Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-lrf7s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-28T17:18:05.385Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Political Language and Political Reality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 November 2022

Murray Edelman*
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin, Madison

Extract

The most incisive twentieth century students of language converge from different premises on the conclusion that language is the key creator of the social worlds people experience, and they agree as well that language cannot usefully be understood as a tool for describing an objective reality. For the later Wittgenstein there are no essences, only language games. Chomsky analyzes the sense in which grammar is generative. For Derrida all language is performative, a form of action that undermines its own presuppositions. Foucault sees language as antedating and constructing subjectivity. The “linguistic turn” in twentieth century philosophy, social psychology, and literary theory entails an intellectual ferment that raises fundamental questions about a great deal of mainstream political science, and especially about its logical positivist premises.

While the writers just mentioned analyze various senses in which language use is an aspect of creativity, those who focus upon specifically political language are chiefly concerned with its capacity to reflect ideology, mystify, and distort. The more perspicacious of them deny that an undistorting language is possible in a social world marked by inequalities in resources and status, though the notion of an undistorted language can be useful as an evocation of an ideal benchmark. The emphasis upon political language as distorting or mystifying is a key theme in Lasswell and Orwell, as it is in Habermas, Osgood, Ellul, Vygotsky, Enzensberger, Bennett, and Shapiro.

Type
The Lasswell Symposium
Copyright
Copyright © The American Political Science Association 1985

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Barry, Brian, Political Argument (New York: Humanities Press, 1966).Google Scholar

2 Habermas, Jurgen, “Toward a Theory of Communicative Competence,” Inquiry, Vol. 13 (1970).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 Schall v. Martin, 81 L. Ed. 2d 207 (1984).

4 Orwell, George, “Politics and the English Language,” in A Collection of Essays (Garden City: Doubleday-Anchor, 1954), p. 172.Google Scholar

5 Heclo, Hugh, “Issue Networks and the Executive Establishment,” in King, Anthony (ed.), The New American Political System (Washington, D.C.: American Enterprise Institute, 1978), pp. 87124.Google Scholar

6 Cf. Foucault, Michel, The Order of Things (New York: Pantheon Books, 1971)Google Scholar; The Archeology of Knowledge (New York: Harper & Row, 1976). A similar idea appears in the works of other twentieth-century European social theorists, notably in Heidegger, Lacan, Derrida, and Ricoeur.

7 Burke, Kenneth, A Grammar of Motives (New York: Prentice-Hall, 1945), p. 393.Google Scholar