Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jkksz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-21T19:50:28.540Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justification, Discovery and the Naturalizing of Epistemology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Harvey Siegel*
Affiliation:
University of Nebraska-Lincoln

Abstract

Reichenbach's well-known distinction between the context of discovery and the context of justification has recently come under attack from several quarters. In this paper I attempt to reconsider the distinction and evaluate various recent criticisms of it. These criticisms fall into two main groups: those which directly challenge Reichenbach's distinction; and those which (I argue) indirectly but no less seriously challenge that distinction by rejecting the related distinction between psychology and epistemology, and defending the “naturalizing” of epistemology. I argue that these recent criticisms fail, and that the distinction remains an important conceptual tool necessary for an adequate understanding of the way in which scientific claims purport to appropriately portray our natural environment.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1980

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I should like to thank Max Black, Lyle Eddy, Sing-nan Fen, Robert Halstead, Sophie Haroutunian, Ralph Page, Hugh Petrie, Israel Scheffler, the members of the Philosophy Department of the University of Nebraska-Lincoln, especially Hardy Jones, and the referees of Philosophy of Science, for helpful comments on and criticisms of earlier drafts of this paper.

References

Achinstein, P. (1974), “History and Philosophy of Science: A Reply to Cohen.” In Suppe, F. (ed.), The Structure of Scientific Theories. Urbana, II.: University of Illinois Press: pp. 350360.Google Scholar
Amsterdamski, S. (1975), Between Experience and Metaphysics. Synthese Library, Volume 77. D. Reidel: Boston.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, D. (1977), “Comment on ‘The Natural Selection Model of Conceptual Evolution’,” Philosophy of Science 44: 502507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feigl, H. (1965), “Philosophy of Science,” in R. M. Chisholm et al. (eds.), Philosophy, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. (1972), Problems and Projects. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Haack, S. (1975), “The Relevance of Psychology to Epistemology,” Metaphilosophy 6: 161176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1966), Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs, N.J: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Kordig, C. R. (1978), “Discovery and Justification,” Philosophy of Science 45: 110117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. University of Chicago Press: Chicago, Il. (2nd ed. enlarged).Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1977a), The Essential Tension. University of Chicago Press: Chicago, Il.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1977b), “Objectivity, Value-Judgment, and Theory Choice.” In Kuhn (1977a), pp. 320339.Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I. (1946), An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation. Open Court. Reprinted in Landesman, C., (ed.), The Foundations of Knowledge, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall (1970), pp. 1719.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1956), The Logic of Scientific Discovery. N.Y.: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Prendergast, C. (1977), “Review of Stefan Amsterdamski, Between Experience and Metaphysics,Philosophy of the Social Sciences 7: 410412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), Mathematics, Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1960), Word and Object. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1969a), Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1969b), “Epistemology Naturalized,” in Quine (1969a), pp. 6990.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1938), Experience and Prediction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. C. (1966), The Foundations of Scientific Inference. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Scheffler, I. (1967), Science and Subjectivity. New York: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Siegel, H. (1976), “Meiland on Scheffler, Kuhn, and Objectivity in Science,” Philosophy of Science 43: 441448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Siegel, H. (1978), “Piaget's Conception of Epistemology.Educational Theory 28: 1622.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suppe, F. (ed.) (1974a), The Structure of Scientific Theories. Urbana Il.: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (1974b), “The Search for Philosophic Understanding of Scientific Theories,” in Suppe (1974a), pp. 3241.Google Scholar
Toulmin, S. (1977), “Epistemology and Developmental Psychology,” Nous XI: 5153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar