Hostname: page-component-788cddb947-xdx58 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-19T10:29:31.146Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE THIRD LIFECYCLE OF PHILOKLEON IN ARISTOPHANES’ WASPS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 January 2023

Robert Cowan*
Affiliation:
The University of Sydney bob.cowan@sydney.edu.au

Extract

The mutability of Philokleon's generational identity in Aristophanes’ Wasps is well established. Critics routinely write of his ‘rejuvenation’ in the second half of the play, and it is in the scene with the αὐλητρίϲ (‘aulos-girl’), Dardanis, that the old man most explicitly plays the part of an irresponsible youth waiting for his son (in the role of father) to die. However, inversions and perversions of generational identity pervade the whole play. Even before Philokleon has undergone his liberating transformation at the symposion, the educational roles of father and son are reversed as Bdelykleon schools him in the proper way to behave in polite society. More subtly and extensively, Bowie has shown how the three agones in which Philokleon unsuccessfully engages during the first half of the play correspond to the three stages of an Athenian male citizen's life: ephebeia, maturity in the hoplite phalanx, and old age in the jury. However, critics have not observed that Philokleon goes through another, parallel journey from youth through maturity to old age in the three ‘iambic scenes’ where he is confronted by the victims of his outrageous behaviour on his way home from the symposion. This article will show how Aristophanes constructs this third lifecycle (counting Bowie's agones and his literal maturation before the play's action begins) before considering its implications for the wider characterization of Philokleon and in particular the final scene.

Type
Research Article
Information
Ramus , Volume 51 , Issue 2 , December 2022 , pp. 131 - 159
Copyright
Copyright © Ramus 2023

I. Introduction

The mutability of Philokleon's generational identity in Aristophanes’ Wasps is well established.Footnote 1 Critics routinely write of his ‘rejuvenation’ in the second half of the play, and it is in the scene with the αὐλητρίϲ (‘aulos-girl’), Dardanis, that the old man most explicitly plays the part of an irresponsible youth waiting for his son (in the role of father) to die.Footnote 2 However, inversions and perversions of generational identity pervade the whole play.Footnote 3 Even before Philokleon has undergone his liberating transformation at the symposion, the educational roles of father and son are reversed as Bdelykleon schools him in the proper way to behave in polite society.Footnote 4 More subtly and extensively, Bowie has shown how the three agones in which Philokleon unsuccessfully engages during the first half of the play correspond to the three stages of an Athenian male citizen's life: ephebeia, maturity in the hoplite phalanx, and old age in the jury.Footnote 5 However, critics have not observed that Philokleon goes through another, parallel journey from youth through maturity to old age in the three ‘iambic scenes’ where he is confronted by the victims of his outrageous behaviour on his way home from the symposion.Footnote 6 This article will show how Aristophanes constructs this third lifecycle (counting Bowie's agones and his literal maturation before the play's action begins) before considering its implications for the wider characterization of Philokleon and in particular the final scene.Footnote 7

The mapping of the three iambic scenes onto the three ages of an Athenian male is most clearly signalled by the way in which each of his antagonists addresses or identifies Philokleon at the opening of their respective entrance speeches. In the first or second line of each successive speech, he is referred to respectively as νεανίαϲ (‘young man’, 1333), ἀνήρ (‘man’, 1390), and γέρων (‘old man’, 1417).Footnote 8 Although none of these words is especially marked in itself, in sequence they inevitably evoke the three principal stages of a man's life, particularly in a play so preoccupied with those stages. The sequence of life-stages, with some variations and often preceded by boyhood, is attested in various texts from Hesiod onwards, perhaps most clearly in Philo's On Joseph, where he describes the average man as ‘the one-time baby, after that a child, then an adolescent, then a lad, and in turn a youth, then a man, and finally an old man’ (ὁ ποτὲ βρέφοϲ καὶ μετὰ ταῦτα παῖϲ, εἶτ’ ἔφηβοϲ, εἶτα μειράκιον, καὶ νεανίαϲ αὖθιϲ, εἶτ’ ἀνήρ, καὶ γέρων ὕϲτατον, Jos. 22 = 127 CW).Footnote 9 In this context, the three words’ positioning at the very opening of each scene programmatically establishes Philokleon's persona for that scene, so that the scenes themselves trace an arc from youth through maturity to senescence.

Although Aristophanes’ iambic scenes can give the superficial impression of being a random, unconnected set of primarily low-comedy sketches, they tend in fact to be carefully arranged and structured into a significant sequence. Gelzer has shown how the many iambic scenes in Birds form a tripartite sequence moving from the foundation rites of Nephelokokkygia to its completion to the impact of that completion.Footnote 10 Grava too has demonstrated, with regard to Dikaiopolis’ encounters with the Megarian and Boiotian merchants and other characters in Akharnians, that ‘the purposes for which these iambic scenes have been inserted into the dramatic fabric show a complexity superior to what may appear at first sight’, for ‘the section has a very complex structure, since it consists of parts that each have several functions.’Footnote 11 Similarly the iambic scenes in Wasps, apparently random and unconnected, are structured around Philokleon's third lifecycle, one scene for each stage from νεανίαϲ to ἀνήρ to γέρων. In each case, as we shall see, this persona is enacted in the course of the scene.

On one level, as has already been suggested, this movement runs parallel with the three age-related agones that Bowie has identified in the first half of the play. However, the differences are equally important. Philokleon is defeated by Bdelykleon in each of the pre-parabasis agones and, with each defeat, he is stripped successively of his identity as youth, man, and old man, until he is finally reduced to the absence of identity which enables him to declare with total accuracy, οὐδέν εἰμ' ἄρα (‘I am nothing’, 997).Footnote 12 In marked contrast to this sequence of defeats, but typically for an Aristophanic hero in iambic scenes, Philokleon wins each of his three agones against his three accusers (as well as against Bdelykleon) and is thus able to maintain each of his identities, overlaying them upon each other. Passing through the lifecycle from νεανίαϲ to ἀνήρ to γέρων does not here mark his relinquishing of each but rather his paradoxical embodiment of all three at the same time, an embodiment which reaches its climax in the exodos. Following his rejuvenation, Philokleon is not ‘nothing’ but everything.

In additional to verbal cues, the visual dimension stresses the paradox of Philokleon's multigenerational status. His distinctive mask of a comic old man stands in jarring contrast to his louche, young-man-about-town costume of Spartan slippers and Persian cloak, a dissonance which was explicitly set up in the scene where Bdelykleon redresses his father (1122–68).Footnote 13 However, it is the contradiction between the old man's mask and his sometimes athletic, always disorderly physical activity that most strongly conveys visually his paradoxical status as both young and old. On a basic level, the contradiction generates the humour of incongruity, as an old man behaves in a way appropriate to a different generation. However, in combination with the other elements of these scenes, it also gives visual reinforcement to the conceit that Philokleon is all three of νεανίαϲ, ἀνήρ, and γέρων. This sense that Philokleon is legion has significant points of contact with Silk's reading of him:

Philocleon seems to transcend the bounds of an individual, as if he were indeed himself the centre of some larger organism. Perhaps, even, he is a kind of one-man community… In his person, it is as if the possibilities of life, not of a specified individual life (because he is ‘larger than life’ in that sense of ‘life’), but of life itself, have been sensuously conveyed, which is to say that in his recreative figuration something of an inclusive vision is implicit.Footnote 14

However, it is time to look at the three scenes, and in particular their programmatic opening speeches, in more detail.

II. Philokleon the νεανίαϲ

In the first iambic scene, an unnamed man rushes onstage immediately after Xanthias’ narration of the symposion and Philokleon's entrance with the aulos-girl, Dardanis:

ἦ μὴν ϲὺ δώϲειϲ αὔριον τούτων δίκην
ἡμῖν ἅπαϲιν, κεἰ ϲφόδρ' εἶ νεανίαϲ.
ἁθρόοι γὰρ ἥξομέν ϲε προϲκαλούμενοι.
(V. 1332–4)
I warn you, you will pay the penalty for these things tomorrow
to all of us, even if you are a very young man.
For we shall come en masse to summons you.Footnote 15

The anomalous nature of this description is amply demonstrated by the unease it has caused among commentators and critics, and the strategies it has forced them to adopt to explain it.Footnote 16 Sansone even suggests emending νεανίαϲ to the more literally true νεανικόϲ (‘like a young man’).Footnote 17 MacDowell adopts a characteristically and sensitively naturalistic approach by suggesting that it is a genuine case of mistaken identity prompted by the accuser's understandable inference from Philokleon's antics.Footnote 18 Biles and Olson reject such an approach to Aristophanes’ dramaturgy but are equally keen to normalize the scene by emphasizing that Philokleon is acting not as but like a young man.Footnote 19 Van Leeuwen is likewise particularly careful to insist that neither actual rejuvenation nor mistaken identity are in question, but only youthful behaviour.Footnote 20 Lenz arguably comes closest to embracing the scene's paradoxical quality, noting that ‘the assignment of youth to Philokleon, which twists the actual realities, is straightaway accepted by him and played with further in his reply.’Footnote 21 Each of these interpretations is, in its own way, correct. It is Philokleon's lawless behaviour which makes him appear to be a youth and this appearance is focalized through the fallible perceptions of the accuser, though the audience's perception of this (perhaps young) actor playing an old man playing a youth is no more reliable. However, in the non-naturalistic, anti-realistic world of Aristophanic comedy—and even in Wasps, which lacks giant dung-beetles or talking birds, elderly jurors have real stings and dogs make prosecution speeches—these factors do not explain away Philokleon's actual rejuvenation but rather establish it.Footnote 22 As Bowie puts it, ‘[t]his joke about his rejuvenation, so often repeated, cannot be merely farcical. We are dealing with a true rolling back of the years for Philocleon.’Footnote 23 Or, in Hutchinson's more succinct formulation, ‘Philocleon now behaves like a νεανίας, and is one’.Footnote 24

However, the rejuvenation is neither simple nor final. It is notable that Bowie's splendid discussion immediately leaps from the Dardanis episode to the exodos, omitting the further developments and complications that accrue in the intervening iambic scenes. It is true that the initial exchange with the first accuser seems not only to assert Philokleon's new status as a rejuvenated νεανίαϲ, but to reinforce it by rejecting his earlier status as a γέρων:

ἰηῦ ἰηῦ, ‘καλούμενοι’.
ἀρχαῖά γ' ὑμῶν. ἆρά γ' ἴϲθ' ὡϲ οὐδ' ἀκούων ἀνέχομαι
δικῶν; ἰαιβοῖ αἰβοῖ.
τάδε μ' ἀρέϲκει⋅ βάλλε κημούϲ. οὐκ ἄπει;
ποῦ 'ϲτ’ ἠλιαϲτήϲ; ἐκποδών.
(V. 1335–40)
Ha ha! ‘To summons.’
Your stuff is ancient! Don't you know that I can't stand even to hear
about trials? Eee-ew!
This is my kind of thing; to hell with voting urns. Won't you get lost?
Where᾽s the juror? Get away!

Philokleon's total rejection of jury duty marks a volte face from his previous status as an obsessive φιληλιαϲτήϲ (‘trial-lover’, 88), his ‘cure’ from his madness, and with it a rejection of his associated status as an old man.Footnote 25 His claim that the accuser and his companions are doing or saying ἀρχαῖα is a comically incongruous insult for an old man to aim at (presumably) younger interlocutors. Starkie compares it to Strepsiades’ expressed surprise in Clouds that his son Pheidippides ‘[is] a lad and [has] old-fashioned ideas’ (παιδάριον εἶ καὶ φρονεῖϲ ἀρχαιϊκά, Nu. 821).Footnote 26 The parallel will be an important one for Philokleon's later, more paradoxical assertion that the old are younger than the young, but here his assertion is bolder though less complex: Philokleon rejects his status as an old man and adopts wholesale the persona of a youth berating the outmodedness of his elders.

This reinvention of himself as the νεανίαϲ his accuser has called him goes hand in hand with the rejection of what had been his persona in the earlier part of the play: the accuser's ἀρχαῖα are the old-fashioned things associated with the old men among whom Philokleon no longer counts himself, but they are also his ‘former’ (LSJ ἀρχαῖος 3) persona as old man and juror.Footnote 27 From being fixated on trials, he can no longer bear even to hear about them and his insatiability has turned to disgust, expressed with the quintessentially Aristophanic αἰβοῖ.Footnote 28 His penultimate jibe, ποῦ 'ϲτ’ ἠλιαϲτήϲ; (1340), does primarily serve as ‘a rhetorical question implying “There's no juror here” and underlin[ing] the lack of recourse to justice that the accuser can expect.’Footnote 29 However, it also draws attention to the fact that Philokleon-the-juror, indistinguishable from Philokleon-the-old-man, is not here.Footnote 30 At this stage, Philokleon's rejuvenation does seem to be straightforward and radical.Footnote 31 He is now a νεανίαϲ and becoming that has entailed total renunciation of his status as a γέρων. Even for the ultimate recreative-discontinuous character, this is a radical metamorphosis.Footnote 32 It should be noted, however, that unlike his previous ephebic phase in the first of Bowie's agones, here in this brief agon with the accuser Philokleon is victorious and as a result not stripped of his status as a νεανίαϲ.

Indeed, so far from being stripped of his youthful persona, Philokleon develops it to considerable comic effect in the ensuing scene, with Dardanis and later Bdelykleon. Furthermore, he superimposes a second identity upon it. His persona is no longer purely that of a νεανίαϲ, with Bdelykleon as the corresponding γέρων. It is in this scene that the paradox of his status as simultaneously νεανίαϲ and γέρων is established, and it will be maintained through to its climax in the final scene. Pace Rusten, it is not quite the case that ‘[t]hese roles [sc. Philokleon as νεανίαϲ, Bdelykleon as γέρων] are not discarded until 1379f., when Bdelykleon calls his father back to reality and Philokleon begins to show a preference for age over youth’.Footnote 33 Throughout Philokleon's speech to Dardanis, the audience is never permitted to forget (quite apart from the aforementioned visual dimension, which modern readers of the play all too easily forget) that he is a γέρων as well as a νεανίαϲ, and conversely he retains his youthful vigour and violence even when asserting the superiority of age in the fist-fight with his son. The gloriously comical incongruities of Philokleon's speech and in particular its inversion of what would at least later become the standard comic relationship between strict father and unruly son have been often and well discussed. The incongruity of an old man speaking in these terms can be taken as a comedic end in itself, or even as tinged with pathos.Footnote 34 However, in this scene, the incongruity is not primarily based on the gap between appearance and reality.Footnote 35 Rather it is a means of expressing the paradox of Philokleon's dual status. It is not so much that he is acting like a νεανίαϲ while, in Vaio's ‘bitter reality’, he is ‘really’ a γέρων, as that he embodies both age-statuses at the same time.

The distinctive feature of the elderly Philokleon's play with the persona of a reckless youth is that it always keeps both identities in view simultaneously. This is most clearly evident when he talks about waiting for the strict Bdelykleon to die:

ἐὰν γένῃ δὲ μὴ κακὴ νυνὶ γυνή,
ἐγώ ϲ' ἐπειδὰν οὑμὸϲ υἱὸϲ ἀποθάνῃ,
λυϲάμενοϲ ἕξω παλλακήν, ὦ χοιρίον.
νῦν δ' οὐ κρατῶ 'γὼ τῶν ἐμαυτοῦ χρημάτων⋅
νέοϲ γάρ εἰμι. καὶ φυλάττομαι ϲφόδρα⋅
τὸ γὰρ υἵδιον τηρεῖ με, κἄϲτι δύϲκολον
κἄλλωϲ κυμινοπριϲτοκαρδαμογλύφον.
ταῦτ' οὖν περί μου δέδοικε μὴ διαφθαρῶ⋅
πατὴρ γὰρ οὐδείϲ ἐϲτιν αὐτῷ πλὴν ἐμοῦ.
(V. 1351–9)
But if you're not a bad girl to me now
I, when my son dies,
will buy your freedom and have you as my concubine, my pussy.
Now, I don't have control over my own property.
For I'm young. And I am heavily guarded.
For my little son keeps watch on me, and he is grumpy
and, another thing, a cress- and cumin-peeling skinflint.
So when it comes to these things, he's anxious about me in case I'm corrupted.
For he has no father but me.

