1.6 Notation

We use lower case letters $a, b, c$ for integers, upper case letters for sets of integers, and rounded letters $\mathcal {A}, \mathcal {B}$ for classes.

A k-cover of a set X is a k-tuple of sets $X_0, \dots , X_{k-1}$ such that $X_0 \cup \dots \cup X_{k-1} \supseteq X$ . We do not require the sets $X_i$ to be pairwise disjoint. Given a set $X \subseteq \omega $ and some $n \in \omega $ , we let $[X]^n$ denote the set of all subsets of X of size n. Accordingly, we write $[X]^\omega $ for the class of all infinite subsets of X. We write $2^{=n}$ for the set of all binary strings of length n, and $2^{<\omega } = \bigcup _n 2^{=n}$ . We write $|\sigma |$ for the length of the string $\sigma $ .

A Mathias condition is a pair $(\sigma , X)$ , where $\sigma \in 2^{<\omega }$ is a finite binary string, X is an infinite set of integers, and $\min X \geq |\sigma |$ . The set X is usually called a reservoir, as it can informally be seen as a reservoir of elements to add to $\sigma $ . A Mathias condition $(\tau , Y)$ extends $(\sigma , X)$ if $\sigma \preceq \tau $ , $Y \subseteq X$ , and $\tau \setminus \sigma \subseteq X$ . Here, we identify a string $\sigma $ with the set $\{ n < |\sigma | : \sigma (n) = 1 \}$ .

2 Partition regularity

In this section, we conduct a general study of partition regularity from a computability-theoretic viewpoint. We introduce several related concepts, including the central notion of partition genericity, which will be justified by the constructions of Section 3.

2.1 Partition regularity

The central notion we are going to consider in this article is the one of partition regularity (see [Reference Hindman and Strauss5]). This concept comes from Ramsey theory and can be considered as a generalization of the infinite pigeonhole principle.

Definition 2.1. A partition regular class is a collection of sets $\mathcal {L} \subseteq 2^\omega $ such that:

  1. 1. $\mathcal {L}$ is not empty.

  2. 2. If $X \in \mathcal {L}$ and $X \subseteq Y$ , then $Y \in \mathcal {L}$ .

  3. 3. For every k, if $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \in \mathcal {L}$ , then there is $i \leq k$ such that $Y_i \in \mathcal {L}$ .

Ramsey’s theory is sometimes characterized as the study of which classes are partition regular. Note that our definition of partition regularity differs from the standard definition in that we require our classes to be closed under superset. We will make an essential use of this extra closure requirement all along this article. There are many well-known examples of partition regular classes in combinatorics:

Example 2.2. The following classes are partition regular.

  1. 1. $\{ X \subseteq \omega : X \mbox { is infinite} \}$ by the infinite pigeonhole principle.

  2. 2. $\{X \subseteq \omega :\ n \in X\}$ for a fixed n.

  3. 3. $\{X \subseteq \omega : \limsup _{n \rightarrow \infty } \frac {| \{1,2,\ldots ,n\} \cap X|}{n}> 0 \}$ .

  4. 4. $\{X \subseteq \omega :\ \sum _{n \in X} \frac {1}{n} = \infty \}$ .

In the computability-theoretic realm, many pigeonhole basis theorems can be rephrased as statements about partition regularity.

Example 2.3. The following classes are partition regular.

  1. 1. $\{ X \subseteq \omega : \exists Y \in [X]^\omega \ Y \not \geq _T C \}$ for any $C \not \leq _T \emptyset $ (see [Reference Dzhafarov and Jockusch3]).

  2. 2. $\{ X \subseteq \omega : \exists Y \in [X]^\omega \ Y \mbox { is not of PA degree} \}$ (see [Reference Liu12]).

  3. 3. $\{ X \subseteq \omega : \exists Y \in [X]^\omega \ Y^{(n)} \not \geq _T C \}$ for any non- $\Delta ^0_{n+1}$ set C (see [Reference Monin and Patey15]).

  4. 4. $\{ X \subseteq \omega : \exists Y \in [X]^\omega \ \omega _1^Y = \omega _1^{ck} \}$ (see [Reference Monin and Patey15]).

Dorais [Reference Dorais1] was the first to use partition regular classes in the context of reverse mathematics. More precisely, he worked with a variant of Mathias forcing whose reservoirs avoid a $\Sigma ^0_2$ free ideal over $2^\omega $ . A class is a free ideal iff it is the complement of a partition regular class.

2.2 Non-trivial classes

A partition regular class can be thought of as a notion of largeness. Indeed, if we interpret $X \in \mathcal {L}$ as “X is large,” then the axioms of partition regularity say that if a set is large, then any superset of it is large, and if we split a large set into two (or finitely many) parts, then at least one of the parts is large. There exist however a family of partition regular classes that fail this intuition. We call them principal classes.

Definition 2.4. A partition regular class $\mathcal {L} \subseteq 2^\omega $ is principal if $\mathcal {L} = \{X \in 2^{\omega }: n \in X\}$ for some n. A partition regular class $\mathcal {L}$ is non-trivial if it contains only infinite sets, otherwise it is trivial.

The following proposition shows that once one excludes the principal partition regular classes, then the remaining partition regular classes satisfy at least one enjoyable property of largeness, namely, having only infinite elements.

Proposition 2.5. A partition regular class $\mathcal {L}$ is non-trivial iff it contains no principal partition regular subclass.

Proof It is clear that if $\mathcal {L}$ is non-trivial, it does not contain a principal partition regular subclass. Suppose now $\mathcal {L}$ is trivial, that is, $\mathcal {L}$ contains a finite set $X = \{n_1, \dots , n_k\}$ . Then in particular we have $\{n_1\} \cup \dots \cup \{n_k\} \supseteq X$ . It follows that we must have $\{n_i\} \in \mathcal {L}$ for some $i \leq k$ . Then any set X containing $n_i$ is in $\mathcal {L}$ , that is, we have $\{X \in 2^{\omega}\,{:}\,n_i \in X\} \subseteq \mathcal {L}$ .

Non-trivial partition regular classes admit a simple characterization, which will be later used to generalize the concept of non-triviality to arbitrary classes.

Proposition 2.6. A partition regular class $\mathcal {L}$ is non-trivial iff $\mathcal {L}$ is included in the $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U}_2$ of sets containing at least two distinct elements.

Proof If $\mathcal {L}$ is non-trivial then every member of $\mathcal {L}$ is infinite and clearly $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {U}_2$ . If $\mathcal {L}$ is trivial then by Proposition 2.5, it contains $\{n\}$ for some $n \in \omega $ and thus we do not have $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {U}_2$ .

The following proposition says that any non-trivial partition regular class must contain many elements, in a measure-theoretic sense. All the partition regular classes we are going to consider in the applications are Borel, hence measurable. Given two sets $X, Y \subseteq \omega $ , we write $X \subseteq ^{*} Y$ to say that $X \setminus Y$ is finite, and $X =^{*} Y$ if $X \subseteq ^{*} Y$ and $Y \subseteq ^{*} X$ . We say that a class $\mathcal {L}$ is closed under finite changes if whenever $X \in \mathcal {L}$ and $X =^{*} Y$ , then $Y \in \mathcal {L}$ .

Proposition 2.7. Let $\mathcal {L}$ be a non-trivial partition regular class. Then $\mathcal {L}$ is closed by finite changes. Furthermore if $\mathcal {L}$ is measurable it has measure $1$ .

Proof Let $X \in \mathcal {L}$ . By definition, any $Y \supseteq X$ also belongs to $\mathcal {L}$ . Thus $\mathcal {L}$ is closed under finite addition of elements, that is, if $X \in \mathcal {L}$ and F is finite, then $X \cup F \in \mathcal {L}$ . Consider now any $Y \subseteq X$ such that $|X \setminus Y|$ is finite. In particular, $X = Y \cup \{n_0, \dots , n_k\}$ for some elements $n_0, \dots , n_k$ . As $\mathcal {L}$ contains only infinite elements, we must have $Y \in \mathcal {L}$ . Thus $\mathcal {L}$ is closed by finite suppression, that is, if $X \in \mathcal {L}$ and F is finite, then $X \setminus F \in \mathcal {L}$ . We easily conclude that $\mathcal {L}$ is closed under finite changes.

If $\mathcal {L}$ is measurable, by Kolmogorov 0–1 law, $\mathcal {L}$ is either of measure $0$ or of measure $1$ . Suppose for contradiction that $\mathcal {L}$ is of measure $0$ . As $\mathcal {L}$ is measurable, if must be included in some Borel set $\mathcal {A}$ of measure $0$ . Let O be an oracle such that $\mathcal {A}$ is included in a $\Pi ^0_2(O)$ classes effectively of measure $0$ , that is, $\mathcal {A} \subseteq \bigcap _e \mathcal {U}_e$ for some uniformly O-computable sequence of $\Pi ^0_2(O)$ classes such that $\mu (\mathcal {U}_e) < 2^{-e}$ . Then no element of $\mathcal {L}$ is O-Martin-Löf random. Let Z be any O-Martin-Löf random set. We also have that $\overline {Z}$ is O-Martin-Löf random. Also $\omega \subseteq Z \cup \overline {Z}$ . As $\omega \in \mathcal {L}$ we must have $Z \in \mathcal {L}$ or $\overline {Z} \in \mathcal {L}$ , which is a contradiction. Thus $\mathcal {L}$ is not of measure $0$ and therefore it is of measure $1$ .

2.3 Closure properties

We now study some good closure properties enjoyed by the collection of all partition regular classes. A superclass of a partition regular class is not partition regular in general, even when the superclass is closed under superset. For example, let A be a bi-infinite set, and let $\mathcal {L}_A = \{ X \in 2^\omega : |A \cap X| = \infty \}$ . Then $\mathcal {L}_A$ is a partition regular class, but $\mathcal {L} = \mathcal {L}_A \cup \{ X \in 2^\omega : X \supseteq \overline {A} \}$ is not. Indeed, let $x_0 = \min \overline {A}$ and $B = \overline {A} \setminus \{x_0\}$ . Then $\{x_0\} \cup B = \overline {A} \in \mathcal {L}$ , but neither $\{x_0\}$ , nor B belong to $\mathcal {L}$ . On the other hand, an arbitrary union of partition regular classes is partition regular.

Proposition 2.8. Suppose $\{\mathcal {L}_i\}_{i \in I}$ is an arbitrary non-empty collection of partition regular classes. Then $\bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ is a partition regular class.

Proof It is clear that $\bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ is not empty. Let $X \in \bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ . Let $Y \supseteq X$ . There is some $i \in I$ such that $X \in \mathcal {L}_i$ . As $\mathcal {L}_i$ is partition regular, $Y \in \mathcal {L}_i \subseteq \bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ .

Let $X \in \bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ . Let $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ . There is some $i \in I$ such that $X \in \mathcal {L}_i$ . As $\mathcal {L}_i$ is partition regular, $Y_j \in \mathcal {L}_i \subseteq \bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ for some $j \leq k$ .

In particular for every class $\mathcal {A}$ containing a partition regular class, there is a largest partition regular class included in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Definition 2.9. Given a class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega $ , let $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ denote the largest partition regular subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . If $\mathcal {A}$ does not contain a partition regular class, let $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ be the empty set.

The largest partition regular class included in $\mathcal {A}$ admits a simple explicit definition that we shall use to analyse the definitional complexity of the partition regular classes we consider.

Proposition 2.10. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega $ be any class. Then

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{L}(\mathcal{A}) = \{X \in 2^\omega\ :\ \forall k\ \forall X_0\cup\dots\cup X_k \supseteq X\ \exists i \leq k\ X_i \in \mathcal{A}\}.\end{align*} $$

Proof Note that by definition, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A}) \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ , as if $X \notin \mathcal {A}$ then itself as a $1$ -cover is not in $\mathcal {A}$ , so $X \notin \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ . Let us show that $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ contains every partition regular class included in $\mathcal {A}$ . Suppose $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ is partition regular. Then given $X \in \mathcal {L}$ , for every k and every $X_0\cup \dots \cup X_k \supseteq X$ we have $X_i \in \mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ for some $i \leq k$ . It follows that $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ and thus that $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ .

Assume $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A}) \neq \emptyset $ . Let us show that $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ is partition regular. Suppose $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ . Let $Y \supseteq X$ . Then for every k, every k-cover of Y is also a k-cover of X. As $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ , one element of the k-cover belongs to $\mathcal {A}$ . Thus for every k and every k-cover of Y, one element of the k-cover belongs to $\mathcal {A}$ . It follows that $Y \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ . Let $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ and let $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ for some k. Let us show there is some $i \leq k$ such that $Y_i \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ . Suppose for contradiction that this is not the case. In particular for every $i \leq k$ there are sets $Y^i_{0}, \dots, Y^i_{k_i} \supseteq Y_i$ such that $\forall j \leq k_i$ , we have $Y^i_{j} \notin \mathcal {A}$ . In particular the sets $\{Y^i_{j}\}_{i \leq k, j \leq k_i}$ are a finite cover of X such that for every $i \leq k$ and every $j \leq k_i$ we have $Y^i_{j} \notin \mathcal {A}$ . This contradicts that $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ . Thus there must exists $i \leq k$ such that $Y_i \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ . So if $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ is non-empty, it is partition regular.

