Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T12:34:11.096Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Significance of the Past

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 August 2021

GUY KAHANE*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF OXFORDguy.kahane@philosophy.ox.ac.uk

Abstract

The past is deeply important to many of us. But our concern about history can seem puzzling and needs justification. After all, the past cannot be changed: we can help the living needy, but the tears we shed for the long dead victims of past tragedies help no one. Attempts to justify our concern about history typically take one of two opposing forms. It is assumed either that such concern must be justified in instrumental or otherwise self-centered and present-centered terms or that our interest in history must be utterly disinterested and pursued for its own sake. But neither approach can fully explain, or justify, our concern about the past. I propose a third approach, on which the past matters because it contains much that is of value—all those past people and the things they did or had endured—and this value calls for our fitting response. In short: the significance of the past is past significance.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Philosophical Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am very grateful to Saul Smilansky and to several anonymous referees for extremely helpful comments.

References

Bicknell, J., Judkins, J., and, Korsmeyer, C., eds. (2019) Philosophical Perspectives on Ruins, Monuments, and Memorials. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Braw, J. D. (2007) ‘Vision as Revision: Ranke and the Beginning of Modern History’. History and Theory, 46, 4560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgett, B., and Hendler, G.. (2020) Keywords for American Cultural Studies. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Bykvist, K. (2009) ‘No Good Fit: Why the Fitting Attitude Analysis of Value Fails’. Mind, 118, 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, E. H. (1961) What Is History? London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Collingwood, R. G. (1956) The Idea of History. New York: Galaxy.Google Scholar
Danto, A. (1965) Analytic Philosophy of History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Danto, A. (2003) ‘Prudence, History, Time, and Truth’. In D. Carr, T. R. Flynn, and R. A. Makkreel (eds.), The Ethics of History (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press), 7688.Google Scholar
Dray, W. (1968) ‘Michael Oakeshott's Theory of History’. In P. King and B. C. Parekh (eds.), Politics and Experience (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 19–42.Google Scholar
Elton, G. (1967) The Practice of History. London: Fontana.Google Scholar
Gibbon, E. (1846) The Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire, Vol. I. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Greene, P., and Sullivan, M.. (2015) ‘Against Time Bias’. Ethics, 125, 947–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herodotus, . (1909) The History of Herodotus. New York: The Tandy Thomas Company.Google Scholar
Hurka, T. (2000) Virtue, Vice and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurka, T. (2011) Drawing Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, S. P. (2013) ‘Why Old Things Matter’. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 12, 313–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jenkins, K. (1995) On ‘What Is History?’: From Carr and Elton to Rorty and White. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kahane, G. (2019) ‘History and Persons’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 99, 162–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsmeyer, C. (2016) ‘Real Old Things’. British Journal of Aesthetics, 56, 219–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsmeyer, C (2018) Things: In Touch with the Past. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, R. (2011) ‘Review of Hurka, The Best Things in Life’. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/the-best-things-in-life-a-guide-to-what-really-matters/Google Scholar
Macaulay, T. B. (1828) ‘History’. Edinburgh Review. Reprinted in Macaulay, The Miscellaneous Writings and Speeches of Lord Macaulay (London: Longmans Green), 133–59.Google Scholar
Margalit, A. (2002) The Ethics of Memory. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthes, E. H. (2013) ‘History, Value, and Irreplaceability’. Ethics, 124, 3564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthes, E. H. (2015) ‘Impersonal Value, Universal Value, and the Scope of Cultural Heritage’. Ethics, 125, 9991027.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Molesworth, W. (1839) The English Works of Thomas Hobbes. Vol. 8. London: John Bohn.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich. (1874/1997) ‘On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life’. In Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 57124.Google Scholar
Oakeshott, M. (1933) Experience and Its Modes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakeshott, M. (1962) ‘The Activity of Being and Historian’. In Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays (London: Basic Books).Google Scholar
Orsi, F. (2013) ‘Fitting Attitudes and Solitary Goods’. Mind, 122, 687–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. (1981) Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Raz, J. (2001) Value, Respect and Attachment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rieff, D. (2016) In Praise of Forgetting. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. (1998) What We Owe To Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. (2010) ‘The Normativity of Tradition’. In Scheffler, Equality and Tradition (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 287311.Google Scholar
Scheffler, S. (2011) ‘Valuing’. In R. J. Wallace, R. Kumar, and S. Freeman (eds.), Reasons and Recognition (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 2342.Google Scholar
Schopenhauer, A. (2007) Studies in Pessimism. New York: Cosimo Classics.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2013) ‘Morally, Should We Prefer Never to Have Existed?Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 655–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, S. (2021) ‘The Idea of Moral Duties to History’. Philosophy, 96, 155–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stearns, P. N. (1998) ‘Why study history?’. American Historical Association, www.historians.org.Google Scholar
Tacitus, . (1942) The Complete Works of Tacitus. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Thucydides, . (1950) History of the Peloponnesian War. New York: E. P. Dutton and Company.Google Scholar
Waldron, J. (1992) ‘Superseding Historical Injustice’. Ethics, 103, 428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, H. (1966) ‘The Burden of History’. History and Theory, 5, 111–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, H. (2010) ‘The Practical Past’. Historein, 10, 1019.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, J. O. (2013) ‘The Values of the Past’. In G. Scarre and R. Coningham (eds.), Appropriating the Past. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2541.Google Scholar
Zemon Davis, N. (1984) The Return of Martin Guerre. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar