Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-21T15:34:07.541Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Evidential Variety and Mixed-Methods Research in Social Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 February 2023

Jaakko Kuorikoski*
Affiliation:
Practical Philosophy, Faculty of Social Science, University of Helsinki, Helsinki, Finland
Caterina Marchionni
Affiliation:
Practical Philosophy, Faculty of Social Science, University of Helsinki, Helsinki, Finland
*
Corresponding author: Jaakko Kuorikoski; Email: jaakko.kuorikoski@helsinki.fi
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Mixed-methods research (MMR)—the combination of qualitative and quantitative data within the same design to strengthen causal inference—is gaining prominence in the social sciences but its benefits are contested. There remains confusion over which methods to mix and what is the point of mixing them. We argue that variety of evidence is what matters, not of data or methods, and that distinct epistemic principles underlie its added value for causal inference. The centrality of evidential variety also implies that strong causal pluralism is untenable as a foundation for MMR.

Type
Contributed Paper
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association

1. Introduction

Mixed-methods research (MMR) is increasingly popular as a methodology in social science. It combines different methods of data production and analysis within a single research design, most often with the purpose of increasing the reliability of causal inference. Its purported novelty is that the methods represent different methodological traditions, usually qualitative and quantitative social research, and that the mixing should happen in a coordinated, integrative fashion within a single research design. MMR designs aim to direct the selection of methods and the units of study as well as the formulation of research questions and hypotheses in such a way that the different methods produce mutually supporting evidence. The attractiveness of MMR, the justification for trying to do many things at once instead of one thing well, is thus based on some version of the variety-of-evidence thesis, according to which the epistemic whole is more than the sum of its evidential parts, provided the parts are varied in some relevant way.

Several MMR designs have been proposed. For example, set theoretic multimethod research combines case studies with small-n comparative studies subjected to qualitative causal analysis (Rohlfing and Schneider Reference Rohlfing and Schneider2018). Take, for example, the causal relation between elites holding liberal ideas and democratic peace (a candidate explanation for the democratic peace phenomenon): process tracing involves identifying the mechanism through which liberal ideas causally contribute to democratic peace and then applying qualitative comparative analysis to generalize to other cases. Nested analysis, instead, combines observational quantitative studies (regression analysis) with case studies carried out within the sample used in the quantitative study, hence the word “nested” (Lieberman Reference Lieberman2005). For example, Coppedge (Reference Coppedge2005, discussed in Lieberman Reference Lieberman2005) first applied general models (statistical causal hypotheses) to account for the deterioration of democracy in Venezuela, identified what remained to be explained, and then “intensively” studied the case of Venezuela to conclude that patriarchy was an overlooked and yet important explanatory factor. Humphreys and Jacobs (Reference Humphreys and Jacobs2015) proposed a unifying Bayesian framework intended to apply to different combinations of statistical and case-study methods.

In spite of its popularity, however, there remains considerable skepticism concerning whether MMR is superior to single-method research. Here is how one commentator summarizes the concern:

[w]hile multimethod research is evidently experiencing a surge of popularity, there are reasons to worry about whether multimethod applications are in fact producing more grounded, justified, and persuasive inferences than studies using a single method. (Seawright Reference Seawright2016, 4)

The confusion is due in part to a lack of consensus about the epistemological rationale of MMR, and in part to differences across MMR designs in terms of which methods are combined, and what the purpose of combining them is.

The aim in this article is to clarify the epistemic rationale of MMR for causal inference in the social sciences. Our main claim is that MMR should be designed and evaluated from the perspective of what hypotheses the evidence produced by different methods is evidence for and of how these hypotheses are inferentially interlinked, not in terms of whether the methods or data are diverse as such. This is so because it is the body of evidence and its features that give reason to believe in the hypothesis of interest. We therefore proceed as follows. In section 2 we explain why a variety of methods does not suffice to produce a variety of evidence and, consequently, why MMR affords epistemic benefits only if, and when, evidence is varied in some relevant way. Drawing on the philosophical literature on the variety-of-evidence thesis, we argue in section 3 that it is possible to understand MMR according to three distinct principles of evidential variety. Section 4 addresses some undesirable consequences of the pluralist claim that different methods in MMR embody different conceptions of causality. Section 5 concludes the article.

2. From methods to evidence

It is often assumed that MMR is about combining data obtained and analyzed by different means (typically qualitative and quantitative) for the purpose of better supporting a causal hypothesis compared to data obtained from a single method. This idea is behind what we call simple methodological pluralism, according to which different methods produce different kinds of data that, when combined in the right way, provide better support for causal inferences. The problem with simple methodological pluralism is that it remains unclear why combining data produced by different methods should in itself improve causal inference, over and above there being more data in support of the hypothesis (with the obvious proviso that the data agree).

Let us think of a method as the causal process whereby the data are generated, together with the inferential practices applied to them, and then further distinguish data from evidence. Data comprise the causally produced, concrete, and public artifacts that carry information from the phenomenon of interest (Bogen and Woodward, Reference Bogen and Woodward1988; Leonelli Reference Leonelli2015). As such they are always of, or from, something, their identity and type determined by the process through which they were created. Evidence, in turn, is a claim or a fact (or some other propositionally structured entity) about the data, usually grounded on a systematic pattern of some sort, which speaks in favor of, or provides a reason to believe in, some specific claim (e.g., Achinstein Reference Achinstein2001; Cartwright Reference Cartwright2013). As such, evidence is always for something: Its identity as evidence is relational to a claim or a hypothesis.

The distinction between data and evidence is not mere philosophical sophistry. The epistemic benefits conferred by variety reflect the relevant differences in the evidence, not in the data or their production as such. The point of bringing together diverse evidence is to substantiate the reasons for believing a hypothesis (in this case a causal claim or a claim about a mechanism). Data in themselves do not speak in favor of a claim, nor do they count as reasons to believe; they do so only when some of their features are interpreted as evidence for a specific claim. As material artifacts, data simply exist, whereas evidence lives in the space of reason. As Leonelli’s (Reference Leonelli2015, 2019) work convincingly shows, data can also be reused and cited as evidence for claims other than the one for which they were originally produced. The distinction between data as material artifacts and evidence as a reason to believe means that it is a category mistake to equate kinds of methods with kinds of evidence, and methodological variety with evidential variety. We should point out that this is not to claim that the methods whereby data are produced are irrelevant to evidential relevance: For example, as we show later on, features of the causal processes whereby the data are produced are relevant to achieving the variety of evidence required for triangulation (Kuorikoski and Marchionni Reference Kuorikoski and Marchionni2016).

We should also point out that if different methods always produce relevantly different evidence, then the epistemic justification of MMR could be straightforwardly explicated in terms of exploiting their complementary strengths and weaknesses, therefore simple methodological pluralism would suffice as a foundation for MMR. For example, it is a widespread belief among social scientists that knowledge of mechanisms can only be generated by case-based methods. This argument is also well rehearsed in the MMR literature, in which it is presupposed that case-based methods and statistical analyses produce essentially different kinds of evidence. For example, most MMR frameworks simply assume that whereas quantitative data yield evidence for population-level claims about average causal effects, qualitative data provide evidence of the process that connects the cause to the effect in each particular case (e.g., Lieberman Reference Lieberman2005). Derek Beach, an influential methodologist in the field of political science, insists (e.g., 2020) that both statistical studies, including randomized controlled trials (RCTs) and cross-country comparisons, and case studies produce different kinds of evidence: difference-making evidence and mechanistic evidence, respectively. Footnote 1

However, differences in methods and evidence do not always go hand in hand. Evidence about mechanisms may be obtained in different ways, including RCTs and statistical analyses (Illari Reference Illari2011; Marchionni and Reijula Reference Marchionni and Reijula2019). Conversely, the same method may generate different kinds of evidence. For example, as discussed in the fields of development economics and criminology, RCTs may generate evidence for the efficacy of an intervention as well as evidence about the mediating mechanism (so-called policy and mechanism experiments, respectively; see Ludwig et al. Reference Ludwig, Kling and Mullainathan2011). Methodological diversity does not guarantee the kind of difference in evidence that is necessary for exploiting the epistemic benefits of evidential variety.