Last, partition regular classes enjoy a very useful property: the intersection of an infinite decreasing sequence of partition regular classes is again partition regular. This property will be used to propagate properties of $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular classes to arbitrary intersections of $\Sigma ^0_1$ partition large classes.

Proposition 2.11. Suppose $\{\mathcal {L}_n\}_{n \in \omega }$ is a collection of partition regular classes with $\mathcal {L}_{n+1} \subseteq \mathcal {L}_n$ . Then $\bigcap _{n \in \omega } \mathcal {L}_n$ is partition regular.

Proof For every n, $\omega \in \mathcal {L}_n$ because $\mathcal {L}_n$ is partition regular. It follows that $\omega \in \bigcap _{n \in \omega } \mathcal {L}_n$ . In particular $\bigcap _{n \in \omega } \mathcal {L}_n$ is not empty.

Suppose $X \in \bigcap _{n \in \omega } \mathcal {L}_n$ . Let $Y \supseteq X$ . For every n, since $X \in \mathcal {L}_n$ then $Y \in \mathcal {L}_n$ as $\mathcal {L}_n$ is partition regular. Thus $Y \in \bigcap _{n \in \omega } \mathcal {L}_n$ .

Suppose $X \in \bigcap _{n \in \omega } \mathcal {L}_n$ . Let $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ . Suppose for contradiction that for every $i \leq k$ the set $Y_i$ is not in $\bigcap _{n \in \omega } \mathcal {L}_n$ . For every $i \leq k$ , let $n_i$ be such that $Y_i \notin \mathcal {L}_{n_i}$ . Let n be larger than these numbers. For every $i \leq k$ , since $\mathcal {L}_{n_i} \supseteq \mathcal {L}_n$ , the set $Y_i$ is not in $\mathcal {L}_n$ . As $X \in \mathcal {L}_n$ , it follows that $\mathcal {L}_n$ is not partition regular, which contradicts our hypothesis. Thus for every $X \in \bigcap _{n \in \omega } \mathcal {L}_n$ and for every $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ , there is some $i \leq k$ such that $Y_i \in \bigcap _{n \in \omega } \mathcal {L}_n$ .

2.4 $\Pi ^0_2$ Partition regular classes

The most basic non-trivial partition regular class, the class of all infinite sets, is $\Pi ^0_2$ . In this section, we study a few specific $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular classes and show that there is no non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_2$ partition regular class.

Proposition 2.12. Let $\mathcal {U}$ be an upward-closed $\Sigma ^0_1$ class. Then $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U})$ is $\Pi ^0_2$ .

Proof By Theorem 2.10, the largest partition regular subclass of $\mathcal {U}$ is defined by

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{L}(\mathcal{U}) = \{X \in 2^\omega\ :\ \forall k\ \forall X_0\cup\dots\cup X_k \supseteq X\ \exists i \leq k\ X_i \in \mathcal{U}\}.\end{align*} $$

Since $\mathcal {U}$ is upward-closed, then $\forall X_0\cup \cdots \cup X_k \supseteq X\ \exists i \leq k\ X_i \in \mathcal {U}$ is equivalent to $\forall X_0\cup \dots \cup X_k = X\ \exists i \leq k\ X_i \in \mathcal {U}$ . Since $\mathcal {U}$ is $\Sigma ^0_1$ , then by compactness, the previous formula is equivalent to $\exists n \forall X_0 \cup \dots \cup X_k = X \cap \{0, \dots , n\}\ \exists i \leq k\ X_i \in \mathcal {U}$ , which is a $\Sigma ^0_1$ formula. Hence, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U})$ is $\Pi ^0_2$ .

The previous proposition will be very useful for our computational analysis of partition regularity, as shows the following corollary.

Corollary 2.13. Let $\mathcal {U}$ be a $\Sigma ^0_1$ class. The sentence “ $\mathcal {U}$ contains a partition regular class” is $\Pi ^0_2$ .

Proof By Theorem 2.10, the class $\mathcal {U}$ contains a partition regular class iff $\omega \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U})$ , which is a $\Pi ^0_2$ sentence.

The partition regular class of all infinite sets can be generalized to a whole family of non-trivial partition regular classes in the following way.

Definition 2.14. For any infinite set X we define $\mathcal {L}_X$ as the $\Pi ^0_2(X)$ partition regular class of the sets that intersect X infinitely often.

In particular, $\mathcal {L}_\omega $ is the class of all infinite sets. It is not the only possible kind of $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class. There are examples of $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular classes $\mathcal {L}$ such that $\mathcal {L}_X \nsubseteq \mathcal {L}$ for any $X \in [\omega ]^{\omega }$ . Consider for instance the class $\{X \subseteq \omega :\ \sum _{n \in X} \frac {1}{n} = \infty \}$ .

We finish this section by proving that there the only $\mathbf {\Sigma ^0_2}$ partition regular classes are the trivial ones. By $\mathbf {\Sigma ^0_2}$ , we mean a class which is $\Sigma ^0_2$ in the sense of the Borel hierarchy, without any effectiveness restriction. For this, we need the following proposition by Miller [Reference Miller14, Proposition 4.1].

Proposition 2.15 (Miller [Reference Miller14]).

If a $\Sigma ^{0,Z}_1$ class contains all the finite sets, then it contains all the Z-hyperimmune sets.

Proof Let $\mathcal {U}$ be such a $\Sigma ^{0,Z}_1$ class. Let $X \not \in \mathcal {U}$ . For any n and every string $\sigma $ of length n we have $\sigma 0^{\infty } \in \mathcal {U}$ . For every n, let $f(n) \in \mathbb {N}$ be large enough such that for any string $\sigma $ of length n we have $[\sigma 0^{f(n)}] \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ . Note that the function f is total and Z-computable. It must be that $X\upharpoonright _{n+f(n)}$ contains at least a $1$ at a position greater than n. By repeating this we see that we can Z-computably bound $p_X$ .

Proposition 2.16. There are no non-trivial $\mathbf {\Sigma ^0_2}$ partition regular classes.

Proof Suppose for contradiction that there exists a non-trivial $\mathbf {\Sigma ^0_2}$ partition regular class $\mathcal {C}$ . Let Z be such that $\mathcal {C}$ is $\Sigma ^{0,Z}_2$ . In particular, $2^\omega \setminus \mathcal {C}$ contains all the finite sets, so by Proposition 2.15, it contains all the Z-hyperimmune sets. Consider now any set X such that both X and $\overline {X}$ are Z-hyperimmune. By partition regularity, at least one of them belongs to $\mathcal {C}$ , which is a contradiction.

2.5 Partition largeness

As mentioned earlier, a partition regular class represents a notion of largeness. However, a class containing a partition regular class is not necessarily itself partition regular. These classes admit a nice characterization.

Definition 2.17. A partition large class is a non-empty collection of sets $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega $ such that:

  1. (a) If $X \in \mathcal {A}$ and $Y \supseteq X$ , then $Y \in \mathcal {A}$ .

  2. (b) For every k, if $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq \omega $ , there is some $j \leq k$ such that $Y_j \in \mathcal {A}$ .

Proposition 2.18. A class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega $ is partition large iff it is upward-closed and contains a partition regular subclass.

Proof Suppose $\mathcal {A}$ is upward-closed and contains a partition regular subclass $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ . (a) is trivially satisfied by hypothesis. By partition regularity of $\mathcal {L}$ , $\omega \in \mathcal {L}$ and for every k and every $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq \omega $ , there is some $j \leq k$ such that $Y_j \in \mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ . So $\mathcal {A}$ is partition large.

Suppose now $\mathcal {A}$ is partition large. By (a), it is upward-closed. We claim that $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ is partition regular. By (b) and Theorem 2.10, $\omega \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ , so $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A}) \neq \emptyset $ . By definition of $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ , it is partition regular, hence $\mathcal {A}$ contains a partition regular subclass.

Lemma 2.19. Let $\mathcal {L} \subseteq 2^\omega $ be a non-trivial partition regular class and $X \in \mathcal {L}$ . Then $\mathcal {L} \cap \mathcal {L}_X$ is partition large.

Proof Let $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq \omega $ . In particular we have $Y_0 \cap X \cup \dots \cup Y_k \cap X \supseteq X$ . As $X \in \mathcal {L}$ we must have $Y_j \cap X \in \mathcal {L}$ for some $j \leq k$ . In particular, since $\mathcal {L}$ is non-trivial, $Y_j \cap X$ is infinite, so $Y_j \cap X \in \mathcal {L}_X$ . Therefore, there is some $j \leq k$ such that $Y_j \cap X \in \mathcal {L} \cap \mathcal {L}_X$ .

The following proposition yields another definition of $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ which will be very useful.

Proposition 2.20. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq \mathcal {U}_2$ be a partition large class. Then

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{L}(\mathcal{A}) = \{ X : \mathcal{A} \cap \mathcal{L}_X \mbox{ is partition large}\}. \end{align*} $$

Proof Let $\mathcal {L} = \{ X : \mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X \mbox { is partition large} \}$ . Since $\mathcal {A}$ is partition large, then by Proposition 2.18, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ is the largest partition regular subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . Moreover, by Proposition 2.6, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ is non-trivial since $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A}) \subseteq \mathcal {U}_2$ . Thus, by Theorem 2.19, for every $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ , $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A}) \cap \mathcal {L}_X$ is partition large. In particular, $\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X$ is partition large, hence $X \in \mathcal {L}$ . It follows that $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A}) \subseteq \mathcal {L}$ .

Let us show that $\mathcal {L}$ is partition regular. First, $\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_\omega = \mathcal {A}$ is partition large, so $\omega \in \mathcal {L}$ . Let $X \in \mathcal {L}$ and $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ . In particular, $\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X$ is partition large, so by Proposition 2.18, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X)$ is partition regular. Moreover, $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X)$ , so there is some $i \leq k$ such that $Y_i \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X)$ . By Theorem 2.19, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X) \cap \mathcal {L}_{Y_i}$ is partition large. Since $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X) \cap \mathcal {L}_{Y_i} \subseteq \mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_{Y_i}$ , then $\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_{Y_i}$ is partition large, so $Y_i \in \mathcal {L}$ .

Last, let us show that $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ . Indeed, if $\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X$ is partition large, then since $X \cup \overline {X} = \omega $ , either X or $\overline {X}$ belongs to $\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X$ . However, $\overline {X} \not \in \mathcal {L}_X$ , so $X \in \mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {L}_X$ . In particular, $X \in \mathcal {A}$ . It follows that $\mathcal {L}$ is a partition regular subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ , so by maximality of $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ , $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ .

Recall that Proposition 2.6 characterizes non-trivial partition regular classes as those which are included in the $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U}_2$ of sets containing at least two distinct elements. Since there is no non-empty $\Sigma ^0_1$ class containing only infinite sets, we take this characterization as the natural generalization of non-triviality to arbitrary classes.

Definition 2.21. A class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega $ is non-trivial if it is included in the $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U}_2$ of sets containing at least two distinct elements.

2.6 Partition genericity

Given a $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class $\mathcal {L}$ and a set X, then either $X \in \mathcal {L}$ , or $\overline {X} \in \mathcal {L}$ . In general, whether the first or the second case holds depends on the choice of $\mathcal {L}$ . For some sets however, the same case always holds. This yields the notion of partition genericity.

Definition 2.22. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega $ be a class. We say that X is partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ if X belongs to every non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . If X is partition generic in $2^\omega $ we simply say that X is partition generic.

The first and most trivial example of partition generic set is $\omega $ . First, note that partition genericity is closed under finite changes.

Proposition 2.23. If X is partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ and $Y =^{*} X$ , then Y is partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proof Let $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ be any non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . Since X is partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ , then $X \in \mathcal {L}$ . Since $Y =^{*} X$ , by Theorem 2.7, $Y \in \mathcal {L}$ . Therefore Y is partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

It follows that every co-finite set is partition generic. Actually, this characterizes the computable partition generic sets. Indeed, if A is a co-infinite computable set, then $\mathcal {L}_{\overline {A}}$ is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class which does not contain A.

Definition 2.24. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega $ be a class. We say that X is bi-partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ if X and $\overline {X}$ are both partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . If X is bi-partition generic in $2^\omega $ we simply say that X is bi-partition generic.

The existence of bi-partition generic sets will be proven in Proposition 2.26. Note that, contrary to partition genericity, no computable set is bi-partition generic.

Proposition 2.25. Every bi-partition generic set is bi-immune.

Proof Let A be bi-partition generic. Let X be an infinite subset of A. Then $\mathcal {L}_X$ is a partition regular class such that $\overline {A} \not \in \mathcal {L}_X$ . Since $\overline {A}$ is partition generic, $\mathcal {L}_X$ is not $\Pi ^0_2$ , so X is not computable. Similarly, $\overline {A}$ has no infinite computable subset.