The casting of Bdelykleon in the role of the strict father led Crichton to the attractive and ingenious formulation that ‘Philocleon as young rake is actually the grandson of Philocleon as old juror’.Footnote 36 Attractive though it is, it does not fully capture the paradox that Aristophanes conjures. It would have been perfectly possible for Philokleon to inhabit the role of the νεανίαϲ so completely—in keeping with his total rejection of the role of γέρων in the confrontation with the first accuser—as to refer to Bdelykleon as his actual father. We might compare the situation in Plautus’ Casina (720–59) where the roles of master and slave are reversed between the senex amator Lysidamus and his slave Olympio.Footnote 37 Although this is part of the larger (doomed) ruse to give Lysidamus sexual access to Casina by marrying her to Olympio, it is not a scene of impersonation which would require strict adherence to roles but rather ‘some horseplay’, as Konstan puts it,Footnote 38 which is clearly demarcated by acknowledgments that the real slave–master relationship is still in place. Nevertheless, for the course of the brief horseplay, Lysidamus fully and straightforwardly (if ironically) adopts the role of slave (seruos sum tuos, ‘I am your slave’, 738) and assigns that of master to Olympio (opsecro te, | Olympisce mi, mi pater, mi patrone, ‘I implore you, my Olympiokins, my father, my former master’, 738f.), while the latter likewise speaks of his master as a slave (quid mi opust seruo tam nequam?, ‘What need do I have for so worthless a slave?’, 741).

Philokleon could easily have spoken in the same terms of what he would do when οὑμὸϲ πατὴρ ἀποθάνῃ (‘my father dies’) or about the watchful eye of his πατρίδιον (‘little father’), casting himself as the only υἱόϲ that Bdelykleon has.Footnote 39 The incongruity would have remained intact and indeed offered a sharper dissonance between the discrete categories of νεανίαϲ and γέρων, between the illusory persona that Philokleon adopts and the reality established by his costume and the action of the play so far. By choosing instead to employ the topoi associated with a dissolute son talking about his strict father, but using language that acknowledges that this is in fact a father talking about the son (οὑμὸϲ υἱόϲ; τὸ γὰρ υἵδιον), Aristophanes obliterates the distinction between νεανίαϲ and γέρων. Philokleon is acting as a youth—or in Hutchinson's formulation, ‘he is one’—at precisely the same moment as he is acknowledging his status as an old man. His waiting for his son to die is not a son's action displaced onto a father, since a son does not have a υἱόϲ. Rather it is a filial action that only a father could perform, the paradoxical essence of youthful old age and senescent adolescence. Philokleon is νεανίαϲ and γέρων in one.

This paradoxical coexistence of νεανίαϲ and γέρων recurs during—and indeed is the key element of—Philokleon's victory over Bdelykleon at the end of this scene. If the elderly component of Philokleon's character in the scene with Dardanis has been neglected by scholars, then his continuing youthfulness in the confrontation with Bdelykleon has been similarly overlooked. Rusten's assertion that ‘Philokleon begins to show a preference for age over youth’ in this sequence identifies its key feature, but obscures the two facts that, except for the brief exchange with the first accuser, he never really stopped valuing old age, and that his youthful character is maintained even here. The key lines are those in which Philokleon uses against Bdelykleon one of the very anecdotes that his son had taught him as repartee for the symposion, combining the verbal victory with a violent physical re-enactment of it:Footnote 40

Φι.     ἄκουϲόν νυν ἐμοῦ.
Ὀλυμπίαϲιν, ἡνίκ' ἐθεώρουν ἐγώ,
Ἐφουδίων ἐμαχέϲατ' Ἀϲκώνδᾳ καλῶϲ
ἤδη γέρων ὤν⋅ εἶτα τῇ πυγμῇ θενὼν
ὁ πρεϲβύτεροϲ κατέβαλε τὸν νεώτερον.
πρὸϲ ταῦτα τηροῦ μὴ λάβῃϲ ὑπώπια.
Βδ. νὴ τὸν Δί', ἐξέμαθέϲ γε τὴν Ὀλυμπίαν.
(V. 1381–7)
Phil.     Listen to me.
At Olympia, when I was a spectator,
Ephoudion fought well against Askondas
even though he was already an old man. Then striking with his fist
the older man knocked down the younger.
Accordingly, watch out that you don't get black eyes.
Bdel. By Zeus, you thoroughly learnt about Olympia at least.

Philokleon's emphasis on Ephoudion's age and the carefully pointed antithesis between older and younger in line 1385 do indeed assert a preference for age over youth, but they do so by foregrounding the paradoxical quality of age's victory and the fact that it is achieved by acting in a youthful manner. The concessive force of the participial phrase ἤδη γέρων ὤν clearly implies the antithesis that, ‘even though he was already an old man’, he fought well as one would expect a young man to. Even to articulate that ‘the older man knocked down the younger’ presupposes an assumption that the roles would normally be the other way round. Philokleon's paradeigma Ephoudion behaves as a νεανίαϲ at the very time that his status as a γέρων is being stressed, just like Philokleon the old-young lover. When Philokleon imitates that paradeigma by knocking down the νεώτεροϲ Bdelykleon, he is a γέρων behaving as a νεανίαϲ, not only in his unexpectedly superior physical prowess, but because the action itself—in the context of the Dardanis scene and through evocation of the previous year's Clouds—becomes that of a πατραλοίαϲ (‘father-beater’), the father-cum-son and aged νεανίαϲ beating the son-cum-father and youthful γέρων.Footnote 41 The first iambic scene closes with a further expression of Philokleon's paradoxical dual status, as Bdelykleon observes that, like a child, his father has ‘thoroughly learnt his lesson’ (ἐξέμαθεϲ), but a lesson that is about how an old man can behave like a youth.

III. Philokleon the ἀνήρ

The second iambic scene follows immediately, as the bread-seller, Myrtia, enters and addresses her summons-witness, Khairephon:

ἴθι μοι παράϲτηθ', ἀντιβολῶ, πρὸϲ τῶν θεῶν.
ὁδὶ γὰρ ἁνήρ ἐϲτιν ὅϲ μ' ἀπώλεϲεν
τῇ δᾳδὶ παίων, κἀξέβαλεν ἐντευθενὶ
ἄρτουϲ δέκ' ὀβολῶν κἀπιθήκην τεττάρων.
(V. 1388–91)
Come and stand by me, I beg you, by the gods.
For this is the man who did for me,
striking me with a torch, and threw off from this
loaves worth ten obols and a tray-cover worth four.Footnote 42

Philokleon's status as ἀνήρ is not delineated in this scene by an association with hoplite warfare, as it is in Bowie's second agon.Footnote 43 Rather, Philokleon is an ἀνήρ as the unmarked, normative, default centre of a patriarchal society and even universe, a mature citizen male human, set in opposition to (or perhaps more accurately, having set in opposition to him) his gendered, political, and zoological others, without the delimiting and diminishing specification of youthful immaturity or enervated senescence.Footnote 44 Like Hermippos’ Thales, he is human not beast, man not woman, Greek not barbarian, and more specifically he is Athenian citizen, not metic or foreigner.Footnote 45 These characteristics, these instances of being safely on the right side of a polarity, also mark a stage of maturation and set him apart from the androgynous liminality of the ephebe and the political limbo of the unenrolled child, or even the qualified civic status of the youth in his twenties.Footnote 46