3. Varieties of evidential variety

If simple methodological pluralism is not a sufficient epistemic foundation for MMR, then what is? MMR rationale is sometimes articulated in terms of methodological triangulation (Johnson et al. Reference Johnson, Onwuegbuzie and Turner2007): the idea that bringing different methods each with its own characteristic weaknesses and strengths to bear on the same causal claim helps to remedy those weaknesses (see also Crasnow Reference Crasnow2010). This idea has been questioned, however (Seawright Reference Seawright2016, 4–10), and other MMR researchers seem to hold different conceptions of the purpose of mixing methods (see Johnson et al. 2007).

As Ahmed and Sil (Reference Ahmed and Sil2012) point out, motivating MMR in terms of triangulation is problematic because in many cases such as nested analysis the different methods clearly address different questions. Rather than a matter of triangulation, Plano Clark and Ivankova (Reference Plano Clark, Ivankova, Clark and Ivanova2016) describe MMR as “the process of integrating quantitative and qualitative research to more completely address a study’s purpose or research questions” (emphasis added). Accordingly, the pieces of evidence integrated into MMR address different questions, not the same question as in the case of triangulation. Shan and Williamson (Reference Shan and Williamson2021) argue that evidential pluralism, which they understand as the claim that causal inference typically requires evidence of both difference making and mechanisms, provides a suitable epistemic foundation for MMR.

As we have already argued elsewhere, there are multiple distinct sources of this value, and distinct epistemic rationales for combining evidence, namely triangulation, security, and integration (Figure 1) (Kuorikoski and Marchionni Reference Kuorikoski and Marchionni2022).

Figure 1. A schematic representation of kinds of evidential variety. P is a proposition about a phenomenon, En is evidence, and M is a mechanism; arrows represent causal relations whereas lines represent evidential relations.

These forms of reasoning are sometimes presented as mutually exclusive alternative rationalizations for the variety-of-evidence thesis, but this need not be case. Because the epistemic rationales for these different forms of the value of variety appear to make sense in their own right, we propose that, depending on what is the inferential problem at hand and/or what characteristics a certain piece of evidence has in relation to a given causal claim, there are simply different ways in which evidence can be combined and different nonaggregative benefits that can accrue. Furthermore, different self-described MMR procedures appear to realize different principles. Hence, dividing the value of variety in this way has analytic value (Kuorikoski and Marchionni Reference Kuorikoski and Marchionni2022).

Triangulation refers to the use of multiple independent lines of evidence for a single claim about a phenomenon such as the existence of a causal relation (e.g., Heesen et al. Reference Heesen, Bright and Zucker2019; Kuorikoski and Marchionni Reference Kuorikoski and Marchionni2016; Schupbach Reference Schupbach2018). Accordingly, the added value of evidential variety derives from the fact that concordance between multiple independent lines of evidence indicates that the common result is unlikely to be an artifact of errors and biases characteristic of any of the individual methods.

Successful triangulation therefore requires that the different pieces of evidence are evidence for the same causal claim, and that they are suitably independent. Philosophers of science have debated how this independence should be understood (e.g., Fitelson Reference Fitelson2001; Stegenga Reference Stegenga2009; Claveau, Reference Claveau2013),Footnote 2 but two things are clear. First, the diversity of methods by which data are produced is not, in itself, sufficient for obtaining evidence that is independent in the right way. Second, the independence condition may be hard to meet in practice and other epistemic considerations, such as the reliability or informativeness of individual sources of evidence, may outweigh the value of its variety (Claveau and Grenier Reference Claveau and Grenier2019). This matters, because at least some of the skepticism related to MMR arises from its being regarded as realizing triangulation. For example, multimethod large-N qualitative analysis is popular in political science and international relations, its aim being to combine statistical analysis with case studies to provide independent evidence for population-level claims about average causal effects. As Rosa Runhardt (Reference Runhardt2022) argues, however, the statistical evidence does not add anything to the evidence about mechanisms obtained from case studies. If this is the case, then it is clearly not a suitable design for realizing triangulation.

Security constitutes another source of value related to evidential variety. Here, one piece of evidence remedies the deficiencies of another piece of evidence relative to a given causal claim (Staley Reference Staley2004; Zahle Reference Zahle2019). The main difference with the case of triangulation is that the different pieces of evidence are not direct evidence supporting the same claim. Variety brings security when there is a causal claim, first-order evidence in its support, and then second-order evidence in favor of the first-order evidence being reliable and relevant for the causal claim in question. To clarify the difference between triangulation and security, we suggest thinking of triangulation as the support afforded by two independent eyewitnesses each testifying to having seen the suspect at the crime scene. Independence here could mean that the eyewitnesses did not know each another and were in different spatial locations with respect to the suspect, for example. According to this analogy, security is involved when the testimony of an expert placing the eyewitness in a position to see the suspect clearly enough counts as second-order evidence in support of the reliability of the eyewitness as first-order evidence (for the claim about the culprit). As in triangulation, second-order evidence can only strengthen the inference if it is not subject to the same errors and biases as the first-order evidence.

Zahle (Reference Zahle2019) suggests that the combination of observational evidence and interview evidence within a case study sometimes follows the logic of security: Under proper conditions, evidence obtained through participant observation provides second-order evidence that interview evidence is reliable first-order evidence for the phenomenon. Evidence obtained through interviews, for example, may confirm that the researchers’ observations are in fact relevant evidence. Extending this idea to MMR is relatively straightforward, even though skeptics might claim that the challenge of incommensurability that besets it does not arise in this case. For example, in arguing for the use of MMR in impact evaluations of development projects (a kind of causal inference), Michael Woolcock (Reference Woolcock2019) lists multiple uses for qualitative methods, most of which are about producing evidence that the primary quantitative (experimental or quasi-experimental) evidence is indeed reliable.

The third source of added value arises when evidence for distinct claims about the same phenomenon together produces a fuller picture of it such that the epistemic whole is better supported by the totality of evidence than the sum of the individual hypotheses (Lloyd Reference Lloyd2009; Cartwright Reference Cartwright2021). Integration differs from triangulation and security because the evidence need not be independent, nor does it need to be about the same claim. To continue with the trial analogy, two experts produce integrating evidence when they testify on different aspects of the case, one being a ballistics expert testifying about the way the gun was fired and the other being a criminal psychologist testifying about the suspect’s motives.

A useful way of understanding how integration works is to use causal graphs. One could think of the mechanism as the full causal graph and the different pieces of evidence as being about different components of the same graph. Again, diverse evidence in this sense is often produced using different methods, but it need not be. For example, evidence for a mechanism mediating an effect in a field experiment could be produced by a mechanism experiment.

Integration may be realized in a number of ways in various epistemic contexts. Cartwright’s (Reference Cartwright2021) proposal for MMR comes closest to our notion of integration. Cartwright’s argument is that a mix of methods may well be needed if the aim is to support different kinds of subsidiary claims (such as claims about the presence or absence of support factors) that must hold true for the overall claim to be true. Likewise, Shan and Williamson (Reference Shan and Williamson2021) point out that “to establish a causal claim one normally needs to establish the existence of an appropriate conditional correlation and the existence of an appropriate mechanism,” proposing this as a foundation for MMR. Combining evidence for the existence of a correlation and evidence for the existence of a mechanism fits both the logic of integration and some instances of MMR. For example, with regard to nested analysis, statistical studies provide evidence for average causal effects, and case studies evidence for case-specific causal mechanisms. However, the nested analysis framework connects these two types of analysis in a relatively restricted way: case studies either provide (dis)confirmatory instances of the mechanistic hypotheses behind the statistical analysis, or serve as a heuristic source of new hypotheses for subsequent statistical analysis.

4. Causal pluralism and mutually supporting evidence

Some defenders of MMR support the idea that different methods of data production and analysis embody different notions or conceptions of causality, which in turn correspond to alternative philosophical theories of causation (e.g., Cartwright Reference Cartwright2007; Reiss Reference Reiss2009; Illari and Russo Reference Illari and Russo2014). Whereas quantitative methods are usually assumed to presuppose a dependence/difference-making concept of causation, qualitative methods are more in tune with production and process conceptions. In turn, it is sometimes claimed, differences in conceptions of causation imply differences in the rules of causal inference. Johnson et al. (Reference Johnson, Russo and Schoonenboom2019, 155) write, for example, that evidential pluralism, which holds that “many sources of evidence are needed and used in our making of causal claims,” entails conceptual pluralism, namely that “there are different kinds of causes at the conceptual level.” The implication is that there are also different kinds of causes on the level of reality, in other words ontological pluralism. However, if evidential pluralism entailed conceptual and especially ontological pluralism, it would create more problems for MMR than it solves.

First, we have already questioned the idea that having methods of different kinds automatically results in stronger evidence.Footnote 3 Second, as Beach and Kaas (Reference Beach and Kaas2020) have argued, strong conceptual pluralism entails that the causal claims supported by different methods are really incommensurable, and therefore that MMR is not feasible to begin with. Our position that it is the variety of evidence, not of methods or data, that is epistemically important further strengthens Beach and Kaas’s argument: If the causal claims for which the distinct methods produced evidence were built on incommensurable concepts of causation, there could not be any well-defined inferential relations between them, and thus no epistemic gains from a variety of evidence.

Finally, conceptual causal pluralism has undesirable practical consequences. If different methods produced evidence for claims that embody different concepts of cause, they could also legitimately support apparently contradictory causal conclusions. For example, in qualitative studies it is claimed that active labor-market policies have a negative impact on employment (through demotivation and exit from the market), whereas quantitative studies indicate that their impact is positive. For the end user of this information (e.g., policy makers) this is deeply unsatisfactory, but for the conceptual pluralist there is not necessarily anything particularly puzzling about it. The apparent contradiction could be attributed to the different methods implying different concepts of “impact” (presumably process and difference making).Footnote 4

As we cannot accept that all MMR research is doomed to either failure or practical irrelevance because of conceptual incommensurability, we have to deny genuine pluralism on either the conceptual or the ontological level. For MMR to work, different kinds of causal claims built from different causal concepts have to be inferentially relatable to one another. This requires at least some degree of conceptual unity and coherence in causal reasoning and inference, which conceptual pluralism does not give. Fortunately, it is one thing to point out that social scientists make use of different causal concepts (e.g., average treatment effect, causal relevance, causal capacity, mechanism, process) with distinct inferential properties, and another to claim that these causal concepts correspond to fundamentally different concepts of causation. Conceptual, let alone ontological, pluralism cannot be motivated by the plurality of causal concepts alone (Reiss Reference Reiss2009).

Even though we cannot conclusively argue in favor of any specific causal account that unifies the causal concepts relevant to MMR, we agree with Rohlfing and Zuber (Reference Rohlfing and Zuber2021) that the interventionist theory of causation utilizing causal graphs is promising in terms of analytic and expressive power. The interventionist account of causation could arguably be used to clarify and regiment inferential relations between unit- and population-level claims, between type and token claims, as well as between causal-effect and mechanism claims. The interventionist framework is not fully neutral with respect to the epistemology of causation, however. Most importantly, it denies the implicit assumption that causal-process observations obtained using case-based research methods could somehow sidestep the fundamental problem of causal inference, namely that the relevant counterfactual values of the variables cannot be directly observed. Beach (Reference Beach2020, 167–68), for example, regards counterfactuals as one possible test for causality that could be achieved by experimental means rather than through analyses of the meaning of the claim being tested. The idea seems to be that if your concept of causation is singularist and process-oriented, you can simply observe causation if you look closely enough.Footnote 5

This is not to say that purely observational case-based causal inference is impossible. What makes it possible, however, is not a distinct concept of causation together with some kind of causal sixth sense. It is rather that the detailed documentation of a series of interactions could ground causal claims when, and insofar as, background causal knowledge is sufficiently reliable. It is quite common in social science for this background knowledge to be based on everyday reasoning and common folk-psychological interpretational practices, and not on explicit social or psychological theories. This may make it easy to forget that reading causation into everyday social interactions does require causal assumptions.

5. Concluding remarks

We have proposed an understanding of MMR in terms of the variety-of-evidence thesis in support of causal inferences, arguing that different MMR procedures can produce and benefit from three distinct kinds of variety of evidence. We also addressed the concern that MMR is not feasible because some methods of data production and analysis embody different, and incommensurable, conceptions of causality. The upshot is that it has the potential to be a powerful methodology for studying causal inference in social science, but its added value can only be secured given the right kind of variety of evidence and the right procedure for bringing it together. The focus on the differences between methods in current methodological discussions on MMR risk distracting scholars from substantial questions concerning the claims for which the diverse evidence is evidence of, how it is diverse over and above being produced by different methods, and in what way different kinds of diversity work in support of causal inference.

Acknowledgments

Previous versions of this paper has been presented at the Mixed Methods Research and Causal Inference conference at the University of Kent in May 2022, ENPOSS 2022, and PSA 2022. We thank the audiences in these events for their useful comments. We would also like to thank Jordi Cat for commenting on a draft of this paper. The authors contributed equally to this paper.

Footnotes

1 Beach (Reference Beach2020) approvingly cites the Russo–Williamson thesis, which states that establishing causal claims in science needs the support of both mechanisms and dependencies since probabilistic evidence only establishes causality if it can be accounted for by an underlying mechanism (Russo and Williamson Reference Russo and Williamson2007, 159). However, the thesis vindicates simple methodological pluralism only on the assumption that probabilistic evidence and evidence of mechanisms are produced by distinct methods.

2 Schupbach (Reference Schupbach2018) argues against explicating the epistemic value of variety in terms of (in)dependence, proposing that the variety relevant to triangulation is grounded on the capability of the body of evidence to eliminate alternative hypotheses. The exact nature of the epistemic value of triangulation not being the main issue here, we do not pursue this question further.

3 See also Crasnow (Reference Crasnow2010), who argues that, perhaps despite appearances, MMR does not deploy diverging conceptions of cause.

4 We thank social policy researcher Ben Baumberg Geiger for this point and for this specific example.

5 MMR frameworks implicitly, and sometimes explicitly inherit this assumption (cf. Lieberman Reference Lieberman2005), even though they are mostly silent about the internal validity of the causal inference methods to be mixed.