In particular, every bi-partition generic set is bi-infinite. We now prove that every typical set is bi-partition generic, that is, every sufficiently random or generic set is bi-partition generic.

Proposition 2.26. Every Kurtz random is bi-partition generic.

Proof By Theorem 2.7, every non-trivial measurable partition regular class is of measure $1$ . It follows that any Kurtz-random belongs to every $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class and thus that any Kurtz-random is bi-partition generic.

In particular, one can be bi-hyperimmune and bi-partition generic. The following proposition shows that is actually always the case, in the sense that every bi-hyperimmune set is bi-partition generic.

Proposition 2.27. Every co-hyperimmune set is partition generic.

Proof Let A be a co-hyperimmune set. Suppose for the contradiction that $A \not \in \mathcal {L}$ for some non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class $\mathcal {L} \subseteq 2^\omega $ . In particular, there is a partition large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \supseteq \mathcal {L}$ such that $A \not \in \mathcal {U}$ . Since $\mathcal {U}$ is partition large, for every $t \in \omega $ , there is some $\rho \in 2^{<\omega }$ with $\min \rho> t$ such that $\rho \in \mathcal {U}$ . In particular, for every such $\rho $ , we have $\rho \cap \overline {A} \neq \emptyset $ . Moreover, such a string $\rho $ can be found computably uniformly in t. We can therefore compute an array tracing $\overline {A}$ , contradicting hyperimmunity of $\overline {A}$ .

Corollary 2.28. Every bi-hyperimmune set is bi-partition generic.

Proof Immediate by Proposition 2.27.

As mentioned earlier, every sufficiently random set is bi-partition generic. Moreover, every sufficiently random set is effectively bi-immune. It is natural to wonder whether every effectively co-immune set is partition generic. The following proposition answers negatively.

Proposition 2.29. There is an effectively co-immune set which is not partition generic.

Proof Consider the following $\Pi ^0_2$ class $\mathcal {L} = \{X\ :\ \forall k\ \exists n\ |X \upharpoonright _{n^2}| \geq nk \}$ . Let us prove it is partition regular: Let $X \in \mathcal {L}$ and $Y_1 \cup \cdots \cup Y_m \supseteq X$ . For $k \in \omega $ there is some n such that $|X \upharpoonright _{n^2}| \geq n m k$ . Then, there is some $e_k \leq m$ such that $|Y_{e_k} \upharpoonright _{n^2}| \geq n k$ . Let $e \leq m$ be such that $e = e_k$ for infinitely many k. We then have for infinitely many k that there exists n such that $|Y_{e} \upharpoonright _{n^2}| \geq n k$ . This is therefore true in particular for every k. Thus $Y_e \in \mathcal {L}$ , so $\mathcal {L}$ is partition regular.

It suffices to construct an effectively co-immune set A such that for every n, $|A \upharpoonright _{n^2}| < n$ for every n. Then $A \not \in \mathcal {L}$ , hence A is not partition generic. To construct such a set, for every e, let $x_e$ be the $e^2$ th element of $W_e$ (in the $<_\omega $ order), if it exists. Assume by convention that $W_0 = \emptyset $ , so $e_0$ does not exist. Let $A = \{ x_e : e \in \omega \}$ . Then A is an infinite set, which is effectively co-immune, as witnessed by the function $n \mapsto n^2$ . Last, for every n, $A \upharpoonright _{n^2} \subseteq \{ x_e : e < n \}$ , so $|A \upharpoonright _{n^2}| < n$ .

We have seen so far three classes of partition generic sets: co-finite sets, co-hyperimmune sets, and Kurtz randoms. Let us construct a bi-partition generic set which belongs to none of these categories.

Proposition 2.30. There is a bi-partition generic set A such that for every n, $A(2n) \neq A(2n+1)$ .

Proof Consider the notion of forcing whose conditions are strings $\sigma $ of even length, such that for every $n < |\sigma |/2$ , $\sigma (2n) \neq \sigma (2n+1)$ . The conditions are partially ordered by the suffix relation. Let us show that every sufficiently generic set G is bi-partition generic.

Let $\sigma $ be a condition, and let $\mathcal {U}$ be a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ partition large class. Let $X_0 = \{2n : 2n> |\sigma | \}$ and $X_1 = \{2n+1 : 2n+1> |\sigma | \}$ . Since $\{0\} \cup \dots \cup \{|\sigma |\} \cup X_0 \cup X_1 \supseteq \omega $ , then either $X_0 \in \mathcal {U}$ , or $X_1 \in \mathcal {U}$ . Say the former case holds as the other case is symmetric. Since $\mathcal {U}$ is $\Sigma ^0_1$ , then there is some k such that $[X_0 \upharpoonright _{2k}] \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ . Let $\tau = \sigma \cup X_0 \upharpoonright _{2k}$ . Note that $\tau $ is a valid condition. Moreover, since $\mathcal {U}$ is closed under superset, then $[\tau ] \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ . Therefore, every sufficiently generic set G for this notion of forcing belongs to every non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ partition large class. By symmetric, so does the complement of G, so G is bi-partition generic.

Corollary 2.31. There is a bi-partition generic set which is neither co-hyperimmune, nor Kurtz random.

Proof Consider the set A of Proposition 2.30. It is clearly neither hyperimmune nor co-hyperimmune since $F_0, F_1, \dots $ defined by $F_n = \{2n, 2n+1\}$ is a c.e. array tracing both A and $\overline {A}$ . Furthermore, A is not Kurtz random, since $A \in \{ X : \forall n X(2n) \neq X(2n+1) \}$ which is a $\Pi ^0_1$ class of measure 0.

The following lemma is a sort of pigeonhole principle, from which we will derive partition regularity of the class of sets which are partition generic in some non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ partition large class.

Lemma 2.32. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega $ be a class and let X be a set which is partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . For every $Y_0 \cup Y_1 \supseteq X$ , if $Y_0 \notin \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {A})$ then $Y_1$ is partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proof Suppose for contradiction that there is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ such that $Y_1 \notin \mathcal {V}$ . In particular, $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {L}(A)$ , so $Y_0 \notin \mathcal {V}$ . By partition regularity of $\mathcal {V}$ , since $Y_0 \cup Y_1 \supseteq X$ , then $X \notin \mathcal {V}$ , which contradicts partition genericity of X in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proposition 2.33. Let $\mathcal {A}$ be a partition large class. Suppose X is partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . Let $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ . Then there is a $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U}$ such that $\mathcal {U} \cap \mathcal {A}$ is partition large, together with some $i \leq k$ such that $Y_i$ is partition generic in $\mathcal {U} \cap \mathcal {A}$ .

Proof We prove the statement by the lemma by induction on k. For $k = 0$ , $Y_0 \supseteq X$ so $Y_0$ is partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ by upward-closure of partition genericity. Take $\mathcal {U} = 2^\omega $ and we are done.

Suppose now that the property holds for $k-1$ . Suppose $Y_k$ is not partition generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . Thus there is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class $\bigcap _{e \in C} \mathcal {U}_e \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ such that $Y_k \not \in \bigcap _{e \in C} \mathcal {U}_e$ . In particular, there is some $e \in \mathcal {C}$ such that $Y_k \notin \mathcal {U}_e$ . Note that $\bigcap _{e \in C} \mathcal {U}_e \subseteq \mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {U}_e$ , so $\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {U}_e$ is partition large. By Theorem 2.32, $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_{k-1}$ is partition generic in $\mathcal {U}_e \cap \mathcal {A}$ . By induction hypothesis on $\mathcal {U}_e \cap \mathcal {A}$ and $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_{k-1}$ , there is a $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {V}$ such that $\mathcal {V} \cap \mathcal {U}_e \cap \mathcal {A}$ is partition large, together with some $i < k$ such that $Y_i$ is partition generic in $\mathcal {V} \cap \mathcal {U}_e \cap \mathcal {A}$ . The property therefore holds with the $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {V} \cap \mathcal {U}_e$ .

Corollary 2.34. The following class is partition regular:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{P} = \{ X : X \mbox{ is partition generic in some non-trivial } \Sigma^0_1 \mbox{ partition large class} \}. \end{align*} $$

Proof First, $\omega $ is partition generic in $\mathcal {U}_2 = \{ X : |X| \geq 2 \}$ . Suppose $X \in \mathcal {P}$ and let $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ . Let $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega $ be a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ partition large class in which X is partition generic. By Proposition 2.33, there is a $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {V}$ such that $\mathcal {U} \cap \mathcal {V}$ is partition large, together with some $i \leq k$ such that $Y_i$ is partition generic in $\mathcal {U} \cap \mathcal {V}$ . Note that $\mathcal {U} \cap \mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ , hence is non-trivial. It follows that $Y_i \in \mathcal {P}$ .

Partition genericity within a large class is not an interesting notion of typicality whenever one does not put effectiveness restrictions on the large classes. Indeed, we shall see that every infinite set is partition generic relative to itself within a large class. Given an infinite set X, let $\mathcal {U}_{X,2} = \{ Y : |Y \cap X| \geq 2\}$ .

Lemma 2.35. For every set X, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{X,2}) = \mathcal {L}_X$ .

Proof First, let us show that $\mathcal {L}_X \subseteq \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{X,2})$ . Suppose that $Y \in \mathcal {L}_X$ . By definition, $|Y \cap X| = \infty $ , so $Y \in \mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ . So $\mathcal {L}_X$ is a partition regular subclass of $\mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ . Since $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{X,2})$ is the largest partition regular subclass of $\mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ , then $\mathcal {L}_X \subseteq \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{X,2})$ .

Then, let us show that $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{X,2}) \subseteq \mathcal {L}_X$ . Let $Y \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{X,2})$ . We claim that $|Y \cap X| = \infty $ . Indeed, otherwise, consider the $|Y \cap X|$ -cover of $Y \cap X$ made of singletons. By partition regularity of $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{X,2})$ , one of the parts belongs to $\mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ , but $\mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ contains no singleton, contradiction. Therefore $|Y \cap X| = \infty $ , so $Y \in \mathcal {L}_X$ .

Lemma 2.36. For every infinite set X, $\mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ is a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1(X)$ partition large class.

Proof $\mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ is clearly non-trivial, upward-closed, and $\Sigma ^0_1(X)$ . By Lemma 2.35, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{X,2}) = \mathcal {L}_X$ . Since X is infinite, $X \in \mathcal {L}_X$ , so $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{X,2}) \neq \emptyset $ . By Proposition 2.18, $\mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ is large.

The following lemma shows, as promised, that every infinite set is partition generic relative to itself within a large class.

Lemma 2.37. For every set X, X belongs to any partition large subclass of $\,\mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ .

Proof Let $\mathcal {V}$ be a partition large subclass of $\mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ . Suppose for the contradiction that $X \not \in \mathcal {V}$ . By largeness of $\mathcal {V}$ , $\overline {X} \in \mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}_{X,2}$ . Then $|\overline {X} \cap X| \geq 2$ , contradiction.

By Patey [Reference Patey17], if f is a hyperimmune function, then for every set A, there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that f is H-hyperimmune. Is it also the case if one replaces hyperimmunity by partition genericity? We answer negatively by constructing a specific bi-partition generic set which is neither Kurtz random, nor bi-hyperimmune.

Lemma 2.38. For every set A and every infinite set $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ , then A is not H-partition generic.

Proof By Lemma 2.36, $\mathcal {U}_{H,2}$ is a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1(A)$ partition large class. In particular, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{H,2})$ is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2(H)$ partition generic class. However, $A \not \in \mathcal {U}_{H,2} \supseteq \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U}_{H,2})$ , so A is not H-partition generic.

Proposition 2.39. There is a bi-partition generic set A such that for every infinite set $H \subseteq A$ and $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ , neither A nor $\overline {A}$ is H-partition generic.

Proof Let A be the bi-partition generic set of Proposition 2.30. Let $H \subseteq A$ . By Lemma 2.38, $\overline {A}$ is not H-partition generic. Let $P = \{ 2n+1 : 2n \in H \} \cup \{2n : 2n+1 \in H \}$ . Then $P \subseteq \overline {A}$ . By Lemma 2.38, $\overline {A}$ is not P-partition generic, hence not H-partition generic. The case $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ is symmetric.

If we consider partition genericity in a non-trivial partition large open class, then the answer is positive, but in an unsatisfactory manner.

Proposition 2.40. Let B be an infinite set. For every set A, there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that B is H-partition generic in a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ partition large class.

Proof Let $H = A \cap B$ if it is infinite, otherwise $H = \overline {A} \cap B$ . By Lemma 2.36, $\mathcal {U}_{H,2}$ is a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ partition large class. We claim that B is H-partition generic in $\mathcal {U}_{H,2}$ . By Lemma 2.37, H is H-partition generic in $\mathcal {U}_{H,2}$ . Since $B \supseteq H$ , then A is also H-partition generic in $\mathcal {U}_{H,2}$ .

3 Applications

We now justify the study of partition genericity by proving several partition genericity subset basis theorems. All these basis theorems are proven with the same notion of forcing, that we call partition generic Mathias forcing. A condition is a tuple $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {U})$ , where $(\sigma , X)$ is a Mathias condition, that is, $\sigma $ is a finite string and X is an infinite set such that $\min X> |\sigma |$ . Moreover, $\mathcal {U}$ is a non-trivial large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class within which X is partition generic. A condition $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {V})$ extends another condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {U})$ if $(\tau , Y)$ Mathias extends $(\sigma , X)$ , that is, $\sigma \prec \tau $ , $Y \subseteq X$ , and $\tau \setminus \sigma \subseteq X$ . Moreover, we require that $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ .

Note that we do not impose any effectivity restriction to the reservoir X. In particular, if A is a set which is partition generic in a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ large class $\mathcal {U}$ , then we will consider sufficiently generic filters containing the condition $(\emptyset , A, \mathcal {U})$ . Indeed, any such filter $\mathcal {F}$ induces a subset $G_{\mathcal {F}} = \bigcup _{(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V}) \in \mathcal {F}} \sigma $ of A.

The first property we prove is that $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is an infinite set.

Lemma 3.1. Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a sufficiently generic filter. Then $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is infinite.

Proof Let us show that for any n, the set of conditions $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {U})$ such that $\tau (x) = 1$ for some $x> n$ is dense. Let $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {U})$ be a condition. Since X is partition generic in $\mathcal {U}$ and $\mathcal {U}$ is non-trivial, then $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {U})$ , hence X is infinite. Let $x \in X$ be greater than n, let $\tau $ be string $\sigma \cup \{x\}$ , and let $Y = X \setminus \{0, \dots , |\rho |\}$ . By Proposition 2.23, Y is partition generic in $\mathcal {U}$ . Therefore, $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {U})$ is a valid extension of $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {U})$ .

We now turn to the various partition genericity subset basis theorems.

3.1 Cone avoidance

The first one is the cone avoidance partition genericity subset basis theorem. Recall that Dzhafarov and Jockusch [Reference Dzhafarov and Jockusch3] proved that if B is a non-computable set, then for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that $B \not \leq _T H$ . We prove the corresponding partition genericity theorem.

Lemma 3.2. Let B be a non-computable set and let $\Phi _e$ be a Turing functional. Then for every condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {U})$ , there is an extension $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {U})$ forcing $\Phi _e^G \neq B$ .

Proof A split pair is a pair of strings $\rho _0, \rho _1$ such that there is an input $x \in \omega $ for which $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho _0}(x)\downarrow \neq \Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho _1}(x)\downarrow $ . We have two cases.

Case 1: the following class is large:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{A} = \{ Y \in \mathcal{U} : Y\ \mathit{contains\ a\ split\ pair} \}. \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathcal {A}$ is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2$ large subclass of $\mathcal {U}$ and X is partition generic in $\mathcal {U}$ , then $X \in \mathcal {A}$ . Let $\rho _0, \rho _1 \subseteq X$ be a split pair, with witness x. In particular, there is some $i < 2$ such that $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho _i}(x)\neq B(x)$ . Let $Y = X \setminus \{0, \dots , |\rho _i|\}$ . By Proposition 2.23, Y is partition generic in $\mathcal {U}$ . Then $(\sigma \cup \rho _i, Y, \mathcal {U})$ is an extension of $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {U})$ forcing $\Phi _e^G(x) \neq B(x)$ .

Case 2: there is some $k \in \omega $ such that the following class is non-empty:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{C} = \{ Z_0 \oplus \dots \oplus Z_{k-1} : Z_0 \cup \dots \cup Z_{k-1} = \omega \wedge \forall i < k\ Z_i\, \not \in \mathcal{U} \mbox{ or } Z_i \mbox{ contains no split pair} \}. \end{align*} $$

Note that $\mathcal {C}$ is a $\Pi ^0_1$ class. By the cone avoidance basis theorem [Reference Jockusch and Soare7], there is an element $Z_0 \oplus \dots \oplus Z_{k-1} \in \mathcal {C}$ such that $B \not \leq _T Z_0 \oplus \dots \oplus Z_{k-1}$ . By Proposition 2.33, there is a $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {V}$ such that $\mathcal {V} \cap \mathcal {U}$ is large and some $i < k$ such that $Z_i \cap X$ is partition generic in $\mathcal {V} \cap \mathcal {U}$ . Note that in particular, $Z_i \cap X \in \mathcal {V} \cap \mathcal {U}$ , so $Z_i \in \mathcal {U}$ , hence $Z_i$ contains no split pair.

The condition $(\sigma , Z_i \cap X, \mathcal {V} \cap \mathcal {U})$ is a valid extension of $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {U})$ .

We claim that $(\sigma , Z_i \cap X, \mathcal {V} \cap \mathcal {U})$ forces $\Phi ^G_e \neq B$ . Suppose for the contradiction that $\Phi ^{G_{\mathcal {F}}}_e = B$ for some generic filter $\mathcal {F}$ . Let $f : \omega \to 2$ be the partial $Z_i$ -computable function which on input x, searches for some $\rho \subseteq Z_i$ such that $\Phi ^{\sigma \cup \rho }_e(x)\downarrow $ . If such a $\rho $ is found, then $f(x) = \Phi ^{\sigma \cup \rho }_e(x)\downarrow $ . Since $\Phi ^{G_{\mathcal {F}}}_e = B$ , then f is total. Since $Z_i$ contains no split pair, then $f = B$ , which contradicts the assumption that $B \not \leq _T Z_i$ .

Theorem 3.3. Let A be a set which is partition generic in a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ large class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega $ . Then for every non-computable set B, there is an infinite set $G \subseteq A$ such that $B \not \leq _T G$ .

Proof Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a sufficiently generic filter containing $(\emptyset , A, \mathcal {U})$ . By Lemma 3.1, $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is infinite. By construction, $G_{\mathcal {F}} \subseteq A$ . Last, by Lemma 3.2, $B \not \leq _T G_{\mathcal {F}}$ .

Corollary 3.4 (Dzhafarov and Jockusch [Reference Dzhafarov and Jockusch3]).

Let B be a non-computable set. Then for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that $B \not \leq _T H$ .

Proof By Corollary 2.34, either A or $\overline {A}$ is partition generic in a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ large class. Apply Theorem 3.3.

3.2 PA avoidance

We now turn to a PA avoidance partition genericity subset basis theorem. Liu [Reference Liu12] proved that for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ of non-PA degree. We prove the corresponding partition genericity theorem.

Lemma 3.5. For every condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {U})$ and every Turing functional $\Phi _e$ , there is an extension $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {V})$ forcing $\Phi ^G_e$ not to be a DNC ${}_2$ function.

Proof For every k, let $S_k$ be the set of pairs $(x, v) \in \omega \times 2$ such that for every k-cover $Z_0 \sqcup \dots \sqcup Z_{k-1} \supseteq \omega $ , there is some $j < k$ such that $Z_j \in \mathcal {U}$ , and some $\rho \subseteq Z_j$ such that $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(x)\downarrow = v$ . Note that the set $S_k$ is $\Sigma ^0_1$ uniformly in k. We have two cases:

Case 1: for every $k \in \omega $ , there is some $x \in \omega $ such that $(x, \Phi _x(x)) \in S_k$ . Then the following class is large:

$$ \begin{align*}\{Y \in \mathcal{U} : \exists x\ \exists \rho \subseteq Y\ \Phi^{\sigma \cup \rho}_e(x)\downarrow = \Phi_x(x) \}. \end{align*} $$

Since X is partition generic, then it belongs to this class, so there is some x and some $\rho \subseteq X$ such that $\Phi ^{\sigma \cup \rho }_e(x)\downarrow = \Phi _x(x)$ . Let $Y = X \setminus \{0, \dots , |\rho |\}$ . Note that Y is again partition generic in $\mathcal {U}$ , so $(\sigma \cup \rho , Y, \mathcal {U})$ is an extension forcing $\Phi ^G_e(x)\downarrow = \Phi _x(x)$ .

Case 2: there is some $k \in \omega $ such that for every $x \in \omega $ , if $\Phi _x(x)\downarrow $ , then $(x, \Phi _x(x)) \not \in S_k$ . Then there must be some x such that $(x, 0), (x, 1) \not \in S_k$ , otherwise we would compute a DNC ${}_2$ function by waiting, for each x, for some $v < 2$ such that $(x, v)$ is enumerated in $S_k$ . Let x be such that $(x, 0), (x, 1) \not \in S_k$ . By definition of $S_k$ , there are two k-covers of $\omega $ , $Z^0_0 \cup \dots \cup Z^0_{k-1} = \omega $ and $Z^1_0 \cup \dots \cup Z^1_{k-1} = \omega $ such that for every $i < 2$ and every $j < k$ such that $Z^i_j \in \mathcal {U}$ , and every $\rho \subseteq Z^i_j$ such that $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(x)\downarrow $ , then $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(x) \neq i$ .

Then $\langle Z^0_s \cap Z^1_t : s, t < k \rangle $ is a $k^2$ -cover of $\omega $ such that for every $s, t < k$ , either $Z^0_s \cap Z^1_t \not \in \mathcal {U}$ , or for every $\rho \subseteq Z^i_j$ , $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(x)\uparrow $ . By Proposition 2.33, there is a non-trivial large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ and some $s, t < k$ such that $Z^0_s \cap Z^1_t \cap X$ is partition regular in $\mathcal {V}$ . The condition $(\sigma , Z^0_s \cap Z^1_t \cap X, \mathcal {V})$ is an extension forcing $\Phi ^G_e(x)\uparrow $ .

Theorem 3.6. Let A be a set which is partition generic in a non-trivial large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega $ . Then there is an infinite set $G \subseteq A$ of non-PA degree.

Proof Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a sufficiently generic filter containing $(\emptyset , A, \mathcal {U})$ . By Lemma 3.1, $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is infinite. By construction, $G_{\mathcal {F}} \subseteq A$ . Last, by Lemma 3.5, $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is of non-PA degree.

Corollary 3.7 (Liu [Reference Liu12]).

For every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ of non-PA degree.

Proof By Corollary 2.34, either A or $\overline {A}$ is partition generic in a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ large class. Apply Theorem 3.6.

Remark 3.8. In all the arguments above, one could have worked with a generalized notion of condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {L})$ where $\mathcal {L}$ is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class. Then, for every sufficiently generic filter $\mathcal {F}$ and every condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {L})$ , $G_{\mathcal {F}} \in \mathcal {L}$ . This implies in particular that all these partition generic basis theorems also hold if one replaces “there exists an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ ” by “there exists a subset $H \subseteq A$ such that $H \in \mathcal {L}$ ” for any non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class $\mathcal {L}$ .

3.3 Constant-bound trace avoidance

Soon after proving his PA avoidance pigeonhole basis theorem, Liu proved a constant bound trace avoidance pigeonhole basis theorem, with several consequences, such as the existence, for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , of an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ which does not compute any Martin-Löf random, or even no set of positive effective Hausdorff dimension.

Definition 3.9. A k-trace is a sequence of finite sets of strings $F_0, F_1, \dots $ such that for every n, $|F_n| = k$ and every string $\sigma \in F_n$ is of length n. A constant-bound trace is a k-trace for some $k \in \omega $ . A k-trace of a class $\mathcal {C} \subseteq 2^\omega $ is a k-trace $F_0, F_1, \dots $ such that $[F_n] \cap \mathcal {C} \neq \emptyset $ for every n, where $[F_n] = \bigcup _{\sigma \in F_n} [\sigma ]$ .

Liu [Reference Liu13] proved that if $\mathcal {C} \subseteq 2^\omega $ is a non-empty $\Pi ^0_1$ class with no computable 1-trace, then for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ which does not compute any 1-trace of $\mathcal {C}$ . We prove the corresponding partition genericity subset basis theorem.

Lemma 3.10. Let $\mathcal {C} \subseteq 2^\omega $ be a non-empty $\Pi ^0_1$ class with no computable 1-trace. For every condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {U})$ and every Turing functional $\Phi _e$ , there is an extension $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {V})$ forcing $\Phi ^G_e$ not to be a 1-trace of $\mathcal {C}$ .

Proof For every k, let $S_k$ be the set of strings $\mu \in 2^{<\omega }$ such that for every k-cover $Z_0 \sqcup \dots \sqcup Z_{k-1} \supseteq \omega $ , there is some $j < k$ such that $Z_j \in \mathcal {U}$ , and some $\rho \subseteq Z_j$ such that $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(|\mu |)\downarrow = \mu $ . Note that the set $S_k$ is $\Sigma ^0_1$ uniformly in k. We have two cases:

Case 1: for every $k \in \omega $ , there is some $\mu \in S_k$ such that $[\mu ] \cap \mathcal {C} = \emptyset $ . Then the following class is large:

$$ \begin{align*}\{ \!Y \in \mathcal{U} : \exists \mu\ \exists \rho \subseteq Y\ \Phi^{\sigma \cup \rho}_e(|\mu|)\downarrow = \mu \wedge [\mu] \cap \mathcal{C} = \emptyset \} \end{align*} $$

is large. Since X is partition generic, then it belongs to this class, so there is some $\mu \in 2^{<\omega }$ and some $\rho \subseteq X$ such that $\Phi ^{\sigma \cup \rho }_e(|\mu |)\downarrow = \mu $ and $[\mu ] \cap \mathcal {C} = \emptyset $ . Let $Y = X \setminus \{0, \dots , |\rho |\}$ . Note that Y is again partition generic in $\mathcal {U}$ , so $(\sigma \cup \rho , Y, \mathcal {U})$ is an extension forcing $\Phi ^G_e(|\mu |)\downarrow = \mu $ .

Case 2: there is some $k \in \omega $ such that for every $\mu \in S_k$ , $[\mu ] \cap \mathcal {C} \neq \emptyset $ . Then there must be some n such that $S_k$ contains no string of length n. Indeed, otherwise, one would compute a 1-trace of $\mathcal {C}$ , contradicting our hypothesis. For every string $\mu $ of length n, let $Z^\mu _0 \cup \dots \cup Z^\mu _{k-1} = \omega $ be a k-cover such that for every $j < k$ such that $Z^\mu _j \in \mathcal {U}$ , and every $\rho \subseteq Z^\mu _j$ such that $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(n)\downarrow $ , then $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(n) \neq \mu $ .

Let $\langle P_j : j < k^{2^n} \rangle $ be the $k^{2^n}$ -cover of $\omega $ refining all the k-covers above. Then for every $j < k^{2^n}$ and every $\rho \subseteq P_j$ , $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(n)\uparrow $ . By Proposition 2.33, there is a non-trivial large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ and some $j < k^{2^n}$ such that $P_j \cap X$ is partition regular in $\mathcal {V}$ . The condition $(\sigma , P_j \cap X, \mathcal {V})$ is an extension forcing $\Phi ^G_e(n)\uparrow $ .

Theorem 3.11. Let A be a set which is partition generic in a non-trivial large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega $ . For every countable collection of non-empty $\Pi ^0_1$ classes $\mathcal {C}_0, \mathcal {C}_1, \dots $ with no computable 1-trace. Then there is an infinite set $G \subseteq A$ such that none of the classes $\mathcal {C}_n$ admits a G-computable 1-trace.

Proof Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a sufficiently generic filter containing $(\emptyset , A, \mathcal {U})$ . By Lemma 3.1, $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is infinite. By construction, $G_{\mathcal {F}} \subseteq A$ . Last, by Lemma 3.10, none of the classes $\mathcal {C}_n$ admits a $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ -computable 1-trace.

Corollary 3.12 (Liu [Reference Liu13]).

Let $\mathcal {C}_0, \mathcal {C}_1, \dots $ be a countable collection of non-empty $\Pi ^0_1$ classes with no computable 1-trace. For every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that none of the classes $\mathcal {C}_n$ admits an H-computable 1-trace.

Proof By Corollary 2.34, either A or $\overline {A}$ is partition generic in a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ large class. Apply Theorem 3.11.

Corollary 3.13. Let $\mathcal {C}_0, \mathcal {C}_1, \dots $ be a countable collection of non-empty $\Pi ^0_1$ classes with no computable 1-trace. For every Kurtz random $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that none of the classes $\mathcal {C}_n$ admits an H-computable 1-trace.

Proof By Proposition 2.26, every Kurtz random is bi-partition generic. Apply Theorem 3.11.

We obtain in particular the following theorem, which improves the result of Kjos-Hanssen and Liu [Reference Kjos-Hanssen and Liu10] from Martin-Löf randomness to Kurtz randomness.

Theorem 3.14. For every Kurtz random A, there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ which does not compute any set of positive effective Hausdorff dimension.

Proof For every $m,c$ , let $\mathcal {C}_{m,c} = \{ X : \forall k K( X \upharpoonright _k ) \geq k/m-c\}$ . A set X has positive effective Hausdorff dimension iff $X \in \mathcal {C}_{m,c}$ for some $m,c \in \omega $ . For every $m,c \in \omega $ , $\mathcal {C}_{m,c}$ has no computable 1-trace (see Corollary 1.4 in [Reference Kjos-Hanssen and Liu10]). By Corollary 3.13, there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that none of the classes $\mathcal {C}_{m,c}$ admits an H-computable 1-trace. In particular, H does not compute any set of positive effective Hausdorff dimension.

3.4 Lowness

It is clearly not the case that for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ of low degree. One can simply pick A to be any bi-immune set relative to $\emptyset '$ . Then A has no even $\Delta ^0_2$ infinite subset in it or its complement. Therefore, there is no low or even $\Delta ^0_2$ partition genericity subset basis theorem. More interestingly, Downey et al. [Reference Downey, Hirschfeldt, Lempp and Solomon2] constructed a $\Delta ^0_2$ set with no low infinite subset in it or its complement, using a very involved infinite injury priority argument. Thus, there is no hope of proving that every $\Delta ^0_2$ partition generic sets has a low subset. On the other hand, if A is a $\Delta ^0_2$ set such that $\overline {A}$ is not partition generic, then A is partition generic in a non-trivial $\Sigma ^0_1$ partition large class in a strong sense, in which case A admits an infinite low subset.

Theorem 3.15. Let A be a $\Delta ^0_2$ set such that $\overline {A}$ is not partition generic. Then there is an infinite subset $G \subseteq A$ of low degree.

Proof Let $\bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ be a $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular class such that $\overline {A} \not \in \bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ . In particular, there is some $m \in \omega $ such that $\overline {A} \not \in \mathcal {V}_m$ . Define a $\Delta ^0_2$ decreasing sequence of Mathias conditions $(\sigma _0, X_0) \geq (\sigma _1, X_1) \geq \cdots $ such that for every $s \in \omega $ :

  1. (1) $\sigma _s \subseteq A$ ; $X_s$ is low; $X_s \in \bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ ;

  2. (2) $\sigma _{s+1} \in \mathcal {V}_e$ if $s = 2e$ ;

  3. (3) $(\sigma _{s+1}, X_{s+1}) \Vdash \Phi ^G_e(e)\downarrow $ or $(\sigma _{s+1}, X_{s+1}) \Vdash \Phi ^G_e(e)\uparrow $ if $s = 2e+1$ .

Start with the condition $(\emptyset , \omega )$ .

Satisfying (2): Given a condition $(\sigma _s, X_s)$ at a stage $s = 2e$ , search $\emptyset '$ -computably for some finite $\rho \subseteq X \cap A$ such that $\rho \in \mathcal {V}_s$ . We claim that such a $\rho $ must exist. Indeed, since X belongs to the partition regular class $\bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ , then either $X \cap A$ or $X \cap \overline {A}$ belongs to $\bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ . However, $\overline {A} \not \in \mathcal {V}_m$ , so by upward-closure of partition regular classes, $X \cap \overline {A} \not \in \bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ , hence $X \cap A \in \bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ . The condition $(\sigma _s \cup \rho , X_s - \{0, \dots , \max \rho \})$ satisfies (2).

Satisfying (3): Given an condition $(\sigma _s, X_s)$ at stage $s = 2e+1$ , consider the $\Pi ^{0,X_s}_1$ class $\mathcal {C}$ of all B such that $\overline {B} \not \in \mathcal {V}_m$ and $(\sigma _s, X_s \cap B) \Vdash \Phi ^G_e(e)\uparrow $ . Decide $\emptyset '$ -computably if $\mathcal {C}$ is empty or not. If $\mathcal {C} = \emptyset $ , then in particular $A \not \in \mathcal {C}$ , so $(\sigma _s, X_s \cap A) \not \Vdash \Phi ^G_e(e)\uparrow $ . Search $\emptyset '$ -computably for some $\rho \subseteq X_s \cap A$ such that $\Phi ^{\sigma _s \cup \rho }_e(e)\downarrow $ . The condition $(\sigma _s \cup \rho , X_s - \{0, \dots , \max \rho \})$ forces $\Phi ^G_e(e)\downarrow $ , hence satisfies (3). If $\mathcal {C} \neq \emptyset $ , then by the low basis theorem, there is some $B \in \mathcal {C}$ of low degree. In particular, $\overline {B} \not \in \mathcal {V}_m$ so $\overline {B} \cap X_s \not \in \mathcal {V}_m$ . However, $X_s \in \bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ , so by partition regularity of $\bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ , $B \cap X_s \in \bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ . The condition $(\sigma _s, X_s \cap B)$ forces $\Phi ^G_e(e)\uparrow $ , hence satisfies (3).

This completes the construction. Let $G = \bigcup _s \sigma _s$ . In particular, by (1), $G \subseteq A$ . By (2) $G \in \bigcap _n \mathcal {V}_n$ , hence G is infinite. By (3), $G' \leq _T \emptyset '$ . This completes the proof.

The previous theorem gives us a characterization of the $\Delta ^0_2$ sets with no low infinite subset in them or their complements.

Corollary 3.16. A $\Delta ^0_2$ set A has no low infinite subset in it or its complement iff it is bi-partition generic relative to every low set.

Proof Suppose A is bi-partition generic relative to every low set. By Proposition 2.25, A is bi-immune relative to every low set, hence has no low infinite subset in it or its complement.

Suppose A is not bi-partition generic relative to a low set L. By symmetry, say $\overline {A}$ is not partition generic relative to L. By Theorem 3.15 relativized to L, there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that $H' \leq _T L' \leq _T \emptyset '$ , hence A has an infinite low subset.

Corollary 3.17. There is a $\Delta ^0_2$ set which is bi-partition generic relative to every low set.

Proof Immediate by the previous corollary and the existence of a $\Delta ^0_2$ set with no low infinite subset in either it or its complement [Reference Downey, Hirschfeldt, Lempp and Solomon2].

4 Preservation of hyperimmunity

The purpose of this section is to find the right genericity notion admitting a preservation of hyperimmunity genericity basis theorem, implying the preservation of hyperimmunity pigeonhole basis theorem. More precisely, the following theorem was proven by Patey [Reference Patey, Beckmann, Mitrana and Soskova16]:

Theorem 4.1 (Patey [Reference Patey, Beckmann, Mitrana and Soskova16]).

If B is a hyperimmune set, then for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that B is H-hyperimmune.

Partition genericity is not the right notion to reprove this pigeonhole basis theorem. Indeed, the following proposition shows that there is no preservation of hyperimmunity partition genericity basis theorem.

Proposition 4.2. There is a hyperimmune set B and a partition generic set A such that B is hyperimmune relative to no infinite subset of A.

Proof Let A be a bi-hyperimmune set and let $B = A$ . Since A is co-hyperimmune, by Proposition 2.27, A is partition generic. Let H be an infinite subset of A. Then, H is an infinite subset of B, so B is not H-hyperimmune.

The remainder of this section is devoted to the design of a notion of genericity which admits a preservation of hyperimmunity basis theorem, implying Proposition 4.2.

4.1 Hyperimmunity genericity

From now on, fix a set $B \subseteq \omega $ . All the following definitions hold for any B, but because of Proposition 4.14, the only interesting case is when the set B is hyperimmune. In what follows, recall that we identify a string $\sigma $ with the set $\{ n < |\sigma | : \sigma (n) = 1 \}$ . Hence, $Y \setminus \sigma $ denotes the set $\{ n \in Y : n \geq |\sigma | \vee \sigma (n) = 0 \}$ .

Definition 4.3. A class $\mathcal {L} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular if it is non-empty, upward-closed, and for every $(X,Y) \in \mathcal {L}$ , every k, every k-cover $Z_0 \cup \dots \cup Z_{k-1} \supseteq X$ and every $\sigma \in 2^{<\omega }$ , there is some $j < k$ such that $(Z_j, Y \setminus \sigma ) \in \mathcal {L}$ .

Proposition 4.4. Suppose $\{\mathcal {L}_i\}_{i \in I}$ is an arbitrary non-empty collection of $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular classes. Then $\bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular.

Proof It is clear that $\bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ is not empty. Let $(X_0,X_1) \in \bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ . Let $Y_0 \supseteq X_0$ and $Y_1 \supseteq X_1$ . There is some $i \in I$ such that $(X_0,X_1) \in \mathcal {L}_i$ . As $\mathcal {L}_i$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular, $(Y_0,Y_1) \in \mathcal {L}_i \subseteq \bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ .

Let $(X_0,X_1) \in \bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ . Let $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ and $\sigma \in 2^{<\omega }$ . There is some $i \in I$ such that $(X_0,X_1) \in \mathcal {L}_i$ . As $\mathcal {L}_i$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular, $(Y_j,X_1 \setminus \sigma ) \in \mathcal {L}_i \subseteq \bigcup _{i \in I} \mathcal {L}_i$ for some $j \leq k$ .

Definition 4.5. Given a class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ , let $\mathcal {L}_{\mathfrak {H}}(\mathcal {A})$ denote the largest $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . If $\mathcal {A}$ does not contain a $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular class, let $\mathcal {L}_{\mathfrak {H}}(\mathcal {A})$ be the empty set.