Philokleon's status as man-not-woman is most clearly established by his opposition to and victory over the female bread-seller, Myrtia, the sole woman among the three complainants, one of just two female characters in the whole play and the only one with a speaking part. The audience is subtly but repeatedly reminded of her femininity, though mere readers of the play must as ever remember that her gender is also obvious to spectators from her mask and costume. Verbal reminders are provided incidentally by Philokleon's reference to her as ταύτῃ (‘this woman’, 1395) and addressing of her ὦ γύναι (‘o woman’, 1399), and more markedly by her own use of ‘an oath used in comedy exclusively by women’, μὰ τὼ θεώ (‘by the two goddesses’, 1396).Footnote 47 Perhaps most marked, however, is her self-identification as the daughter of citizen parents: Μυρτίαϲ | τῆϲ Ἀγκυλίωνοϲ θυγατέροϲ καὶ Ϲωϲτράτηϲ (‘Myrtia, the daughter of Ankylion and Sostrate’, 1396f.).Footnote 48 Commentators have rightly identified Myrtia's anxiety to establish her citizen status and the way in which her attempt to do so is ironically undermined by the reference to Ankylion, apparently a stock figure notorious for incestuous or other transgressions. However, they have overlooked how the basis of Myrtia's anxiety and the failure of her attempt to allay it are also underlined by the anomalous form of her self-identification, as if she were a citizen male.Footnote 49

Sommerstein is of course correct that, in Greek comedy, ‘[w]omen name themselves and each other freely, even when addressing men’ and ‘that there is a tendency in Aristophanes…to identify women indirectly by naming their male relatives’ so that ‘the evident implication is that so far as men outside the family were concerned, a married woman's only identity was as somebody's wife’.Footnote 50 However, Myrtia is here establishing her own identity, using her own name and those of her parents rather than her husband. If we exclude the special case of the anthropomorphized trireme, Nauphantes, daughter of Nauson (Ναυφάντης γε τῆς Ναύσωνος) at Knights 1309, the closest and perhaps only parallel is Kritylla in Thesmophoriazousai. When Kritylla identifies herself as Κρίτυλλά γ᾿ Ἀντιθέου Γαργηττόθεν (‘Kritylla, [wife/daughter] of Antitheos from Gargettos’, Th. 898), whether Antitheos is the name of her (dead, 446) husband or father,Footnote 51 her inclusion of the demotic is clearly marked and anomalous, so that ‘in the spirit of the women's assembly, she appropriates the male form of état civil.’Footnote 52 Lenz and Sommerstein have rightly stressed that the naming of both parents establishes Myrtia's full citizenship, but while they are also correct in seeing this as an assertion of her civic right to be protected from ill treatment, it simultaneously throws into relief the limitations of those civic rights vis-à-vis the ‘fuller’ full citizenship of an adult male.Footnote 53 As a woman and hence a citizen with only partial citizen rights, Myrtia is not permitted to give evidence in court and is thus reliant on a male κλήτηρ (‘summons witness’) to bear witness to her summonsing of her attacker. That attacker, Philokleon, is set in sharp contrast as both ἀνήρ and πολίτηϲ.

It is not only Myrtia whose diminished gender and citizenship status throw Philokleon's role as ἀνήρ into relief. Her (or Aristophanes’) choice of Khairephon as summons-witness has puzzled critics.Footnote 54 While the full implications of that choice may continue to elude modern readers and audiences unfamiliar with aspects of his reputation which have been lost over time, his depiction in this scene throws marked and surely significant emphasis on his pallor:

Φι.  καὶ ϲὺ δή μοι, Χαιρεφῶν,
γυναικὶ κλητεύειϲ ἐοικὼϲ θαψίνῃ
Ἰνοῖ κρεμαμένῃ πρὸϲ ποδῶν Εὐριπίδου;
(V. 1412–14)
Phil.  And are you of all people, Khairephon,
acting as summons-witness against me for a woman, like pallid
Ino hanging before the feet of Euripides?

The precise relevance of the allusion to Euripides’ Ino and in particular the substitution of the playwright himself for one of his characters (probably Athamas) is also elusive and the recent papyrus discoveries of fragments from the tragedy have unfortunately shed no new light on it.Footnote 55 Nevertheless, it is clear that his notorious pallor, which is also mentioned in Clouds and Birds, in this scene at least is closely associated with effeminacy, providing as it does the principal point of comparison with the tragic heroine Ino. As Taaffe puts it, ‘[h]is pale skin suggests effeminacy. At best, his masculinity would be compromised and the authority of his testimony weakened. At worst, the witness might be mistaken for a woman and so not be able to testify in court.’Footnote 56 Philokleon emphasizes not only Myrtia's need, as a woman, for a summons-witness (γυναικὶ κλητεύειϲ), but the unsuitability for the job of Khairephon of all people (ϲὺ δή)Footnote 57 as one whose effeminacy renders him the civic as well as the sexual equivalent of a woman. In the agonistic context of the iambic scene, both emphases presuppose the superiority—and the fact that it can be presupposed reinforces that superiority—of Philokleon as man and full citizen.

However, it is not only in gender and politics that Philokleon's status as ἀνήρ is set above Myrtia's. Thales’ first polarity of human and beast is also brought to bear as Philokleon uses an anecdote about Aesop and a dog to attempt to silence his accuser.

Αἴϲωπον ἀπὸ δείπνου βαδίζονθ' ἑϲπέραϲ
θραϲεῖα καὶ μεθύϲη τιϲ ὑλάκτει κύων.
κἄπειτ' ἐκεῖνοϲ εἶπεν, ‘ὦ κύον κύον,
εἰ νὴ Δί' ἀντὶ τῆϲ κακῆϲ γλώττηϲ ποθὲν
πυροὺϲ πρίαιο, ϲωφρονεῖν ἄν μοι δοκεῖϲ.’
(V. 1401–5)
As Aesop was walking home one evening from dinner,
a certain insolent and drunken bitch barked at him.
And then he said, ‘O bitch, bitch,
if, by Zeus, if in exchange for your wicked tongue, from somewhere
you were to buy wheat, I think you'd be showing sense.’

In employing an Aesopic fable ostensibly to defuse a hostile situation, just as with the Sybarite tales he uses with his next accuser (1427–40), Philokleon is either incompetently or, more probably, wilfully and mischievously misapplying his son's earlier advice that these are perfect techniques to ‘turn the matter [of drunken violence] into a joke so that [the victim] lets [him] off and leaves’ (κᾆτ' εἰϲ γέλων | τὸ πρᾶγμ' ἔτρεψαϲ, ὥϲτ' ἀφείϲ ϲ' ἀποίχεται, 1260f.).Footnote 58 Where Bdelykleon envisaged the reconciliatory effect of communal laughter, his father weaponizes the Aesopic to render his opponents the objects of derision so that they leave the field of battle and let him off by defaulting.Footnote 59 Myrtia herself recognizes his tactic as she immediately responds ‘Are you also deriding me?’ (καὶ καταγελᾷϲ μου;, 1406), the καί indicating that this verbal assault is in addition and parallel to his earlier physical one. As well as offering Myrtia something that is ‘a subtle but undeniable misrepresentation of the facts and offensive at the same time’,Footnote 60 Philokleon makes the further unexpected move of interpreting his son's formulation ‘some funny Aesopic story’ (λόγον…τινα, | Αἰϲωπικὸν γέλοιον, 1258f.) not as a beast fable entirely populated by anthropomorphized animals, but as a story featuring Aesop himself that sets up a sharp distinction between the human and the animal. It is this aspect of the λόγοϲ that contributes to Philokleon's depiction as ἀνήρ in this scene.

Animal imagery, often connected to Aesopic fable, is famously pervasive throughout Wasps and is most frequently associated with Philokleon himself.Footnote 61 In the course of the play he is described as or compared to (often by himself) a non-specific ‘beast’ (κνώδαλον, 4), limpet (105), bee (107 bis, 366), jackdaw (129), mouse (140, 204), donkey (189, 1306, 1310), horse (192), sparrow (207), weasel (363), and of course wasp (430).Footnote 62 This ‘multifaceted human-animal identity of Philocleon’, as Miles terms it,Footnote 63 makes it all the more marked that in the confrontation with Myrtia he firmly identifies himself with the human Aesop against the female dog who transparently stands for his opponent. The detail of having Aesop walking home from a feast, as Philokleon was from the symposion, clearly identifies the two, even if he more tendentiously transfers his own insolence and drunkenness onto the dog. The identification of Myrtia with the dog, however, produces a rather more complex effect than merely providing ‘an excuse for him to shout “You stupid bitch!” in the woman's face’, though that is undeniably part of the old man's intention.Footnote 64 On one level, it dehumanizes her, exploiting the culturally constructed superiority of ἄνθρωποϲ over θηρίον, Αἴϲωποϲ over κύων, to assert Philokleon's superiority over Myrtia. Yet its very assimilation of the bitch to the bread-seller—most jarringly in ‘Aesop's’ suggestion that the ‘dog’ buy wheatFootnote 65—activates that complex of associations which equates ideas of the canine and the feminine. As Franco puts it, ‘[t]he symbolic overlap between dog and woman [was] a perfect training ground for exercising ideological strategies that maintained feminine subordination.’Footnote 66 Myrtia is demeaned, not so much because she is constructed as dog rather than woman, but because dog and woman are constructed as equivalents. Her overlapping statuses as γυνή and κύων emphasize the antithetical and superior status of Philokleon as ἀνήρ.

Throughout the scene, Philokleon's status as the ἀνήρ that Myrtia initially calls him is reinforced by setting him in polar opposition to the femininity, animality, and limited citizen status of Myrtia as well as to Khairephon's effeminacy. The paradox of his triple status as νεανίαϲ, ἀνήρ, and γέρων is foregrounded less than in the preceding scene. Nevertheless, being depicted as a mature man with full citizen rights and powers while simultaneously behaving with the wanton outrageousness of a youth and wearing the headpiece (and presumably employing the gait and gestures) of an old man maintain the audience's sense that he is all three.

IV. Philokleon the γέρων and his ‘Death’

The third and final accuser—another man—addresses Philokleon as an old man, bringing his tripartite lifecycle across the three iambic scenes to its logical conclusion:

οἴμοι κακοδαίμων. προϲκαλοῦμαί ϲ᾿, ὦ γέρον,
ὕβρεωϲ.
(V. 1417f.)
Oh poor me! I summon you on a charge, old man,
of wanton assault.

Finally, Philokleon is identified, not as a νεανίαϲ or ἀνήρ, but as the γέρων as which his costume and backstory also designate him. However, this acknowledgment of his old age is immediately undercut by its juxtaposition with an accusation that jarringly reasserts his youth.Footnote 67 ὕβριϲ was closely connected with youth, as in the famous Sophoklean fragment:Footnote 68

ὕβριϲ δέ τοι
οὐπώποθ᾿ ἥβηϲ εἰϲ τὸ ϲῶφρον ἵκετο,
ἀλλ᾿ ἐν νέοιϲ ἀνθεῖ τε καὶ πάλιν φθίνει.
(S. fr. 786 Radt)
ὕβριϲ, I tell you,
never reaches the moderation of maturity
but flowers in the young and in its turn fades.

In setting out the qualities of old age, Aristotle specifically differentiates the ὕβριϲ of youth from the κακουργία (‘malice’) of the elderly (Rh. 1390a), while, at the other end of the age spectrum, Xenophon marks it out as a tendency which develops when males undergo the transition from being παῖδεϲ (‘boys’) to μειράκια (‘lads’, often equivalent to νεανίαι; Lac. 3.1f.). Plato describes Ktesippos as good and noble in nature ‘except that he was a ὑβριϲτήϲ on account of being young’ (ὅϲον μὴ ὑβριϲτὴϲ διὰ τὸ νέος εἶναι, Euthd. 273a). Most pertinently for Philokleon, Agathon's servant in Thesmophoriazousai reacts to one of Mnesilokhos’ characteristically outrageous insults by wryly commenting, ἦ που νέοϲ γ' ὢν ἦϲθ' ὑβριϲτήϲ, ὦ γέρον (Th. 63). As Austin and Olson unpack the implications of the particles, ‘You must certainly have acted outrageously when you were young, old man, [if you're acting this way now]!’Footnote 69 The implicit incongruity of a γέρων acting as a ὑβριϲτήϲ leads the servant to infer that Mnesilokhos must a fortiori have been a ὑβριϲτήϲ when he was a νέοϲ and at the age when such ὕβριϲ is to be expected.

Back in Wasps, the incongruity of the old man's hubristic behaviour is emphasized already in Xanthias’ (Philokleon's slave) narration of the symposion at 1299–325. The notion that behaviour rather than years is the determinant of life-stage is introduced when the chorus justify calling Xanthias παῖ (‘boy’, but also ‘slave’), ‘for it's fitting to call someone who takes a beating “boy”, even if he's an old man’ (παῖδα γάρ, κἂν ᾖ γέρων, | καλεῖν δίκαιον ὅϲτιϲ ἂν πληγὰϲ λάβῃ, 1297f.). At the symposion, Philokleon was ‘by far the most outrageous’ (ὑβριϲτότατοϲ μακρῷ, 1303), even against some very disreputable competition, and ‘thoroughly insulted’ (περιύβριζεν, 1319) the whole company. The incongruity of an old man's behaving in this way is indicated lightly by Xanthias’ introduction of him as ὁ γέρων (1299) and more pointedly when Lysistratos addresses him ὦ πρεϲβῦτα (1309) before noting his similarity to a nouveau riche Phrygian or a donkey in a chaff-heap. Most marked of all is Xanthias’ description of how the old man beat him νεανικῶϲ, not just ‘vigorously’, but ‘like a young man’, with Philokleon also inverting the slave's age too by calling him παῖ παῖ (1307).Footnote 70

This is not, of course, to say that mature men are never accused of ὕβριϲ or of being ὑβριϲταί. MacDowell is absolutely correct to declare that the ‘usual view is that it is in the teenager or the young man that hybris is most often found…[b]ut hybris can exist in old men too; youth or age is not part of the definition of hybris’.Footnote 71 Nevertheless, it is striking how often the association with youth is still made even when the ὑβριϲτήϲ is not a young man. Two of the closest, as well as among the most famous, parallels for Philokleon's humiliating physical assault are to be found in Demosthenes’ speeches against Konon and Meidias. Both are men in later middle age, Konon a little over fifty (D. 54.22), Meidias a little under (D. 21.154), but both are repeatedly accused of and associated with acts and displays of ὕβριϲ.Footnote 72 However, far from this being treated as something the jury might normatively expect fifty-year-old men to indulge in, even here the association of ὕβριϲ with youth is emphasized. Meidias’ act of ὕβριϲ against Demosthenes is one of the two ‘crowning acts he put on the entirety of his youthful pranks’ (κεφάλαι᾽ ἐφ᾽ ἅπαϲι τοῖϲ ἑαυτῷ νενεανιευμένοιϲ ἐπέθηκεν, 21.18) and he chose this option rather than acting as khoregos in competition with Demosthenes as a way to ‘manifest his youthful intemperance’ (ἐνεανιεύσατο, 21.69). The incongruity of an older man's behaving in a manner associated with the young is even more pointed in the case of Konon, who, unlike youths who can be afforded indulgence, performs his act of ὕβριϲ, as a man ‘who is over fifty, in the presence of younger fellows and these sons of his, and [acts] not to steer them away or prevent them, but himself is the leader and foremost and most loathsome of them all’ (ὅϲτιϲ δ᾽ ἐτῶν μέν ἐϲτιν πλειόνων ἢ πεντήκοντα, παρὼν δὲ νεωτέροιϲ ἀνθρώποιϲ καὶ τούτοιϲ υἱέϲιν, οὐχ ὅπωϲ ἀπέτρεψεν ἢ διεκώλυϲεν, ἀλλ᾽ αὐτὸϲ ἡγεμὼν καὶ πρῶτοϲ καὶ πάντων βδελυρώτατοϲ γεγένηται, 54.22).Footnote 73 While ὕβριϲ can be associated with tyrants, barbarians, the wealthy, and others with no particular reference to age, it is clear that, when age is an issue, as it is with Philokleon, Konon, and Meidias, the sense that such behaviour is the province of the young and incongruous in the old is never far from the surface and very frequently breaks through.

