Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-wtssw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-14T17:01:28.294Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Conserved Quantity Theory of Causation and Closed Systems

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Advocates of the conserved quantity (CQ) theory of causation have their own peculiar problem with conservation laws. Since they analyze causal process and interaction in terms of conserved quantities that are in turn defined as physical quantities governed by conservation laws, they must formulate conservation laws in a way that does not invoke causation, or else circularity threatens. In this paper I will propose an adequate formulation of a conservation law that serves CQ theorists’ purpose.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

My thanks to Jaeyoung Ghim and Inrae Cho for their help with earlier versions of this article. I owe especial debts to Inkyo Chung and two anonymous referees for their detailed and insightful comments. This work was supported by Korea Research Foundation Grant (KRF-2002-041-A00094).

References

Arya, Atam P. (1990), Introduction to Classical Mechanics. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.Google Scholar
Bigelow John, Brian Ellis, and Pargetter, Richard (1988), “Forces”, Forces 55:614630.Google Scholar
Choi, Sungho (2002), “Causation and Gerrymandered World Lines”, Causation and Gerrymandered World Lines 69:105117.Google Scholar
Desloge, Edward, and Karch, Robert (1977), “Noether’s Theorem in Classical Mechanics”, Noether’s Theorem in Classical Mechanics 45:336339.Google Scholar
Dowe, Phil (1995), “What’s Right and What’s Wrong with Transference Theories”, What’s Right and What’s Wrong with Transference Theories 42:363374.Google Scholar
Dowe, Phil (2000), Physical Causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doughty, Noel (1988), Lagrangian Interaction: An Introduction to the Relativistic Symmetry in Electrodynamics and Gravitation. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Ehring, Douglas (1986), “The Transference Theory of Causation”, The Transference Theory of Causation 67:249258.Google Scholar
Fair, David (1979), “Causation and the Flow of Energy”, Causation and the Flow of Energy 14:219250.Google Scholar
Feynman Richard, Robert Leighton, and Sands, Matthew (1989), The Feynman Lectures on Physics, Vol. 1. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Goldstein, Herbert (1980), Classical Mechanics. Reading, MA: Addison-Wisely.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher R. (1995), “Discussion: Salmon on Explanatory Relevance”, Discussion: Salmon on Explanatory Relevance 62:304320.Google Scholar
Kittel Charles, Water Knight, and Ruderman, Malvin (1973), Berkeley Physics Course Vol. 1: Mechanics, 2d ed. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Marion, Jerry B. (1970), Classical Dynamics of Particles and Systems, 2d ed. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
McDaniel, Kristopher (2002), Review of Physical Causation, by Phil Dowe, Erkenntnis 56:258263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nilo, Bobillo-Ares (1988), “Noether’s Theorem in Discrete Classical Mechanics”, American Journal of Physics 56:174177.Google Scholar
Purcell, Edward (1985), Berkeley Physics Course Vol. 2: Electricity and Magnetism, 2d ed. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan (2001), Review of Physical Causation, by Phil Dowe, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52:809813.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, Wesley (1997), “Causality and Explanation: A Reply to Two Critiques”, Causality and Explanation: A Reply to Two Critiques 64:461477.Google Scholar
Symon, Keith (1985), Mechanics, 3d ed. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar