Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T03:48:25.875Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Animals and the Unity of Psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

Gareth B. Matthews
Affiliation:
University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Extract

By ‘the unity of psychology’ I mean something one might also express by saying that the psychology of human beings is part of the psychology of animals generally.

Perhaps there are several different ways of trying to trace out the ramifications of the idea that psychology is one. A central consideration, I think, is likely to be some sort of principle of continuity up and down the scale of nature. The idea would be that up and down the scale of animated or ensouled things (‘psyched up’ beings, empsucha) there are always psychological continuities, never any strict discontinuity. If human beings can get angry, can want to get ahead in life, can see an illusion, can develop an Oedipus complex, then so can some lower animal do either the very same thing, something similar, or at least something analogous.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1978

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 ‘Persistent Problems in the Evolution of Mind,’ Quarterly Review of Biology, 24 (1959), 2842Google Scholar; quoted in Griffin, , p. 117.Google Scholar

2 E.g., Phaedo 81d82bGoogle Scholar, Timaeus 90e91c.Google Scholar

3 De Anima 63.Google Scholar

4 The Philosophical Works of Descartes, Vol. II, Haldane, & Ross, (trans.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1934), 210211.Google Scholar

5 Descartes, , Philosophical Letters, Kenny, A. (trans.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1970), 207.Google Scholar

6 Ibid., p. 133.

7 Rosenfield, Leonora, From Beast-Machine to Man-Machine (New York: Columbia, 1968), 54.Google Scholar

8 Ithaca, New York: Cornell, 1972.

9 Reprinted in Malcolm, Norman, Thought and Knowledge (Ithaca, New York: Cornell, 1977), 4057.Google Scholar

10 Vendler, , p. 153.Google Scholar

11 New York Times, 29 05 1974, p. 52.Google Scholar

12 Malcolm, , pp. 5455.Google Scholar

13 Ibid., p. 56.

14 Ibid., pp. 49–50.

16 Ibid., p. 54.

17 Vendler, , p. 154.Google Scholar

18 Malcolm, , p. 47.Google Scholar

19 Ibid., pp. 48–49.

20 Vendler, , pp. 162163.Google Scholar

21 Cf. Melzack, Ronald, The Puzzle of Pain (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1973), Chapter 2.Google Scholar

22 Descartes, , Letters, p. 208.Google Scholar

23 Letter to More, , 5 02 1649Google Scholar, Letters, p. 245.Google Scholar

24 Philosophy, 52, No. 199 (01 1977), 1326.Google Scholar

25 This article draws on material from two lectures in a series of eight given at Cambridge University in 1976 under the title, ‘The Concept of Soul’. I have responded to criticisms from my Cambridge audience and from audiences at the Universities of Notre Dame, Rochester, Vermont, Rice Univrsity, Oberlin College and Franklin and Marshall College. At Oberlin this material went into two in the 1976 series of Mead-Swing Lectures.