Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T05:40:41.688Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

IN NOSTRIS EXTREMIS (TERROR AND FANATICISM IN THE WESTERN MIND)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 October 2014

JULIAN BOURG*
Affiliation:
Department of History, Boston College E-mail: bourgj@bc.edu

Extract

The abolitionist John Brown. Freedom fighter? Terrorist? The choice is unsatisfying for any number of reasons, least of all for the anachronistic nomenclature and the moral obviousness of his cause. Of course Brown was right, we can easily say, to take up the fight against that “peculiar institution” of barbarous slavery. Insofar as the federal government stood in the way of historical progress, perhaps he also was justified in striking the arsenal at Harper's Ferry in 1859 as the first salvo of the American Civil War, demonstrating by his pitiful action that the Union would have to choose sides and fight. Yet no less clear today is the sheer difficulty of justifying such antistate violence. Since the 1970s and especially since September 11, 2001, with comparable moral obviousness, insurgent and terroristic violence have generally been condemned as threats to social stability and political coherence. The very liberal-democratic traditions that might otherwise superficially heroize someone like John Brown recoil at the disorder he personified. The truth of Brown's adventurism is clearly more complicated than the postcard version, and his crazed biblical prophetism, nasty 1856 murder spree in Kansas, and patronizing wish to play Moses to southern blacks must be read alongside successful efforts by the government and pro-slavery camp to brand him an incorrigible fanatic—a label that Brown himself and other abolitionists embraced as their own. What Brown represents, however, is an access point to the deep history of ideas about fanaticism and terrorism in the modern West, a history filled with paradoxes and ambiguities that nonetheless revolve around the basic fact—avoided with ease by contemporary pundits and prognosticators—that for the past several centuries we have met the enemy, and he is us.

Type
Review Essays
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Fellman, Michael, In the Name of God and Country: Reconsidering Terrorism in American History (New Haven, 2010), 1456Google Scholar.

2 Robin, Corey, Fear: The History of a Political Idea (Oxford, 2004)Google Scholar.

3 Edelstein, Daniel, The Terror of Natural Right: Republicanism, the Cult of Nature, and the French Revolution (Chicago, 2010)Google Scholar.

4 Jensen, Richard Bach, The Battle against Anarchist Terrorism: An International History, 1878–1934 (Cambridge, 2014)Google Scholar.

5 Negri, Cf. Antonio, “Kairòs, Alma Venus, Multitudo,” in Negri, Time for Revolution (New York, 2003)Google Scholar, 139–261, 147–80. Badiou, Alain, Saint Paul: The Foundation of Universalism (Stanford, 2003)Google Scholar.

6 La Vopa, Anthony J., “The Philosopher and the Schwärmer: On the Career of a German Epithet from Luther to Kant,” Huntington Library Quarterly, 60, 1–2 (1997), 85115CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Orsini, Alessandro, Anatomy of the Red Brigades: The Religious Mind-Set of Modern Terrorists (Ithaca, 2011)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Arendt, Hannah, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York, 1973), 344Google Scholar. On state terror's anti-terrorism see Report of Court Proceedings: The Case of the Trotskyite–Zinovievite Terrorist Centre: Heard before the Military Collegium of the Supreme Court of the U.S.S.R., Moscow, August 19–24, 1936 (Moscow, 1936).

9 Derrida, Jacques, “The Ends of Man,” in Derrida, Margins of Philosophy (Chicago, 1985), 109–36, 134, original emphasisGoogle Scholar.