Proposition 4.6. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ be an upward-closed class. Then

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{L}_{\mathfrak{H}}(\mathcal{A}) = \left\{(X,Y) \in 2^\omega \times 2^\omega \ : \begin{array}{l} \forall k \forall X_0 \cup \dots \cup X_k \supseteq X \\ \forall \sigma \in 2^{<\omega}\ \exists i \leq k\ (X_i, Y \setminus \sigma) \in \mathcal{A} \end{array} \right\}.\end{align*} $$

Definition 4.7. A class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -large if it is upward-closed and for every co-finite set $X_1$ , $\{ X_0 : (X_0, X_1) \in \mathcal {A} \}$ is partition large.

Proposition 4.8. A class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -large iff it is upward-closed and contains a $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular subclass.

Proof Suppose $\mathcal {A}$ is upward-closed and contains an $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular subclass $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ . Upward closure is trivially satisfied by hypothesis. By $\mathfrak {H}$ -regularity of $\mathcal {L}$ , $(\omega ,\omega ) \in \mathcal {L}$ and for every k-cover $Y_0, \dots , Y_{k-1}$ of $\omega $ , and every $\sigma \in 2^{<\omega }$ , there is some $j < k$ such that $(\! Y_j, \omega \setminus \sigma ) \in \mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ . So $\mathcal {A}$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -large.

Suppose now $\mathcal {A}$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -large. It is upward-closed by definition. We claim that $\mathcal {L}_{\mathfrak {H}}(\mathcal {A})$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular. By definition of $\mathfrak {H}$ -largeness and Theorem 4.6, $(\omega ,\omega ) \in \mathcal {L}_{\mathfrak {H}}(\mathcal {A})$ , so $\mathcal {L}_{\mathfrak {H}}(\mathcal {A}) \neq \emptyset $ . By definition of $\mathcal {L}_{\mathfrak {H}}(\mathcal {A})$ , it is $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular, hence $\mathcal {A}$ contains an $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular subclass.

Definition 4.9. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ be a class. We say that X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ if $(X,\overline {B})$ belongs to every non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2 \mathfrak {H}$ -regular subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . If X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ , we simply say that X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic.

Proposition 4.10. If X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ and $Y \supseteq X$ , then Y is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proof Let $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ be any non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2 \mathfrak {H}$ -regular subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . Since X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ , then $(X,\overline {B}) \in \mathcal {L}$ . Since $Y \supseteq X$ , then by upward-closure of $\mathcal {L}$ , $(Y, \overline {B}) \in \mathcal {L}$ . Therefore Y is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proposition 4.11. If X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ and $Y =^{*} X$ , then Y is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proof Let $\mathcal {L} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ be any non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2 \mathfrak {H}$ -regular subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . Since X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ , then $(X,\overline {B}) \in \mathcal {L}$ . Since $Y =^{*} X$ , then there is a finite set F such that $Y \cup F \supseteq X$ . By $\mathfrak {H}$ -regularity of $\mathcal {L}$ , either $(Y,\overline {B})$ or $(F,\overline {B})$ belongs to $\mathcal {L}$ . Since $\mathcal {L}$ is non-trivial, $(F,\overline {B}) \notin \mathcal {L}$ , so $(Y,\overline {B}) \in \mathcal {L}$ . Therefore Y is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Lemma 4.12. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ be a class and let X be $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . For every $Y_0 \cup Y_1 \supseteq X$ , if $(Y_0,\overline {B}) \notin \mathcal {L}_{\mathfrak {H}}(\mathcal {A})$ , then $Y_1$ is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proof Suppose for contradiction that there is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2 \mathfrak {H}$ -regular class $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ such that $(Y_1,\overline {B}) \notin \mathcal {V}$ . In particular, $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {L}_{\mathfrak {H}}(A)$ , so $(Y_0,\overline {B}) \notin \mathcal {V}$ . By partition $\mathfrak {H}$ -regularity of $\mathcal {V}$ , since $Y_0 \cup Y_1 \supseteq X$ , then $(X,\overline {B}) \notin \mathcal {V}$ , which contradicts $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -genericity of X in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proposition 4.13. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ be a non-trivial $\mathfrak {H}$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class. Suppose X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . Let $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ . Then there is a non-trivial $\mathfrak {H}$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ subclass $\mathcal {U} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ together with some $i \leq k$ such that $Y_i$ is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {U}$ .

Proof We proceed by induction on k. For $k = 0$ , $Y_0 \supseteq X$ , so by Proposition 4.10, $Y_0$ is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . Take $\mathcal {U} = \mathcal {A}$ and we are done.

Suppose now that the property holds for $k-1$ . Suppose $Y_k$ is not $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . Thus there is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2 \mathfrak {H}$ -regular class $\bigcap _{e \in C} \mathcal {U}_e \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ such that $(Y_k,\overline {B}) \not \in \bigcap _{e \in C} \mathcal {U}_e$ . In particular, there is some $e \in \mathcal {C}$ such that $(Y_k,\overline {B}) \notin \mathcal {U}_e$ . Note that $\bigcap _{e \in C} \mathcal {U}_e \subseteq \mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {U}_e$ , so $\mathcal {A} \cap \mathcal {U}_e$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -large. By Theorem 4.12, $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_{k-1}$ is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {U}_e \cap \mathcal {A}$ . By induction hypothesis on $\mathcal {U}_e \cap \mathcal {A}$ and $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_{k-1}$ , there is a non-trivial $\mathfrak {H}$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}_e \cap \mathcal {A}$ , together with some $i < k$ such that $Y_i$ is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {V}$ .

Proposition 4.14. Suppose B is hyperimmune. Then $\omega $ is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic.

Proof Let $\mathcal {L} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ be a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2 \mathfrak {H}$ -regular class. We can assume $\mathcal {L} = \bigcap _n \mathcal {U}_n$ for some decreasing sequence of $\Sigma ^0_1 \mathfrak {H}$ -large classes. Fix $n \in \omega $ and let $W \subseteq 2^{<\omega } \times 2^{<\omega }$ be a c.e. set such that $\mathcal {U}_n = \{ (X,Y) : \exists (\rho _0, \rho _1) \in W\ \rho _0 \subseteq X \wedge \rho _1 \subseteq Y \}$ . Let P be a cofinite set.

Fix some $s \in \omega $ . Since $\mathcal {U}_n$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -large, then $(\omega , \{s+1, s+2, \dots \}) \in \mathcal {U}_n$ . Therefore, there is some $(\rho _0, \rho _1) \in W$ such that $\min \rho _1> s$ . Let $F_s = \rho _1$ . Note that $F_s$ can be found computably uniformly in s. Since B is hyperimmune, there is some s such that $F_s \subseteq \overline {B}$ . It follows that $(\omega , \overline {B}) \in \mathcal {U}_n$ . Since this holds for every n, then $(\omega , \overline {B}) \in \bigcap _n \mathcal {U}_n = \mathcal {L}$ .

Proposition 4.15. Suppose B is hyperimmune and A is partition generic relative to B. Then A is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic.

Proof Let $\mathcal {L} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ be a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2 \mathfrak {H}$ -regular class. By Proposition 4.14, $(\omega , \overline {B}) \in \mathcal {L}$ . Since $\mathcal {L}$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -regular, then for every k, every $Z_0 \cup \dots \cup Z_{k-1} = \omega $ , there is some $j < k$ such that $(Z_j, \overline {B}) \in L$ . Thus the class $\mathcal {L}_0 = \{ X : (X, \overline {B}) \in \mathcal {L} \}$ is partition large. Moreover, $\mathcal {L}_0$ is $\Pi ^0_2(B)$ , so since A is partition generic relative to B, $A \in \mathcal {L}_0$ . It follows that $(A,\overline {B}) \in \mathcal {L}$ .

4.2 Applications

We now turn to the main application of $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -genericity, that is, a partition genericity subset basis theorem for preservation of hyperimmunity. As mentioned earlier, the basic preservation of hyperimmunity statement fails for partition genericity. However, when one considers relativized partition genericity, then one can prove such as basis theorem.

Theorem 4.16. Suppose A is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in a non-trivial $\mathfrak {H}$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ . Then there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is H-hyperimmune.

Proof Consider the notion of forcing $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ where $(\sigma , X)$ is as Mathias condition, and $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ is an $\mathfrak {H}$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class within which X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic. A condition $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {W})$ extends another condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ if $(\tau , Y)$ Mathias extends $(\sigma , X)$ and $\mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ .

Any filter $\mathcal {F}$ induces a subset $G_{\mathcal {F}} = \bigcup _{(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V}) \in \mathcal {F}} \sigma $ of A. The first property we prove is that $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is an infinite set.

Lemma 4.17. Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a sufficiently generic filter. Then $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is infinite.

Proof Let us show that for any n, the set of conditions $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {V})$ such that $\tau (x) = 1$ for some $x> n$ is dense. Let $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ be a condition. Since X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {V}$ and $\mathcal {V}$ is non-trivial, then $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ , hence X is infinite. Let $x \in X$ be greater than n, let $\tau $ be string $\sigma \cup \{x\}$ , and let $Y = X \setminus \{0, \dots , |\rho |\}$ . By Proposition 4.11, Y is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {V}$ . Therefore, $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {V})$ is a valid extension of $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ .

In the following lemma, we interpret $\Phi _e^G$ as a partial G-c.e. array $\{ \Phi _e^G(n) : n \in \omega \}$ . An array $\{F_n : n \in \omega \}$ intersects a set C if $\forall n\ F_n \cap C \neq \emptyset $ .

Lemma 4.18. For every condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ , there is an extension $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {W})$ forcing $\Phi _e^G$ not to be a G-c.e. array intersecting B.

Proof We have two cases.

Case 1: the following class is $\mathfrak {H}$ -large:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{A} = \{ (Y,C) \in \mathcal{V} : \exists \rho \subseteq Y \exists n\ \Phi_e^{\sigma \cup \rho}(n) \subseteq C \}. \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathcal {A}$ is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2 \mathfrak {H}$ -large subclass of $\mathcal {U}$ and X is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {U}$ , then $(X,\overline {B}) \in \mathcal {A}$ . Therefore there is some $\rho \subseteq X$ and some n such that $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(n) \subseteq \overline {B}$ . Let $Y = X \setminus \{0, \dots , |\rho |\}$ . By Proposition 4.11, Y is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {V}$ . Therefore $(\sigma \cup \rho , Y, \mathcal {V})$ is an extension of $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ forcing $\Phi _e^G(n) \subseteq \overline {B}$ .

Case 2: there is a co-finite set P and some k such that the following class is non-empty:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{C} = \left\{ Z_0 \oplus \dots \oplus Z_{k-1} : \begin{array}{l} Z_0 \cup \dots \cup Z_{k-1} = \omega \wedge \\ \forall i < k\ (Z_i,P) \not \in \mathcal{V} \vee \forall n \forall \rho \subseteq Z_i \Phi_e^{\sigma \cup \rho}(n)\uparrow \vee \Phi_e^{\sigma \cup \rho}(n) \not \subseteq P \end{array} \!\!\!\!\right\}\!. \end{align*} $$

Note that $\mathcal {C}$ is a non-empty $\Pi ^0_1$ class. Pick any element $Z_0 \oplus \dots \oplus Z_{k-1} \in \mathcal {C}$ . By Proposition 4.13, there is an $\mathfrak {H}$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ subclass $\mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ and some $i < k$ such that $Z_i \cap X$ is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {W}$ . In particular, $(Z_i \cap X, \overline {B}) \in \mathcal {L}_{\mathfrak {H}}(W) \subseteq \mathcal {W}$ , so $(Z_i \cap X, \overline {B} \cap P) \in W \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ and by upward-closure of V, $(Z_i, P) \in \mathcal {V}$ , so for every n and every $\rho \subseteq Z_i$ , $\Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(n)\uparrow \vee \Phi _e^{\sigma \cup \rho }(n) \not \subseteq P$ . The condition $(\sigma , Z_i \cap X, \mathcal {W})$ is an extension of $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ forcing $\Phi _e^{G}$ not to be a c.e. array.

We are now ready to prove Theorem 4.16. Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a sufficiently generic filter containing $(\emptyset , A, \mathcal {U})$ . By Lemma 4.17, $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is infinite. By construction, $G_{\mathcal {F}} \subseteq A$ . Last, by Lemma 4.18, B is $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ -hyperimmune.

Corollary 4.19. Suppose B is hyperimmune and A is partition generic relative to B. Then there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is H-hyperimmune.

Proof By Proposition 4.15, A is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic. By Theorem 4.16, there is infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is H-hyperimmune.

Corollary 4.20. Suppose B is hyperimmune and A is Kurtz random relative to B. Then there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is H-hyperimmune.

Proof By Proposition 2.26, A is partition generic relative to B. Apply Corollary 4.19.

Corollary 4.21. Let B be a hyperimmune set. Then for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that B is H-hyperimmune.

Proof By Proposition 4.14, $\omega $ is $\mathfrak {H}(B)$ -generic. By Proposition 4.13, there is an $\mathfrak {H}$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega \times 2^\omega $ within which either A or $\overline {A}$ is $\mathfrak {H}$ -generic. By Theorem 4.16, there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that B is H-hyperimmune.