So it is when the third accuser juxtaposes his address of Philokleon as γέρων with the accusation of ὕβριϲ. In case the audience misses the crucial word, Bdelykleon immediately and despairingly repeats it, incredulously asking if this youthful crime is really what the accuser is charging an old man with (ὕβρεωϲ, ‘wanton assault’, 1418).Footnote 74 As in all three iambic scenes, the incongruity generates humour, but it also expresses the paradox of Philokleon's dual (or triple) status, an old man who is also sufficiently a youth that he possesses both the vigour and the arrogance to commit the quintessentially youthful crime of ὕβριϲ.Footnote 75

Despite this persistence of his νεότηϲ into the γῆραϲ of his accelerated third lifecycle, there are initially signs that Philokleon may be showing a degree of mellowing and moderation in keeping with his age and stage.Footnote 76 When the panic-stricken Bdelykleon offers to pay the accuser compensation for his father's misdemeanours, Philokleon offers of his ‘own free will to settle the matter’ with his victim (ἐγὼ μὲν οὖν αὐτῷ διαλλαχθήϲομαι | ἑκών, 1421f.) and confesses to assaulting him. However, his method of ‘settling’ is once more the wilful misapplication of his son's pre-sympotic advice, this time using two of the Sybarite tales which Bdelykleon paired with Aesopic fables (1259), to insult his accuser.Footnote 77 Unlike the aggressively masculine, anthropocentric Aesopic anecdote targeted at Myrtia, but like the inconsequential lasisma (story about Lasos) which follows it, the content of Philokleon's Sybarite tales to the third accuser have little significance for the construction of his generational identity. Rather it is their aggressive quality that marks him as reverting to or persisting in hubristic youthfulness. This is even more the case if Kaimio is correct in speculating that, as with the blow to Bdelykleon that mimetically accompanied Philokleon's narration of Ephoudion's felling of Askondas, he here (again) strikes the accuser while narrating the breaking of the ἐχῖνοϲ (‘jar’) by the Sybarite woman in 1435f.Footnote 78

Regardless of whether the violence is also physical or solely verbal, it demonstrates that, despite Philokleon's apparent reversion to behaviour befitting his (biological) age, this γέρων is continuing to act with the ὕβριϲ of a νεανίαϲ. This continuity is explicitly flagged to the audience by how the other characters onstage react to each of the Sybarite tales. Bdelykleon responds to the first by declaring ‘these acts of yours too are just like your other behaviour’ (ὅμοιά ϲου καὶ ταῦτα τοῖϲ ἄλλοιϲ τρόποιϲ, 1433).Footnote 79 The τρόποι of the main characters, their ‘“manners, ways, typical patterns of behaviour”…which stand in an ambiguous relation to [their] φύσις’,Footnote 80 especially Philokleon's (1002), but also Bdelykleon's (135) and the chorus’ (454, 1102), and in particular the possibility of changing them (504f., 748, 1450f., 1459f.), are a major theme of the play. Although the influences that shape and the criteria that characterize such τρόποι are complex and multifaceted, age-appropriateness is prominent among them. That there were distinct τρόποι in which the young and old respectively were expected to behave can be seen from the drama of the period. Euripides’ early Peliades includes sententious advice delivered to a young girl (Collard and Cropp suggest Pelias to Alkestis)Footnote 81 about appropriate behaviour:

αἰνῶ⋅ διδάξαι δ᾿ ὦ τέκνον ϲε βούλομαι⋅
ὅταν μὲν ᾖϲ παῖϲ, μὴ πλέον παιδὸϲ φρονεῖν,
ἐν παρθένοιϲ δὲ παρθένου τρόπουϲ ἔχειν
(E. Peliades fr. 603.1–3 Kannicht)
I commend you, but, my child, I want to instruct you:
when you are a child, not to think bigger than a child,
and when among maidens to have the τρόποι of a maiden

Gender roles are, of course, also in play here and Pelias goes on to talk about marriage and leaving business to men, but there is clear emphasis on age here (τέκνον, παῖϲ, even παρθένου) and what constitute appropriate τρόποι for the young. At the other end of the spectrum, the fourth-century Middle Comedy poet Philetairos (Aristophanes’ son, according to some traditions) rebukes an old man who has been spending too much time with prostitutes: ‘Because you are an old man, cease these τρόποι’ (παῦϲαι γέρων ὢν τοὺϲ τρόπουϲ, The Huntress fr. 6.1 PCG).Footnote 82 The addressee must cease his behaviour because he is an old man, a syllogism with the implied premise that this is not the societally approved behaviour of an old man.

Philokleon's τρόποι had appeared to be harmonizing with the status of γέρων which the accuser had assigned to him, but this was an illusion (or a deception) and his hubristic Sybarite tales are ‘just like’ (ὅμοιά, 1433) his youthfully hubristic behaviour towards the first accuser, Myrtia, and her witness Khairephon in the other iambic scenes, and towards all three of his victims in the offstage rampage that preceded them. The same point is made in a slightly different way by the third accuser's response to the second Sybarite tale: ‘Keep on acting hubristically, until the arkhon calls your case’ (ὕβριζ', ἕωϲ ἂν τὴν δίκην ἅρχων καλῇ, 1441). The continuous force of the present imperative, as well as the ring composition with the charge of ὕβριϲ that the accuser made on entrance (1418), stress that this is ongoing behaviour, ‘just like’ Philokleon's other τρόποι, and that he persists in acting as a νεανίαϲ, even though the opening address established him as the γέρων that his headpiece and backstory have always made him. Once again, in the third of this second series of agones, he is victorious, as the third accuser leaves the arena. Instead of being successively stripped of his identities as νεανίαϲ, ἀνήρ, and γέρων, he has maintained each of them while paradoxically (and acceleratedly) passing through the stages of life.

Despite this victory—or perhaps as an extension of it—Philokleon's third lifecycle still comes to its natural end with a symbolic death. The pre-parabasis agones also ended in a metaphorical death, which some critics take as part of the initiatory process ushering him from his old life of jury-mania to his new life of ease and pleasure.Footnote 83 Following Philokleon's triumph in the third of the post-parabasis agones, Bdelykleon finally loses patience and decides to take action:

Βδ. οὔτοι μὰ τὴν Δήμητρ' ἔτ' ἐνταυθοῖ μενεῖϲ,
ἀλλ' ἀράμενοϲ οἴϲω ϲε—
Φι.  τί ποιεῖϲ;
Βδ.  ὅ τι ποιῶ;
εἴϲω φέρω ϲ' ἐντεῦθεν⋅ εἰ δὲ μή, τάχα
κλητῆρεϲ ἐπιλείψουϲι τοὺϲ καλουμένουϲ.
Φι. Αἴϲωπον οἱ Δελφοί ποτ'—
Βδ.  ὀλίγον μοι μέλει.
Φι. φιάλην ἐπῃτιῶντο κλέψαι τοῦ θεοῦ⋅
ὁ δ' ἔλεξεν αὐτοῖϲ ὡϲ ὁ κάνθαρόϲ ποτε—
Βδ. οἴμ' ὡϲ ἀπολεῖϲ με τοῖϲι ϲοῖϲι κανθάροιϲ.
(V. 1442–9)
Bdel. By Demeter, you won't stay here any longer
but I'll pick you up and carry you—
Phil. What are you doing?
Bdel.  What am I doing?
I'm carrying you inside away from here. If I don't, soon
we'll run out of summons witnesses for the plaintiffs.
Phil. As for Aesop, the Delphians once—
Bdel.  I don't care a jot.
Phil. accused him of stealing one of the god's bowls.
But he told them that the dung-beetle once—
Bdel. Bloody hell, you'll kill me with these dung-beetles of yours!

Bdelykleon's intervention takes the play full-circle and marks the failure of his attempt to cure his father as he reverts to shutting the old man up inside the house.Footnote 84 This ring composition produces in the audience a sense of false closure, though one kept in tension with their expectation of the conventional convivial finale. The action of physically ‘carrying’ his father ‘inside’ (εἴϲω φέρω ϲ') serves as an inverted funereal ἐκφορά (‘carrying out’). Yet, in keeping with Philokleon's multiple age-statuses, it also renders the old man a babe in arms.Footnote 85 However, it is Philokleon's abortive introduction of one final Aesopic λόγοϲ that most clearly marks his carrying indoors as a symbolic death, albeit one very different from that following the acquittal of the dog Labes in the mock-trial at the end of the first half of the play.

