Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T23:46:24.589Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Transcending the Realism/Anti-Realism Divide in the Philosophy of History

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 February 2017

Abstract

In this essay an attempt is made to transcend the divide between realists and anti-realists in the philosophy of history by proposing an alternative account of understanding the past, one based on the nature of testimonies, specifically their scope and depth. This is done through a critical engagement with the works of prominent realist and anti-realist philosophers of history (Bevir/Lorenz and Ankersmit/White, respectively); other philosophers working on relevant topics such as epistemology, and historians who have written on historical method. The alternative account thus developed is then tested by applying it to the case of the Historikerstreit, the bitterly waged historian's struggle concerning the history and legacy of Nazism. On the surface it appears to affirm the anti-realist position that posits historical narratives as being inherently normative/aesthetic given the inadequacies of the ‘thick’ realist position, but upon closer scrutiny it demonstrates the merit of my alternative, testimony-based ‘thin’ realist account.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Carr, E.H., What is History? Second Edition (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 2627 Google Scholar.

2 Bevir, Mark, ‘What is genealogy?’, Journal of the Philosophy of History 2 (2008), 263275, 269CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Bevir, Mark, ‘Why historical distance is not a problem’, History and Theory 50 (2011), 2437, 31CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

4 Bevir, Mark, The Logic of the History of Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 104 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Lorenz, Chris, ‘Can Histories be True? Narrativism, Positivism, and the “Metaphorical Turn”’, History and Theory 37 (1998), 309329, 325CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

6 White, Hayden, Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973), 12 Google Scholar.

7 Ankersmit, Frank, Historical representation (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 11 Google Scholar.

8 For an acknowledgement of this from the realist side see Bevir (op. cit. note 3, 24) and Lorenz (op. cit. note 5, 309), and from the anti-realist side see Bevir, Mark & Ankersmit, Frank, ‘Exchanging Ideas’, Rethinking History: The Journal of Theory and Practice 4 (2011), 351372, 352CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 Whereas Ankersmit is a classical liberal in the European sense of the term.

10 Used here not in the pejorative sense, since White's conception of ideology ‘included beliefs about the nature of reality and the nature of the good life (…) designat[ing] a wide range of basic beliefs that somehow guide an individual's moral life’. See Paul, Herman, Hayden White: The Historical Imagination (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2011), 23 Google Scholar.

11 White, Hayden, ‘Afterword’ in Bonnel, Victoria E. & Hunt, Lynn (eds), Beyond the Cultural Turn: New Directions in the Study of Society and Culture (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998), 315324, 316Google Scholar.

12 The modes of emplotment White distinguishes are: Romance, Comedy, Tragedy, Satire; the modes of explanation: Formist, Organicist, Mechanistic, Contextualist; the modes of ideology: Anarchist, Conservative, Radical, Liberal (op. cit. note 6, 29).

13 Op. cit. note 6, x, 11–12, 29.

14 Ibid., xii.

15 Op. cit. note 10, 139. However, as I discuss below as well, partly under pressure from critics he was forced to concede to realists the existence of what he termed ‘modernist events’ such as the Holocaust, which are absolutes that do not fall under the category of normative judgement (op. cit. note 10, 129–130). Lorenz argues that this concession undermines his anti-realist stance, which requires one to go all the way (op. cit. note 5, 328). I tend to agree with this, though I believe White was merely conceding this point for, somewhat ironically perhaps, strategic, normative reasons.

16 Op. cit. note 7, 11.

17 Ankersmit, Frank, ‘[Historiography and Postmodernism: Reconsiderations]: Reply to Professor Zagorin’, History and Theory 29 (1990), 275–296, 275277 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

18 Zammito, John, ‘Ankersmit and Historical Representation’, History and Theory 44 (2005), 155–181, 155, 178179 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Ankersmit, Frank, Narrative Logic: A Semantic Analysis of the Historian's Language (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1983) 7 Google Scholar.

20 Op. cit. note 19, 82.

21 Ibid., 8.

22 Domanska, Ewa, ‘Frank Ankersmit: From Narrative to Experience’, Rethinking History 13 (2009), 175195, 188CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

23 Op. cit. note 7, 13, 33–34, 97–97; op. cit. note 18, 178–179. In his most recent work Ankersmit has shifted his focus from historical narrative to historical experience, which Domanska argues represents a regression, ‘a return to a traditional Romantic view of immediate experience combined with an Enlightenment analysis of it’ (op. cit. note 22, 175). I will not focus on this dimension of his work as it does not directly bear on the discussion concerning realism and anti-realism in historical theory. See Ankersmit, Frank, Sublime Historical Experience (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005); op. cit. note 22, 175Google Scholar.

24 Though as Iggers notes the interpretation of Ranke by many positivist postwar historians as one of their own does not do justice to the nuance of his own thoughts on historical method. See Iggers, Georg, The German Conception of History: The National Tradition of Historical Thought from Herder to the Present (Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1983) 6365 Google Scholar.

25 Op. cit. note 17, 275–276.

26 West, Cornel, The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989), 201 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations: Revised Fourth Edition (Singapore: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009 [1953]), 11 Google Scholar.

28 Bevir, Mark & Paul, Herman, ‘Naturalized Epistemology and/as Historicism: A Brief Introduction’, Journal of the Philosophy of History 6 (2012), 299303 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

29 For an account of the debates surrounding the nature of such conceptual primitives – in phenomenological parlance known as the basic features of our being in the world – proposed by realist philosophers of science, mind and language in various ways (e.g. in Quine originating from observation and in Chomsky from innate mental structures), see Shanker, Stuart, ‘The Conflict between Wittgenstein and Quine on the Nature of Language and Cognition and its Implications for Constraint Theory’ in Arrington, Robert & Glock, Hans-Johann (eds). Wittgenstein and Quine (London: Routledge, 2003), 212–25Google Scholar.

30 Op. cit. note 4, 114–115.

31 Ibid., 18, 23.

32 Ibid., 24, 28.

33 Lorenz, Chris, ‘Historical Knowledge and Historical Reality: A Plea for “Internal Realism”’, History and Theory 33 (1994), 297327, 309CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

34 Op. cit. note 4, 18.

35 Ibid., 90–91.

36 Ibid., 88, 184.

37 Ibid., 94–95.

38 Op. cit. note 4, 125–126.

39 Ibid., 87–88. As argued in the following section, it is from the overextension of this argument that Bevir's problematic focus on the linguistic as opposed to the institutional dimensions of historiographical practices emanates from.

40 Op. cit. note 33, 309–310; op. cit. note 5, 317–319. Bevir levels the same critique against the anti-realists (op. cit. note 3, 30), and I believe they are right in this respect as elaborated in the following sections.

41 Op. cit. note 33, 307, 321.

42 Ibid., 324.

43 Ibid., 313.

44 Kuhn, Thomas, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions: Third Edition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 7, 10CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

45 Rorty, Richard, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press), 11 Google Scholar.

46 Op. cit. note 19, 82.

47 Historiographical practices thus refer to all of the historian's activities, not merely its products; so source-gathering in archives, writing texts, participating in conferences, and the embodied forms of knowledge possessed by virtue of being participants in the historian's field. For a detailed account of what is included in this category see Paul, Herman, ‘Performing History: How Historical Scholarship is Shaped by Epistemic Virtues’, History and Theory 50 (2011), 1–19, 23 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

48 This is a crucial point, for in cases where the historian's field is politicized, as is typically the case in totalitarian societies where it is subject to censorship and is forced to engage in propagandistic activity, its nomos or logic no longer functions in accordance with rational criteria of theory choice in the way I go on to describe. This is effectively blocked by interference from the political field (i.e. the state). As Pierre Bourdieu elaborates with respect to academic fields more generally: ‘The anarchic confrontation of individual investments and interests is transformed into rational dialogue only to the extent that the field is sufficiently autonomous (and therefore equipped with sufficiently high entry barriers) to exclude the importation of non-specific weapons, especially political or economic ones, into the internal struggles – to the extent that the participants are constrained to use only instruments of discussion or proof corresponding to the scientific demands in the matter (such as the “principle of charity”), and are therefore obliged to sublimate their libido dominandi into a libido sciendi that can only triumph by answering a demonstration with a refutation, one scientific fact with another scientific fact’. See Bourdieu, Pierre, Pascalian Meditations (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000), 111112 Google Scholar.

49 Op. cit. note 4, 100.

50 Ankersmit, Frank, Historical Representation (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 21, 28Google Scholar.

51 Quine, W.V.O., Pursuit of Truth (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990), 13 Google Scholar.

52 Op. cit. note 1, 10–11.

53 For the philosophical importance of this exclusion with respect to maintaining a realist position in the philosophy of history see Ginzburg, Carlo, ‘Just One Witness: The Extermination of the Jews and the Principle of Reality’ in idem, Threads and Traces: True False Fictive (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2012), 165179 Google Scholar. As Ginzburg notes there (169), the denial is not a philosophically interesting point except to illustrate the ‘principle of reality’ underlying the field, just as the denial of the existence of gravity or the existence of flat earth theories does not undermine the normal consensus on these matters existing in the scientific community, also derived from our first-order realist beliefs emanating from our being in the world. As noted by Quine the same holds true for the obverse, the affirmation of epistemological and ontological foundationalism (op. cit. note 51, 9–10).

54 Op. cit. note 3, 25.

55 Op. cit. note 5, 317–319.

56 Op. cit. note 11, 316.

57 Op. cit. note 7, 37.

58 Op. cit. note 3, 29.

59 Ibid., 31.

60 Ibid., 37.

61 Op. cit. note 4, 19.

62 Op. cit. note 1, 11–12.

63 Iggers, Georg G. & Wang, Q. Edward, A Global History of Modern Historiography (London: Routledge, 2013), 25 Google Scholar.

64 Ricœur, Paul, Memory, History, Forgetting (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004), 21 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

65 Op. cit. note 4, 27.

66 Op. cit. note 64, 178.

67 Ibid., 174.

68 Ibid., 147.

69 Hansen, Mogens Herman, Polis: An Introduction to the Ancient Greek City-State (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 90, 122Google Scholar.

70 Op. cit. note 1, 13; Op. cit. note 63, 286. Anthropologists such as Jack Goody have done extensive analyses of non-literate communities, but this is another matter entirely as its possibility is premised on the production of direct testimonies by others who observe their practices. Non-literate communities lacking such an externality, and not being in the vicinity of a literate community, are literally without history except through the oral traditions passed on over many generations, which are on the level of indirect rather than direct testimonies where it concerns the remembrance of events extending beyond one's direct experiences, which is what witness accounts require. See Goody, Jack, The Interface Between the Written and the Oral (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987)Google Scholar.

71 Op. cit. note 64, 147.

72 Op. cit. note 53.

73 Ibid., 169; Op. cit. note 64, 255.

74 Op. cit. note 10, 132–133.

75 Hilberg, Raul, The Destruction of the European Jews (Chicago: Quadrangle Books, 1961)Google Scholar; Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Assassins of Memory: Essays on the Denial of the Holocaust (New York: Columbia University Press); Yehuda Bauer, Rethinking the Holocaust (New Haven: Yale University Press).

76 Vidal-Naquet, Pierre, ‘A Paper Eichmann: Anatomy of a Lie’ in idem, Assassins of Memory: Essays on the Denial of the Holocaust (New York: Columbia University Press, 1992)Google Scholar. Retrieved 3 January 2017 from http://www.anti-rev.org/textes/VidalNaquet92a/.

77 Op. cit. note 76.

78 Op. cit. note 4, 18–19, 80. One can even say, speaking with Habermas, that it contains a performative contradiction, in that the past is being described when at the same time the epistemological possibility of the means of viably describing the past (via first-order truth-claims contained in testimonies) is being denied or undercut. In Habermas's own technical vocabulary: ‘A performative contradiction occurs when a constative speech act k(p) rests on noncontingent presuppositions whose propositional content contradicts the asserted proposition p’. See Jürgen Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press), 80.

79 In relation to the possibility of reconstructing the nature of testimonies – which are affected by the social conditions of their production though not reducible to them – this means to take on the post-foundational approach of rejecting absolute objectivity (be it obtainable via a monistic method such as linguistic contextualism or otherwise), and instead taking it on as a regulative ideal (op. cit. note 4, 33–34).

80 Sosa, Ernest, A Virtue Epistemology: Apt Belief and Reflective Knowledge: Volume 1 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007), 93 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

81 Ibid., 93–94.

82 Bevir, Mark, ‘Objectivity in history’, History and Theory 33 (1994), 328344, 340CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

83 Op. cit. note 80, 94–95.

84 White, Hayden, ‘The Public Relevance of Historical Studies: A Reply to Dirk Moses’, History and Theory 44 (2005), 333338, 337CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

85 Op. cit. note 64, 394.

86 Op. cit. note 4, 18–19.

87 Op. cit. note 7, 12, 237.

88 Op. cit. note 80, 93–94.

89 Op. cit. note 33, 313.

90 Op. cit. note 33, 318.

91 Op. cit. note 33, 318–319.

92 Ibid., 313.

93 Ibid., 318–319.

94 Ibid., 318.

95 Op. cit. note 47.

96 Op. cit. note 84, 337; op. cit. note 7, 12, 237.

97 The historiography of which is littered with contention that often maps onto ideological differences, like Marxists against liberals.