5 Preservation of non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ definitions

The purpose of this section is to find the right genericity notion admitting a preservation of non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ definitions genericity basis theorem, implying the preservation of non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ definitions pigeonhole basis theorem. More precisely, the following theorem was proven by Wang [Reference Wang21]:

Theorem 5.1 (Wang [Reference Wang21]).

If B is a non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ set, then for every set $A \subseteq \omega $ , there is an infinite set $H \subseteq A$ or $H \subseteq \overline {A}$ such that B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ .

Partition genericity is not the right notion to reprove this pigeonhole basis theorem. Indeed, the following proposition shows that there is no preservation of non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ definitions partition genericity basis theorem.

Proposition 5.2. There is a non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ set B and a partition generic set A such that B is $\Sigma ^0_1$ in every infinite subset of A.

Proof Fix any computable linear order $L = (\omega , <_L)$ of order type $\omega +\omega ^{*}$ with no infinite computable ascending or descending sequence (see [Reference Rosenstein18]). Let A be the $\omega $ part of this order. Note that $\overline {A}$ is the $\omega ^{*}$ part of this order. First, note that A is bi-hyperimmune. Indeed, suppose $F_0, F_1, \dots $ is a c.e. array such that for every n, $F_n \cap A \neq \emptyset $ . Then the set $X = \{ \min _{<_L} F_n : n \in \omega \}$ is an infinite c.e. subset of A. By thinning out the set X, one can compute an infinite increasing sequence, contradicting our assumption. Thus A is hyperimmune. By a symmetric argument, A is co-hyperimmune.

By Proposition 2.27, since A is co-hyperimmune, it is partition generic. Let $B = A$ . Since A is hyperimmune, then it is not c.e. Let H be any infinite subset of A. Then $B = \{ x \in \omega : \exists n \in H,\ x <_L n \}$ . Thus B is c.e. in every infinite subset of A.

The remainder of this section is devoted to the design of a notion of genericity which admits a preservation of non-c.e. definitions basis theorem, implying Theorem 5.1.

5.1 Enumeration genericity

From now on, fix a set $B \subseteq \omega $ . All the following definitions hold for any B, but because of Proposition 5.4, the only interesting case is when the set B is non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ . Contrary to hyperimmunity genericity, we need to work with largeness rather than regularity, for some reasons which will become clear when proving Proposition 5.4.

Definition 5.3. A class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large if:

  1. 1. If $(X,n) \in \mathcal {A}$ and $X \subseteq Y$ , then $(Y,n) \in \mathcal {A}$ .

  2. 2. For every finite set $F \subseteq B$ and every k-cover $Y_0, \dots , Y_{k-1}$ of $\omega $ , there is some $j < k$ such that $\forall n \in F\ (Y_j, n) \in \mathcal {A}$ .

The definition of $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -largeness ensures that the class $\{ X : \forall n \in B\ (X,n) \in \mathcal {A} \}$ is partition large. If B is not c.e. but $\mathcal {A}$ is $\Sigma ^0_1$ , then there must be some “overflow,” in the sense that for every k-cover $Y_0, \dots , Y_{k-1}$ of $\omega $ , there must be some $n \in \overline {B}$ and some $j < k$ such that $(Y_j,n) \in \mathcal {A}$ . Such an n however depends on k. Therefore, there does not exist in general an $n \in \overline {B}$ such that the class $\{ X : (X,n) \in \mathcal {A} \}$ is partition large, but one still have the following proposition:

Proposition 5.4. Suppose B is not c.e. For every $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ , the class $\{ X : \forall n \in B\ (X, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (X, n) \in \mathcal {U} \}$ is partition large.

Proof Suppose B is non-c.e. Let $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ be any non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class. For every $k, s$ , let $A_{k,s} = \{ m : \forall Z_0 \cup \dots \cup Z_{k-1} = \omega \ \exists i < k\ (Z_i, m) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \forall n \in B \upharpoonright _s\ (Z_i, n) \in \mathcal {U} \}$ . Since $\mathcal {U}$ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large, for every $k, s$ , the set $A_{k,s}$ is a c.e. superset of B, so since B is not c.e., there is some $n_s \in A_{k,s} \setminus B$ . By the infinite pigeonhole principle, for every $Z_0 \cup \dots \cup Z_{k-1} = \omega $ , there is some $i < k$ such that for infinitely many s, $n_s \in Z_i$ and $\forall n \in B \upharpoonright _s\ (Z_i, n) \in \mathcal {U}$ . It follows that for every $Z_0 \cup \dots \cup Z_{k-1} = \omega $ , there is some $i < k$ such that $\exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z_i,n) \in \mathcal {U}$ and $\forall n \in B\ (Z_i,n) \in \mathcal {U}$ . Thus the class $\{\kern-1.3pt X : \forall n \in B\ (X, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (X, n) \in \mathcal {U} \}$ is partition large.

A class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ is non-trivial if for every $(X,n) \in \mathcal {A}$ , $|X| \geq 2$ .

Definition 5.5. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ be a class. We say that X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ if for every non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ , $X \in \mathcal {L}(\kern-1pt\{ Z : \forall n \in B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \}\kern-1pt)$ . If X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $2^\omega \times \omega $ , we simply say that X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic.

Proposition 5.6. Suppose B is not c.e. and A is partition generic relative to B. Then A is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic.

Proof Fix a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ . Since B is not c.e., by Proposition 5.4, the class $\mathcal {V} = \{ X : \forall n \in B\ (X, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (X, n) \in \mathcal {U} \}$ is partition large. Note that $\mathcal {V}$ is $\Pi ^0_2(B)$ . By Proposition 2.18, $\mathcal {V}$ contains a partition regular subclass, so $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ is partition regular. By Theorem 2.10, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ is $\Pi ^0_2(B)$ , so since A is partition generic relative to B, $A \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ .

Proposition 5.7. Suppose B is not c.e. Then $\omega $ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic.

Proof Immediate from Proposition 5.6, since $\omega $ is partition generic relative to B.

Proposition 5.8. If X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ , then X is infinite.

Proof Let $\mathcal {V} = \{ Z : \forall n \in B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {A} \}$ . Since X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ , $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . Since $\mathcal {A}$ is non-trivial, for every $X \in \mathcal {V}$ , $|X| \geq 2$ . Therefore, by Proposition 2.6, $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ is non-trivial, so since $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ , X is infinite.

Proposition 5.9. If X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ and $Y \supseteq X$ , then Y is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proof Let $\mathcal {U}$ be a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . Since X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ , then, letting $\mathcal {V} = \{ Z : \forall n \in B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \}$ , $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . Since $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ is closed upward, $Y \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . Therefore Y is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proposition 5.10. If X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ and $Y =^{*} X$ , then Y is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proof Let $\mathcal {U} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ be any non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ subclass of $\mathcal {A}$ . Let $\mathcal {V} = \{ Z : Z : \forall n \in B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \}$ . Since X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ , then $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . Since $Y =^{*} X$ , then there is a finite set F such that $Y \cup F \supseteq X$ . By partition regularity of $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ , either $F \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ , or $Y \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . Since $\mathcal {U}$ is non-trivial, then $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ is non-trivial, so $F \not \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . It follows that $Y \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . Therefore Y is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Lemma 5.11. Suppose X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in a class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ . For every $Y_0 \cup Y_1 \supseteq X$ , if $Y_0 \not \in \mathcal {L}(\{ Z : \forall n \in B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {A} \})$ , then $Y_1$ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proof Fix any non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ and let $\mathcal {V} = \{ Z : \forall n \in B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \}$ . Since X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ , then $X \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . Since $Y_0 \cup Y_1 \supseteq X$ , then by partition regularity of $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ , either $Y_0 \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ , or $Y_1 \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . Since $\mathcal {U} {\kern-1pt}\subseteq{\kern-1pt} \mathcal {A}$ , then $\mathcal {V} {\kern-1pt}\subseteq{\kern-1pt} \{ Z : \forall n {\kern-1pt}\in{\kern-1pt} B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z, n) {\kern-1pt}\in{\kern-1pt} \mathcal {A} \}$ , so $\mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V}) \subseteq \mathcal {L}(\{ Z : \forall n \in B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {A} \})$ . If follows from hypothesis that $Y_0 \not \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ , so $Y_1 \in \mathcal {L}(\mathcal {V})$ . Therefore, $Y_1$ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ .

Proposition 5.12. Let $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ be a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class. Suppose X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . Let $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_k \supseteq X$ . Then there is a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ subclass $\mathcal {U} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ together with some $i \leq k$ such that $Y_i$ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {U}$ .

Proof We proceed by induction on k. For $k = 0$ , $Y_0 \supseteq X$ , so by Proposition 5.9, Y is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . Take $\mathcal {U} = \mathcal {A}$ and we are done. Suppose now that the property holds for $k-1$ . Suppose $Y_k$ is not $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {A}$ . Thus there is a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq \mathcal {A}$ such that $Y_k \not \in \mathcal {L}(\{ Z : \forall n \in B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \})$ . By Theorem 5.11, $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_{k-1}$ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {U}$ . By induction hypothesis on $\mathcal {U}$ and $Y_0 \cup \dots \cup Y_{k-1}$ , there is a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ subclass $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ together with some $i < k$ such that $Y_i$ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {V}$ .

5.2 Applications

We now turn to the main application of enumeration genericity, which is a partition genericity subset basis theorem for preservation of non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ definitions.

Theorem 5.13. Suppose A is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ . Then there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ .

Proof Consider the notion of forcing $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ where $(\sigma , X)$ is a Mathias condition, and $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ is an $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class within which X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic. A condition $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {W})$ extends another condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ if $(\tau , Y)$ Mathias extends $(\sigma , X)$ and $\mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ .

Any filter $\mathcal {F}$ induces a subset $G_{\mathcal {F}} = \bigcup _{(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V}) \in \mathcal {F}} \sigma $ of A. The first property we prove is that $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is an infinite set.

Lemma 5.14. Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a sufficiently generic filter. Then $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is infinite.

Proof Let us show that for any n, the set of conditions $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {V})$ such that $\tau (x) = 1$ for some $x> n$ is dense. Let $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ be a condition. Since X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {V}$ , then by Proposition 5.8, X is infinite. Let $x \in X$ be greater than n, let $\tau $ be string $\sigma \cup \{x\}$ , and let $Y = X \setminus \{0, \dots , |\rho |\}$ . By Proposition 5.10, Y is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {V}$ . Therefore, $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {V})$ is a valid extension of $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ .

Lemma 5.15. For every condition $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ , there is an extension $(\tau , Y, \mathcal {W})$ forcing $W_e^G \neq B$ .

Proof We have two cases.

Case 1: the following class is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{A} = \{ (Y,n) \in \mathcal{V} : \exists \rho \subseteq Y\ n \in W_e^{\sigma \cup \rho} \}. \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathcal {A}$ is a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ subclass of $\mathcal {U}$ and X is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {U}$ , then $X \in \mathcal {L}(\{ Z : \forall n \in B\ (Z, n) \in \mathcal {U} \wedge \exists n \in \overline {B}\ (Z,n) \in \mathcal {A} \})$ . Therefore there is some $\rho \subseteq X$ and some $n \in \overline {B}$ such that $n \in W_e^{\sigma \cup \rho }$ . Let $Y = X \setminus \{0, \dots , |\rho |\}$ . By Proposition 5.10, Y is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {V}$ . Therefore $(\sigma \cup \rho , Y, \mathcal {V})$ is an extension of $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ forcing $W_e^G \neq B$ .

Case 2: there is some finite set $F \subseteq B$ and some $k \in \omega $ such that the following class is non-empty:

$$ \begin{align*}\mathcal{C} = \left\{ Z_0 \oplus \dots \oplus Z_{k-1} : \begin{array}{l} Z_0 \cup \dots \cup Z_{k-1} = \omega \wedge\\ \forall i < k\ \exists n \in F\ (Z_i,n) \not \in \mathcal{V} \vee \forall \rho \subseteq Z_i\ n \not \in W_e^{\sigma \cup \rho} \end{array}\right\}. \end{align*} $$

Note that $\mathcal {C}$ is a non-empty $\Pi ^0_1$ class. Pick any element $Z_0 \oplus \dots \oplus Z_{k-1} \in \mathcal {C}$ . By Proposition 5.12, there is a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ subclass $\mathcal {W}$ of $\mathcal {U}$ and some $i < k$ such that $Z_i \cap X$ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic in $\mathcal {W}$ . In particular, $\forall n \in B\ (Z_i \cap X, n) \in \mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ , and by upward-closure of $\mathcal {V}$ , $\forall n \in B\ (Z_i, n) \in \mathcal {V}$ . By choice of $Z_i$ , there is some $n \in F$ such that $(Z_i,n) \not \in \mathcal {V} \vee \forall \rho \subseteq Z_i\ n \not \in W_e^{\sigma \cup \rho }$ . Since $F \subseteq B$ , $(Z_i, n) \in \mathcal {V}$ , so $\forall \rho \subseteq Z_i\ n \not \in W_e^{\sigma \cup \rho }$ . The condition $(\sigma , Z_i \cap X, \mathcal {W})$ is an extension of $(\sigma , X, \mathcal {V})$ forcing $n \not \in W_e^G$ , with $n \in B$ .