Although this is the first extant reference to it, scholars generally agree that the story of Aesop's death at the hands of the Delphians must have been well established and well known by 422 BCE.Footnote 86 The extreme allusiveness which Bdelykleon's interruptions impose upon his father's fragmentary recounting of the story strongly suggest that the audience would have been easily able to fill in the gaps. In revenge for telling the unpalatable truth about them, the Delphians framed and falsely accused Aesop of stealing a sacred vessel of Apollo, then dragged him from a shrine (either of Apollo or the Muses) where he had taken sanctuary. Before they executed him, he narrated a fable of how a dung-beetle took revenge on an eagle who had killed a hare, despite the beetle's offering it protection. The humble beetle kept destroying the eagle's eggs, even on the lap of Zeus, showing that even the lowly can enact justice upon the mighty. Philokleon's deployment of the story is particularly complex, treating it as a sort of meta-fable, since he is implicitly comparing himself to Aesop who is in turn comparing himself to both the hare and the dung-beetle.Footnote 87 Scholars rightly emphasize both figures’ identification with the dung-beetle and its significance for the low, Aesopic-cum-comic ‘revenge’ that Philokleon, like Aesop, will exact.Footnote 88 However, they tend to downplay or ignore the allegorical significance of the hare. Van Dijk neatly draws the parallel between Philokleon's being hauled offstage and Aesop's being dragged from his sanctuary (implicitly, as the hare was taken from the dung-beetle's protection), but he interprets the relationship between their subsequent fates as one of incongruous contrast: ‘Aesop faces his execution, Philocleon his exit.’Footnote 89 However, when Philokleon has been characterized in successive scenes as going through the stages of life from νεανίαϲ to ἀνήρ to γέρων, and follows this by comparing himself to someone (who is in turn comparing himself to something) at the moment of their death, there is surely a strong encouragement for the audience to see this exit as a symbolic death, the conclusion of Philokleon's third lifecycle.Footnote 90

Unlike Philokleon's earlier symbolic death, defeated in three agones and declaring himself to be ‘nothing’, this death comes at a moment of total victory and, despite a temporary setback, declares that he will not only have his revenge but will live on as the dung-beetle. Ironically, it is Bdelykleon for whom this is the final exit, the theatrical death.Footnote 91 Philokleon will return for the exodos but his son will not. It is tempting to take Bdelykleon's final, exasperated cry—his last line in the play—as partially literal as well as metaphorical. Just as Aesop's dung-beetle did to the eagle and its eggs, so Philokleon with his own dung-beetles will indeed not just ‘bore to death’ (ἀπολεῖϲ, LSJ 2) but actually, albeit symbolically, ‘kill’ (LSJ 1) him. Paradoxical to the (false) end, Philokleon completes his third lifecycle with a death that involves his being carried inside not outside, like a child not a corpse, a death that ‘kills’ his killer, leaving the way clear for his return, like the dung-beetle, for a grand, comic finale.

V. Philokleon (re)redivivus Footnote 92

Following a brief and elusive choral ode (1449–73), the exodos opens in a manner strikingly similar to that following the second parabasis. Just as Xanthias there narrated Philokleon's outrageous behaviour both at the symposion and on the way home (1292–325), declaring him ‘a most baneful pest’ (ἀτηρότατον…κακόν, 1299), so the same slave here offers a briefer account of a private party that the old man has just had in the house (1474–81) and warns the audience: ‘Look! Here comes the pest’ (τουτὶ καὶ δὴ χωρεῖ τὸ κακόν, 1483). In the three iambic scenes which followed Xanthias’ earlier speech, Philokleon vanquished three antagonists in succession before facing an ambiguous struggle against his own son. In the exodos, he vanquishes in quick succession the three sons of Karkinos and then the father himself in a dance-fight.Footnote 93 The whole of the exodos can be taken as an accelerated replay of the iambic scenes. Yet while, in the earlier scenes, the complexity of Philokleon's age-status was plotted against his third lifecycle from νεανίαϲ to ἀνήρ to γέρων, here, in a fully Dionysiac dissolution of boundaries, his youth and age are paradoxically simultaneous throughout.Footnote 94 The previous iambic scenes are, then, not so much accelerated as conflated into a single assertion of Philokleon's old-young victory over his adversaries.

The careful construction of this implicit paradox over the course of the iambic scenes gives greater piquancy and significance to the explicit paradox that Xanthias, quoting Philokleon, expresses:

καὶ τοὺϲ τραγῳδούϲ φηϲιν ἀποδείξειν Κρόνουϲ
τοὺϲ νῦν διορχηϲάμενοϲ ὀλίγον ὕϲτερον.
(V. 1480f.)
And he says that a little later he'll show that the tragedians
of today are Kronoses by having a dance-fight with them.

Scholars have rightly placed great emphasis on the paradoxical nature of Philokleon's self-positioning. As Hutchinson puts it, he ‘paradoxically mixes old and young: he outdoes a younger father's sons in dancing; he champions the old tragic dances, but aims to show contemporary tragic dancers as the real Κρόνοι (1480f.).’Footnote 95 What has not been observed is how this paradoxical mixture of old and young has been developed in the preceding three scenes by Philokleon's transition through the three stages of life while maintaining (again, paradoxically) all three at once. It is in this context that the audience is fully able to appreciate the coexistence of old and new, aged and young, in Philokleon and the play that he in many ways emblematizes.Footnote 96

A great virtue of interpreting Philokleon's progress through the post-parabasis iambic scenes as a third lifecycle in which he maintains the status of old and young simultaneously is that it is compatible with and can contribute to many of the diverse interpretations—political, poetic, social, and ethical—of the final scenes and of the play as a whole. At the same time, that very compatibility means that it is less potent as a tool for privileging one interpretation over another and so does not in itself offer a key to unlocking the play's ‘meaning’, if we should want to place such restrictive shackles on this most Protean of comedies. The triumph of Philokleon over his antagonists which goes hand in hand with his ‘final, defiant inversion of the laws of transience’Footnote 97 sits less easily (though it is by no means exclusive of) what might, broadly speaking, be termed pessimistic readings that anticipate mundane repercussions for his carnivalesque behaviour,Footnote 98 or even see the final scene as ‘an impending outburst of tragic havoc’.Footnote 99 Certainly Philokleon's antisocial behaviour springs in large part from his combination of youthful recklessness and senile irresponsibility, so that, if we imagine the playwright and his audience as disapproving of or even despairing at that behaviour, then they would doubtless have held the same attitude towards its cause. The paradoxically old-young nature of Philokleon would then contribute to his status as one of the ‘characters who egotistically, almost manically, trample over their fellow citizens [and so] can hardly count for a large audience of Athenians as normatively admirable, yet the comic momentum of their behavior seems also to exclude any moralistic disapproval of them.’Footnote 100

My preference—and I must stress that the case for the third lifecycle does not stand or fall with this broader interpretation of the play—is that the audience is encouraged to support Philokleon and his old-new worldview, whether it applies to politics, poetics, or both. Whether his victory constitutes that of radical democracy made new or a modified, representative form of democracy, whether that of comedy over tragedy, tragedy over epic, Kratinos over Aristophanes, or simply Aristophanes over all-comers, Philokleon is triumphant at the end and the paradoxical coexistence of old and new, aged and young in him reflects the traditional innovation that the play endorses.Footnote 101

Footnotes

This article grew out of teaching a Greek Comedy unit on Wasps at the University of Sydney in 2019 and I am deeply indebted to all the students (John Bordon, Janek Drevikovsky, Phillip Dupesovski, Emily Kerrison, Patricia Lemaire, Theo Millar, Connie Skibinski, and Ikuko Sorensen) who made it such a stimulating experience. The Zoom audience of the Department of Classics and Ancient History's lockdown seminar in May 2020 (especially Harold Tarrant and Tom Hillard) gave helpful feedback on an oral version. I am particularly grateful to my students (Emily Kerrison and Phillip Dupesovski, again) and colleagues (Sonia Pertsinidis, Frances Muecke, and Peter Wilson), who commented on a written draft, as well as Ramus’ anonymous readers and editor, Helen Morales.

