Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2brh9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T18:24:12.366Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why are proofs difficult?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 August 2016

Tony Barnard*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, King's College, London WC2R 2LS

Extract

For several years, the notion of ‘mathematical proof’ has been at the centre of much discussion, writing and educational research. To a very large extent the discussions have focused on the nature of the acceptability of the reasons for a mathematical conclusion. Admittedly there have been contributions concerning the role of proof in mathematics and also the mechanics of pupils‘ proof behaviour, including works which discuss both affective and pedagogical aspects, but the dominant context has usually been one of validation. That is to say, discussions have largely been in the domain of what ‘counts as a proof’ and for whom. However, I claim that there is another dimension to proof that is of central importance in the intellectual development of students at school and university. This relates to the phenomenon in mathematical thinking in which a section of mathematical structure is mentally compressed into a single unit, small enough to fit into the conscious focus of attention at a given time, and possessing an interiority which is able to both guide manipulation of the unit and also be subsequently expanded without loss of detail. This article discusses the role of this phenomenon in the manipulation of mathematical statements involved in proof. An analysis in these terms of the dynamics of certain types of mathematical proof suggests both an explanation for students’ difficulties and a possible means of help in some cases.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Mathematical Association 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Barnard, T. and Tall, D. O. Cognitive units, connections and mathematical proof, Proceedings of the 21st International Conference for the Psychology of Mathematics Education, Vol. 2 (1997) pp. 4148.Google Scholar
2. Barnard, T. Compressed units of mathematical thought, Journal of Mathematical Behavior, 17(4) (1999) pp. 401404.Google Scholar
3. Krutetskii, V. A. (trans. Teller, J. ed. Kilpatrick, J. and Wirzup, I.), The Psychology of Mathematical Abilities in Schoolchildren University of Chicago (1976).Google Scholar
4. Davis, R. B. Learning Mathematics: The Cognitive Science Approach to Mathematics Education Ablex, Norwood, NJ (1984).Google Scholar
5. Dubinsky, E. Reflective abstraction in advanced mathematical thinking. In Tall, D. O. (Ed.), Advanced Mathematical Thinking, Kluwer, Dordrecht (1991) pp. 95123.Google Scholar
6. Sfard, A. On the dual nature of mathematical conceptions: reflections on processes and objects as different sides of the same coin, Educational Studies in Mathematics, 22(1) (1991) pp. 136.Google Scholar
7. Gray, E. M. and Tall, D. O. Duality, ambiguity and flexibility: a proceptual view of simple arithmetic, Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 26(2) (1994) pp. 115141.Google Scholar