References

Achinstein, Peter. 2001. The Book of Evidence. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ahmed, Amel, and Sil, Rudra. 2012. “When Multi-Method Research Subverts Methodological Pluralism—Or, Why We Still Need Single-Method Research.” Perspectives on Politics 10 (4):935–53.10.1017/S1537592712002836CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beach, Derek. 2020. “Multi-Method Research in the Social Sciences: A Review of Recent Frameworks and a Way Forward.” Government and Opposition 55 (1):163–82.Google Scholar
Beach, Derek, and Kaas, Jonas. 2020. “The Great Divides: Incommensurability, the Impossibility of Mixed-Methodology, and What to Do about It.” International Studies Review 22 (2):214–35.Google Scholar
Bogen, Jim, and Woodward, James. 1988. “Saving the Phenomena.” The Philosophical Review 97 (3):303–52.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 2007. Hunting Causes and Using Them: Approaches in Philosophy and Economics. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 2013. “Evidence, Argument and Prediction.” In EPSA11 Perspectives and Foundational Problems in Philosophy of Science, edited by Vasillios Karakostas and Dennis Dieks, 317. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 2021. “Rigour Versus the Need for Evidential Diversity.” Synthese 199 (5):13095–119.Google Scholar
Claveau, Francois. 2013. “The Independence Condition in the Variety-of-Evidence Thesis.” Philosophy of Science 80 (1):94118.Google Scholar
Claveau, Francois, and Grenier, Olivier. 2019. “The Variety-of-Evidence Thesis: A Bayesian Exploration of its Surprising Failures.” Synthese 196 (8):3001–28.Google Scholar
Coppedge, Michael. 2005. “Explaining Democratic Deterioration in Venezuela through Nested Induction.” In The Third Wave of Democratization in Latin America, edited by Frances Hagopian and Scott Mainwaring, 289316. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Crasnow, Sharon. 2010. “Evidence for Use: Causal Pluralism and the Role of Case Studies in Political Science Research.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (1):2649.Google Scholar
Fitelson, Brandon. 2001. “A Bayesian Account of Independent Evidence with Applications.” Philosophy of Science 68 (S3):S123S140.Google Scholar
Heesen, Remco, Bright, Liam, and Zucker, Andrew. 2019. “Vindicating Methodological Triangulation.” Synthese 196 (8):3067–81.Google Scholar
Humphreys, Macartan, and Jacobs, Alan. 2015. “Mixing Methods: A Bayesian Approach.” The American Political Science Review 109 (4):653–73.Google Scholar
Illari, Phyllis. 2011. Mechanistic evidence: disambiguating the Russo–Williamson thesis. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 25(2), 139157.Google Scholar
Illari, Phyllis, and Russo, Federica. 2014. Causality: Philosophical Theory Meets Scientific Practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, R. Burke, Onwuegbuzie, Anthony, and Turner, Lisa. 2007. “Toward a Definition of Mixed Methods Research.” Journal of Mixed Methods Research 1 (2):112–33.Google Scholar
Johnson, R. Burke, Russo, Federica, and Schoonenboom, Judith. 2019. “Causation in Mixed Methods Research: The Meeting of Philosophy, Science, and Practice.” Journal of Mixed Methods Research 13 (2):143–62.10.1177/1558689817719610CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuorikoski, Jaakko, and Marchionni, Caterina. 2016. “Evidential Diversity and the Triangulation of Phenomena.” Philosophy of Science 83 (2):227–47.10.1086/684960CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuorikoski, Jaakko, and Marchionni, Caterina. 2022. “Mixed Method Research and Variety of Evidence in Political Science.” in Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Political Science, edited by Harold Kincaid and Jeroen van Bouwel, 266–280. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Leonelli, Sabina. 2015. “What Counts as Scientific Data? A Relational Framework.” Philosophy of Science 82 (S5):S810S821.Google Scholar
Lieberman, Evan, 2005. “Nested Analysis as a Mixed-Method Strategy for Comparative Research.” American Political Science Review 99 (3):435–52.Google Scholar
Lloyd, Elisabeth. 2009. “Varieties of Support and Confirmation of Climate Models.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 83 (1):213–32.Google Scholar
Ludwig, Jens, Kling, Jeffrey, and Mullainathan, Sendhil. 2011. “Mechanism Experiments and Policy Evaluations.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 25 (3):1738.10.1257/jep.25.3.17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marchionni, Caterina, and Reijula, Samuli. 2019. “What Is Mechanistic Evidence and Why Do We Need It for Evidence-Based Policy?Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 73:5463.Google Scholar
Plano Clark, Vicky, and Ivankova, Natalya. 2016. “How to Use Mixed Methods Research? Understanding the Basic Mixed Methods Designs.” In Mixed Methods Research: A Guide to the Field, edited by Clark, Vicky Plano and Ivanova, Natalya, 105–34. Los Angeles: SAGE.Google Scholar
Reiss, Julian. 2009. “Causation in the Social Sciences: Evidence, Inference, and Purpose.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 39 (1):2040.Google Scholar
Rohlfing, Ingo, and Schneider, Carsten. 2018. “A Unifying Framework for Causal Analysis in Set-Theoretic Multimethod Research.” Sociological Methods & Research 47 (1):3763.Google Scholar
Rohlfing, Ingo, and Zuber, Christina. 2021. ”Check Your Truth Conditions! Clarifying the Relationship between Theories of Causation and Social Science Methods for Causal Inference.” Sociological Methods & Research 50 (4):1623–59.Google Scholar
Runhardt, Rosa. 2022. “Limits to Limits to Evidential Pluralism: Multi-Method Large-N Qualitative Analysis and the Primacy of Mechanistic Studies.” Synthese 200 (2): 171.10.1007/s11229-022-03650-wCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russo, Federica, and Williamson, Jon. 2007. “Interpreting Causality in the Health Sciences.” International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21 (2):157–70.Google Scholar
Schupbach, Jonah. 2018. “Robustness Analysis as Explanatory Reasoning.” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 (1):275300.Google Scholar
Seawright, Jason. 2016. Multi-Method Social Science: Combining Qualitative and Quantitative Tools. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Shan, Yafeng, and Williamson, Jon. 2021. “Applying Evidential Pluralism to the Social Sciences.” European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 (4):127.Google Scholar
Staley, Kent. 2004. “Robust Evidence and Secure Evidence Claims.” Philosophy of Science 71 (4):467–88.Google Scholar
Stegenga, Jacob. 2009. “Robustness, Discordance, and Relevance.” Philosophy of Science 76 (5):650–61.Google Scholar
Woolcock, Michael. 2019. “Reasons for Using Mixed Methods in the Evaluation of Complex Projects.” In Contemporary Philosophy and Social Science: An Interdisciplinary Dialogue. Edited by Michiru Nagatsu and Attilia Ruzzene, 147–171. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
Zahle, Julie. 2019. “Data, Epistemic Values, and Multiple Methods in Case Study Research.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 78:3239.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. A schematic representation of kinds of evidential variety. P is a proposition about a phenomenon, En is evidence, and M is a mechanism; arrows represent causal relations whereas lines represent evidential relations.