Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T15:23:12.488Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kinds and Criteria of Scientific Laws

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Mario Bunge*
Affiliation:
University of Buenos Aires

Abstract

Factual statements that might qualify for the status of law statements are classed from various philosophically relevant standpoints (referents, precision, structure of predicates, extension, systemicity, inferential power, inception, ostensiveness, testability, levels, and determination categories). More than seven dozen of not mutually exclusive kinds of lawlike statements emerge. Strictly universal and counterfactually powerful statements are seen to constitute just one kind of lawlike statements; classificatory and some statistical laws, e.g., are shown not to comply with the requirements of universality and counterfactual force.

Conditions for lawlike statements to be called laws are then examined, and a liberal criterion of lawfulness is finally proposed, which reads thus: A proposition is a law statement if and only if it is a posteriori (not logically true), general in some respect (does not refer to unique objects), has been satisfactorily corroborated for the time being in some domain, and belongs to a theory (whether adult or embryonic). It is claimed that criteria of laws change alongside with the emergence of new usages of the term ‘law’, and that by adopting a liberal criterion of lawfulness we would conform to contemporary usage and would cease inhibiting the search for regularities in the sciences of man.

Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1961

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Braithwaite, Richard Bevan, Scientific Explanation, Cambridge University Press, 1953.Google Scholar
[2] Bunge, Mario, Causality: The Place of the Causal Principle in Modern Science, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1959.Google Scholar
[3] Bunge, Mario, Metascientific Queries, Springfield, Ill., Charles C. Thomas 1959.Google Scholar
[4] Bunge, Mario, “The Place of Induction in Science”, Philosophy of Science, 27, 262 1960.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5] Bunge, Mario, “Analyticity Redefined”, Mind (to appear).Google Scholar
[6] Bunge, Mario, “Levels: A Semantical Preliminary”, Review of Metaphysics, 13, 396, 1960.Google Scholar
[7] Bunge, Mario, “On the Connections among Levels”, Proceedings of the XIIth International Congress of Philosophy (in press).Google Scholar
[8] Bunge, Mario, “Laws of Laws” (forthcoming).Google Scholar
[9] Campbell, Norman, What is Science? 1921, New York: Dover, 1952.Google Scholar
[10] Carnap, Rudolf, “Testability and Meaning”, Philosophy of Science, 3, 419, 1936 and 4, 1, 1937.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[11] Carnap, Rudolf, Logical Foundations of Probability, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1950.Google Scholar
[12] Chisholm Roderick, M.Law Statements and Counterfactual Inference”, Analysis, 15, 97, 1955.Google Scholar
[13] Feigl, Herbert, “Existential Hypotheses”, Philosophy of Science, 17, 35, 1950.Google Scholar
[14] Goodman, Nelson, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, London, Athlone Press, 1954; Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1955.Google Scholar
[15] Hempel, Carl G. and Oppenheim, PaulStudies in the Logic of Explanation”, Philosophy of Science, 15, 135, 1948.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[16] Hempel, Carl G, Fundamentals of Concept Formation, being No 7, vol. II of the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press, 1952.Google Scholar
[17] Kneale, William, Probability and Induction, Oxford University Press, 1952.Google Scholar
[18] Körner, Stephan, “On Laws of Nature”, Mind (N.S.), 62, 216, 1953.Google Scholar
[19] Lalande, André, “Les théories de l'induction et de l'expérimentation, Paris, Boivin, 1929.Google Scholar
[20] Mehlberg, Henryk, The Reach of Science, Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 1958.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[21] Popper, Karl R., The Logic of Scientific Discovery, 1935, London, Hutchinson, 1959.Google Scholar
[22] Reichenbach, Hans, Elements of Symbolic Logic, N. York, Macmillan, 1947.Google Scholar
[23] Reichenbach, Hans, Nomological Statements and Admissible Operations, Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1954.Google Scholar
[24] Ritchie, A. D. Scientific Method, London, Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co, 1923.Google Scholar
[25] Wisdom, John Oulton Foundations of Inference in Natural Science, London, Methuen, 1952.Google Scholar