Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-cx56b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-04T14:23:47.825Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

After Theory by Terry Eagleton, Allen Lane, imprint of Penguin Books, London, 2003, Pp. ix + 225, £18.99 hbk.

Review products

After Theory by Terry Eagleton, Allen Lane, imprint of Penguin Books, London, 2003, Pp. ix + 225, £18.99 hbk.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Book Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © The Dominican Council/Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004

For Terry Eagleton, the golden age of cultural theory is over, because not much has been written that matches the ambitiousness and originality of the innovative theoretical currents of the 1960s and 1970s.

His new book is fundamentally about what kind of fresh thinking our new era demands after the golden age of cultural theory. ‘Theory’ for Eagleton is the most general form of critical self-reflection. Reflecting critically on our situation is a feature of the particular way we belong to the world, and without it humanity would not have survived as a species. As linguistic animals we have the ability to ask ourselves the moral question such as whether our beliefs are sound or whether their reasons are good ones. Eagleton notes that recent theory on the whole fails to deliver: ‘It has been shamefaced about morality and metaphysics, embarrassed about love, biology, religion and revolution, largely silent about evil, reticent about death and suffering, dogmatic about essences, universals and foundations, and superficial about truth, objectivity and disinterestedness’(pp.101–102). After Theory seeks to remedy those deficiencies.

Eagleton advocates a form of essentialism inspired by the thought of Aristotle and Marx. The essence of human beings is to realize their nature as an end in itself. ‘Nature’ is here understood as the way we are most likely to flourish, which brings happiness. The justification he offers for this argument is that it is ‘natural’. ‘Nature is a bottom-line concept; you cannot ask why a giraffe should do the things it does. To say ‘It belongs to nature’ is answer enough. You cannot cut deeper than that. In the same way, you cannot ask why people should want to feel happy and fulfilled. It would be like asking what someone hoped to achieve by falling in love. Happiness is not a means to an end’(p.116). The virtuous life is a particular way of living which allows us to be at our best for the kind of creatures we are. Virtue is thus implicit in our own nature, as opposed to transcendent in origins. Happiness is not the reward for virtue, being virtuous is to be happy.

For Eagleton virtue is a reciprocal affair, it is a function of social relationships. ‘We live well when we fulfill our nature as an enjoyable end in itself. And since our nature is something we share with other creatures of our kind, morality is an inherently political matter’(p.124) This is why he refuses to separate ethics and politics. For Eagleton, we have to try to organise political institutions so that self-realisation can become reciprocal. You realize your nature in a way which allows other to do so too. For Eagleton, socialism makes that fulfilling life of a kind proper to human beings possible. To quote the Communist Manifesto, it is ‘an association in which the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all’.

One of the most original ideas in the book is how Eagleton argues that ethics and politics are ultimately rooted in corporality, our shared material nature. It is true that as labouring, linguistic and sexual animals our bodies are materially geared to culture because meaning, symbolism and interpretation and the like are essential to what we are. Culture is what is natural to us, but we are above all bodily creatures. This is why Eagleton argues that ‘it is the mortal, fragile, suffering, ecstatic, needy, dependent, desirous, compassionate body which furnishes the basis of all moral thought’(p.155). He roots universality in the body and shared material practices. The material body is what we share most significantly with the rest of our species, extended both in space and time. ‘Our material bodies are such that they are, indeed must be, in principle capable of feeling compassion for any others of their kind’(p.156). This is based on our material dependency on each other. We need to work together to survive economically, and sexuality is necessary for the species to be reproduced. Human beings share a ‘species being’ in common, which makes solidarity (and simultaneously conflict) possible. ‘It is a material fact that we are dependent on others for our physical survival, given the helpless state in which we are born. Yet this material dependency cannot really be divorced from such moral capacities as care, selflessness, vigilance and protectiveness, since what we are dependent on is exactly such capacities in those who look after us’(p.169).

For Eagleton human existence is essentially contingent, rough-textured and open-ended, and a certain fundamentalist ideology has sought to fill it with dogma, first principles, fixed meanings and self-evident truth: ‘It is the fear of the unscripted, improvised or indeterminate, as well as a horror of excess and ambiguity’(p.203). This fundamentalism fears the ‘non-being’ which haunts human existence. Examples of ‘non-being’ are death and desire; they show us the ultimate unmasterability of our lives. For Eagleton what is necessary is to oppose a bad sense of non-being with a good one –’non being as an awareness of human frailty and unfoundedness’(p.221). ‘It represents the non-being of those who have been shut out of the current system, who have no real stake in it, and who thus serve as an empty signifier of an alternative future’(p.220). It is not surprising that as a left-wing Catholic, there is room in Eagleton's thought for religion, albeit as a form of spirituality without fetishes or idolatry.

After Theory is overall an excellent book. The author is able to present highly complex and controversial ideas in a very accessible format. Eagleton is definitely not one of those ‘Meaning of the Universe Merchants’. This is a genuine work of popular philosophy.