We are now ready to prove Theorem 5.13. Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a sufficiently generic filter containing $(\emptyset , A, \mathcal {U})$ . By Lemma 5.14, $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is infinite. By construction, $G_{\mathcal {F}} \subseteq A$ . Last, by Lemma 5.15, B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(G_{\mathcal {F}})$ .

Corollary 5.16. Let B be a non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ set. Let A be partition generic relative to B. Then there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ .

Proof By Proposition 5.6, A is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic. By Theorem 5.13, there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ .

Corollary 5.17. Let B be a non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ set. Let A be Kurtz random relative to B. Then there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ .

Proof By Proposition 2.26, A is partition generic relative to B, so by Corollary 5.16, there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ .

Proof of Theorem 5.1

Let B be a non- $\Sigma ^0_1$ set and let A be a set. By Proposition 5.7, $\omega $ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic. By Proposition 5.12, there is a non-trivial $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {A} \subseteq 2^\omega \times \omega $ within which either A or $\overline {A}$ is $\mathfrak {E}(B)$ -generic. By Theorem 5.13, there is an infinite subset $H \subseteq A$ such that B is not $\Sigma ^0_1(H)$ .

6 Partition genericity and computability

We conclude this study of partition regularity and partition genericity by considering the corresponding notions of lowness, and constructing a partition generic set which is both computably dominated and of non-DNC degree.

Definition 6.1.

  1. 1. A set X is low for partition genericity if every partition generic set is partition X-generic.

  2. 2. A set X is low for partition regularity if for every $\Pi ^0_2(X)$ partition regular class $\mathcal {L}$ , there is a $\Pi ^0_2$ partition regular subclass $\mathcal {M} \subseteq \mathcal {L}$

  3. 3. A set X is low for partition largeness if for every $\Sigma ^0_1(X)$ partition large class $\mathcal {U}$ , there is a $\Sigma ^0_1$ large subclass $\mathcal {V} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ .

It is clear that if X is low for partition regularity or low for partition largeness, then it is low for partition genericity. Actually, all three notions are trivial, in the sense that the only degree which is low for partition genericity is the computable one.

Proposition 6.2. If X is low for partition genericity, then X is computable.

Proof Let X be a non-computable set. Let $A = \{ \sigma \in 2^{<\omega } : \sigma \prec X \}$ . Then $A \equiv _T X$ and every infinite subset of A computes A. Either A is partition generic in a non-trivial partition large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class, or $\overline {A}$ is partition generic in $2^\omega $ . In the first case, by Theorem 3.3, there is an infinite subset of A which does not compute A, contradiction. Therefore $\overline {A}$ is partition generic.

Let us show that $\overline {A}$ is not partition generic relative to X. Since A is infinite, $\mathcal {L}_A$ is a non-trivial $\Pi ^0_2(X)$ partition regular class. However, $\overline {A} \not \in \mathcal {L}_A$ . Therefore, X is not low for partition genericity.

The degrees of partition generic sets are not fully understood. In Section 2.6, we proved that every co-hyperimmune set and every Kurtz random is partition generic. By the computably dominated basis theorem, there are Kurtz randoms of computably dominated degree. Since every weakly 1-generic is Kurtz random, there are Kurtz randoms of non-DNC degree. On the other hand, Stephan and Yu [Reference Stephan and Yu19] proved that the degrees which are low for Kurtz-randomness are precisely the computably dominated non-DNC degrees, which implies that no Kurtz random is of both degrees simultaneously. We now prove the existence of a partition generic set which is low for Kurtz-randomness. This is done using a perfect tree forcing starting from a suitable tree.

Definition 6.3 (Terwijn and Zambella [Reference Terwijn and Zambella20]).

Fix a canonical coding of all finite sets $D_0, D_1, \dots $ . A set X is computably traceable if there is a computable function p such that, for each function $f \leq _T A$ , there is a computable function h satisfying, for all n, $|D_{h(n)}| \leq p(n)$ and $f(n) \in D_{h(n)}$ .

Terwijn and Zambella [Reference Terwijn and Zambella20] proved that the computably traceable degrees are precisely those which are low for Schnorr randomness. It is clear that every computably traceable set is computably dominated. Moreover, by Kjos-Hanssen, Merkle, and Stephan [Reference Kjos-Hanssen, Merkle and Stephan11], every computably traceable set is of non-DNC degree.

Proposition 6.4. There is a partition generic set which is computably traceable and of minimal degree.

Proof A function tree is a function $T : 2^{<\omega } \to 2^{<\omega }$ such that for every $\sigma \in 2^{<\omega }$ , $T(\sigma 0)$ and $T(\sigma 1)$ are incompatible extensions of $T(\sigma )$ . Any such function $T : 2^{<\omega } \to 2^{<\omega }$ induces a function $T : 2^\omega \to 2^\omega $ by defining $T(X) = \bigcup _{\sigma \prec X} T(\sigma )$ . We then write $[T] = \{ f(X) : X \in 2^\omega \}$ . A function tree S extends a function tree T (written $S \leq T$ ) if $[S] \subseteq [T]$ .

Lemma 6.5. There is a computable function tree $T_0$ such that for every $X,Y \in 2^\omega $ with $X \neq Y$ , then $T_0(X) \cup T_0(Y) =^{*} \omega $ .

Proof Let $T_0(\epsilon ) = \epsilon $ . Suppose $T_0$ is defined on $2^{\leq n}$ for some n. Let $\sigma _0, \sigma _1, \dots , \sigma _{2^{n+1}-1}$ be the list of all strings of length $n+1$ . For every $i < 2^{n+1}$ , let $\tau _i$ be the string of length $2^{n+1}$ which has a 0 at position i, and 1 everywhere else. Let $T_0(\sigma _i) = T_0(\sigma _i \upharpoonright _n)^\frown \tau _i$ . For instance, $T_0(0) = 01$ , $T_0(1) = 10$ , $T(00) = 010111$ , $T(01) = 011011$ , $T(10) = 101101$ , and $T(11) = 101110$ . Note that every two strings of same length is sent to strings of same length.

Let $X, Y \in \omega $ be such that $X \neq Y$ , and let $\sigma $ be the longest common substring. We claim that for every $n> |T_0(\sigma )$ , then either $n \in T_0(X)$ , or $n \in T_1(Y)$ . Indeed, let t be the smallest length such that $n < |T_0(X \upharpoonright _t)|$ , or equivalently such that $n < |T_0(Y \upharpoonright _t)|$ . Let i and $j < 2^t$ be such that $X\upharpoonright _t$ and $Y\upharpoonright _t$ are respectively the ith and the jth string of length t. Note that since $n> |T_0(\sigma )|$ , then $X\upharpoonright _t$ and $Y\upharpoonright _t$ are incomparable, hence $i \neq j$ . By definition, $T_0(X \upharpoonright _t) = T_0(X \upharpoonright _{t-1})^\frown \tau _i$ and $T_0(Y \upharpoonright _t) = T_0(Y \upharpoonright _{t-1})^\frown \tau _j$ , where $\tau _i$ and $\tau _j$ do not have a 0 at the same position. By choice of t, $n \geq |T_0(X \upharpoonright _{t-1})| = |T_0(Y \upharpoonright _{t-1})|$ , so either $n \in T_0(X \upharpoonright _t)$ , or $n \in T_0(Y \upharpoonright _t)$ .

Consider the notion of forcing $\mathbb {P}$ whose conditions are computable function trees extending $T_0$ . Any sufficiently generic filter $\mathcal {F}$ induces a set $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ which is the unique member of $\bigcap _{T \in \mathcal {F}} [T]$ . A condition T forces a formula $\varphi (G)$ if the formula holds for every $G \in [T]$ .

Lemma 6.6. For every non-trivial partition large $\Sigma ^0_1$ class $\mathcal {U} \subseteq 2^\omega $ and every condition T there is an extension $S \leq T$ forcing $G \in \mathcal {U}$ .

Proof Pick two $X,Y \in 2^\omega $ with $X \neq Y$ . Since $T \leq T_0$ , then $T(X) \cup T(Y) =^{*} \omega $ . Since $\mathcal {U}$ is a non-trivial partition large class, either $T(X) \in \mathcal {U}$ , or $T(Y) \in \mathcal {U}$ . Assume the first case holds, by symmetry. Since $\mathcal {U}$ is $\Sigma ^0_1$ , there is a finite string $\sigma \prec X$ such that $[T(\sigma )] \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ . Let S be the extension of T defined by $S(\tau ) = T(\sigma \tau )$ . Then for every $G \in [S]$ , $G \in \mathcal {U}$ .

Let $\mathcal {F}$ be a sufficiently generic filter. By Lemma 6.6, $G_{\mathcal {F}}$ is partition generic. It is well known that every sufficiently generic filter for computable Sacks forcing produces sets of minimal degree. Terwijn and Zambella [Reference Terwijn and Zambella20] proved that these sets are also computably traceable.

Acknowledgements

The authors are thankful to the anonymous referee for his remarks and improvement suggestions.

Funding

The authors are partially supported by grant ANR “ACTC” #ANR-19-CE48-0012-01.

References

Dorais, F. G., A variant of Mathias forcing that preserves ACA 0 . Archive for Mathematical Logic , vol. 51 (2012), nos. 7–8, pp. 751780.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downey, R., Hirschfeldt, D. R., Lempp, S., and Solomon, R., A ${\varDelta}_2^0$ set with no infinite low subset in either it or its complement, this Journal, vol. 66 (2001), no. 3, pp. 1371–1381.Google Scholar
Dzhafarov, D. D. and Jockusch, C. G., Ramsey’s theorem and cone avoidance, this Journal, vol. 74 (2009), no. 2, pp. 557–578.Google Scholar
Greenberg, N. and Miller, J. S., Lowness for Kurtz randomness, this Journal, vol. 74 (2009), no. 2, pp. 665–678.Google Scholar
Hindman, N. and Strauss, D., Algebra in the Stone–Čech Compactification , De Gruyter Textbook, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 2012.Google Scholar
Hirschfeldt, D. R., Jockusch, C. G., Kjos-Hanssen, B., Lempp, S., and Slaman, T. A., The strength of some combinatorial principles related to Ramsey’s theorem for pairs , Computational Prospects of Infinity, Part II: Presented Talks , World Scientific, Singapore, 2008, pp. 143161. Available at https://mathscinet.ams.org/mathscinet-getitem?mr=MR2449463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jockusch, C. G. and Soare, R. I. ${\varPi}_1^0$ classes and degrees of theories . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 173 (1972), pp. 3356.Google Scholar
Kjos-Hanssen, B., Infinite subsets of random sets of integers . Mathematics Research Letters , vol. 16 (2009), pp. 103110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kjos-Hanssen, B., A strong law of computationally weak subsets . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 11 (2011), no. 1, pp. 110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kjos-Hanssen, B. and Liu, L., Extracting randomness within a subset is hard . European Journal of Mathematics , vol. 6 (2020), no. 4, pp. 14381451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kjos-Hanssen, B., Merkle, W., and Stephan, F., Kolmogorov complexity and the recursion theorem . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 363 (2011), no. 10, pp. 54655480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liu, L., RT ${}_2^2$ does not imply WKL 0, this Journal, vol. 77 (2012), no. 2, pp. 609–620.Google Scholar
Liu, L., Cone avoiding closed sets . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 367 (2015), no. 3, pp. 16091630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, J. S., Pi-0-1 Classes in Computable Analysis and Topology , Cornell University, 2002. Available at https://mathscinet.ams.org/mathscinet-getitem?mr=2703773.Google Scholar
Monin, B. and Patey, L., The weakness of the pigeonhole principle under hyperarithmetical reductions . Journal of Mathematical Logic , vol. 21 (2021), no. 3, Article no. 2150013, 41 pp.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patey, L., Iterative forcing and hyperimmunity in reverse mathematics , Evolving Computability (Beckmann, A., Mitrana, V., and Soskova, M., editors), Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 9136, Springer, 2015, pp. 291301. Available at https://mathscinet.ams.org/mathscinet-getitem?mr=3382369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patey, L., Iterative forcing and hyperimmunity in reverse mathematics , Computability , vol. 6 (2017), no. 3, pp. 209221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenstein, J. G., Linear Orderings , Pure and Applied Mathematics, vol. 98, Academic Press, New York–London, 1982.Google Scholar
Stephan, F. and Yu, L., Lowness for weakly 1-generic and Kurtz-random , Theory and Applications of Models of Computation , Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol. 3959, Springer, Berlin, 2006, pp. 756764.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Terwijn, S. A and Zambella, D., Algorithmic randomness and lowness, Mathematical Logic and Foundations (ML), 1997. Available at https://eprints.illc.uva.nl/id/eprint/1388/.Google Scholar
Wang, W., The definability strength of combinatorial principles, this Journal, vol. 81 (2016), no. 4, pp. 1531–1554.Google Scholar