1. Menu (Reference Menu and Moreau1992), 169f.: ‘la comédie joue-t-elle constamment, à l'endroit de Bdélycléon et de Philocléon, sur les interférences, voire les inversions, entre le réel et le délire quant à l’âge et au statut des deux protagonistes: jeune / vieux, fils / père, initiateur / initié.’ See also esp. Byl (Reference Byl1977), 64f., Bowie (Reference Bowie1987), (Reference Bowie1993), 78–101, Crichton (Reference Crichton1993), Slater (Reference Slater1996), Orfanos (Reference Orfanos, Cusset and Hammout1999).

2. Rejuvenation: Whitman (Reference Whitman1964), 156–61, Vaio (Reference Vaio1971), 343, Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein1977), 268, Lenz (Reference Lenz1980), 38–40, Henderson (Reference Henderson1991), 81f., Purves (Reference Purves and Zimmermann1997), 18, Silk (Reference Silk2000), 425–9, Boulic (Reference Boulic2009), Biles (Reference Biles2016), 136, Payne (Reference Payne and Walsh2016), 13f., Farmer (Reference Farmer2017), 148, Papathanasopoulou (Reference Papathanasopoulou2019), 268 n.47, Morosi (Reference Morosi, Fries and Kanellakis2020), 119f. Dardanis: Ar. V. 1341–87, esp. 1352f.: ἐγώ ϲ' ἐπειδὰν οὑμὸϲ υἱὸϲ ἀποθάνῃ, | λυϲάμενοϲ ἕξω παλλακήν, ὦ χοιρίον. (‘I, when my son dies, will buy your freedom and have you as my concubine, my pussy.’)

3. Lenz (Reference Lenz1980), 32: ‘Der normale Hergang einer Erziehungskomödie, daß ein Alter einen im vollen Saft der Jugend stehenden Jungen erziehlich dämpfen will und nicht recht kann, ist hier in sehr komischem Rollentausch auf den Kopf gestellt.’ Zimmermann (Reference Zimmermann and Baier2007), 78: ‘Das ganze Stück…ist eingespannt in ein typisch dionysisches Grundmuster, in das Konzept der verkehrten Welt—der Sohn erzieht den Vater, der Alte übertrifft die Jungen an Vitalität’.

4. Slater (Reference Slater1996), 41: ‘Bdelycleon is now playing the father, tutoring a son who is about to attend his first symposium.’

5. Bowie (Reference Bowie1993), 81: ‘the agones…follow the normal sequence of the stages of human life, from youth to age: the first surrounds Philocleon with the imagery of youth and the ephebeia, the second sees him as a mature hoplite and the third as a juror, a job much associated with the older generation’, introducing the extended discussion from 81–93.

6. I use the term ‘iambic scenes’, sometimes called ‘episodic scenes’ (episodische Szenen, scene episodiche), throughout in the specific sense of the short, post-parabasis scenes in which the protagonist confronts and triumphs over a series of minor adversaries, and not to refer to all scenes in spoken trimeters, as in e.g. Marshall (Reference Marshall and Revermann2014). Philokleon's brief runs of trochees and iambic dimeters at 1326–31 and 1335–40 do not affect the applicability of the term. On such scenes, see Gelzer (Reference Gelzer1976), 9–11, Kaimio et al. (Reference Kaimio1990), 59–61, Grava (Reference Grava1999), Spatharas (Reference Spatharas2008), Pellegrino (Reference Pellegrino2017).

7. On exodoi in Aristophanes, see Pirrotta (Reference Pirrotta2016), Auger (Reference Auger and Faure-Ribreau2017). On that of Wasps, see section V below, with further bibliography.

8. All three passages are quoted and discussed at greater length below.

9. Cf. the more extensively subdivided list at Ar. Byz. fr. 1.12 Nauck: ὁ δὲ μετὰ ταῦτα μειράκιον ἢ μεῖραξ, εἶτα νεανίϲκοϲ, εἶτα νεανίαϲ, εἶτα ἀνὴρ μέϲοϲ, εἶτα προβεβηκώϲ, ὃν καὶ ὠμογέροντα καλοῦϲιν, γέρων, εἶτα πρεϲβύτηϲ, εἶτα ἐϲχατόγηρωϲ. (‘The person after this is a lad or boy, then a youth, then a young man, then a middle-aged man, then an old man, advanced in age, whom they also call a sprightly old man, then a senior, then one in extreme old age.’) The tripartite post-puberty sequence (with μειράκιον and πρεϲβύτηϲ in place of their respective virtual synonyms νεανίαϲ and γέρων) is preserved rather closer in time to 422 BCE at X. Smp. 4.17: ἐπεὶ ὥϲπερ γε παῖϲ γίγνεται καλόϲ, οὕτω καὶ μειράκιον καὶ ἀνὴρ καὶ πρεϲβύτηϲ. (‘[S]ince, just as a boy is beautiful, so is a lad, a man, and an old man.’) Cf. Arist. Rh. 1339a: ἡλικίαι δ᾿ εἰσὶ νεότης καὶ ἀκμὴ καὶ γῆρας (‘the times of life are youth, prime, and old age’). On the ages of Greek man, see esp. Garland (Reference Garland1990), 1–16, Davidson (Reference Davidson, Goldhill and Osborne2006).

10. Gelzer (Reference Gelzer1976), 10: ‘[Aristophanes] does not simply tack the sketches on to each other, but uses two fair-sized choral interludes…split the series up into three sections: the first (801–1057) deals with the foundation ceremony…; the second uses four messengers to give preliminary reports on the completion of the project (1118–1312); the third section then gives us a picture of the effects of this foundation on men and gods (1335–1719).’

11. Grava (Reference Grava1999), 35: ‘Gli scopi per cui queste scene giambiche sono state inserite nel tessuto drammatico manifestano una complessità superiore a quanto possa apparire a prima vista. La sezione presenta una strutturazione molto articolata, poiché essa consta di parti che rivestono ognuna più funzioni’.

12. Bowie (Reference Bowie1993), 93. Slater (Reference Slater1996), 36f. Bowie's argument that this stripping of identity puts Philokleon in the position of an ephebe ready for initiation through a rite de passage into manhood is attractive, but not directly relevant to the iambic scenes or essential for this argument. On initiation in Wasps, see also Menu (Reference Menu and Moreau1992), Jedrkiewicz (Reference Jedrkiewicz2006), 84. Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein2009b) is sceptical about initiation but not about the play with ages. On the further implications of Philokleon as οὐδέν, see Boulic (Reference Boulic2009).

13. On the significance of costume in this scene: Bowie (Reference Bowie1993), 93f., McGlew (Reference McGlew2004), 27f., Compton-Engle (Reference Compton–Engle2015), 67–74, Telò (Reference Telò2016), 27–55.

14. Silk (Reference Silk2000), 255.

15. The text of Wasps is Wilson's OCT (Reference Wilson2007); all translations are my own.

16. Sidwell (Reference Sidwell1995), 70: ‘he is (oddly) called νεανίαϲ᾽.

17. Reported at Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad loc.

18. MacDowell (Reference MacDowell1971) ad loc.: ‘Farcically, Philokleon's wild youthful behaviour has made the man believe that he is really young, despite his aged appearance.’ Similarly, Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein1983) ad loc.: ‘the victims of this riotous reveller are unaware that he is in fact an old man.’

19. Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad loc.: ‘Philocleon is acting as recklessly as young men—esp. drunk young men—were often thought to do’.

20. Van Leeuwen (Reference van Leeuwen1893) ad loc.: ‘idem quod κεἰ ϲφόδρα νεανιεύει, non enim est iuuenis senex neque ceteris esse uidetur, sed iuuenem se gerit iuueniliter lasciuiens.’

21. My translation of Lenz (Reference Lenz2014) ad loc.: ‘Die Zuschreibung von Jugend an Philokleon, die die realen Gegebenheiten verdreht, wird von Philokleon alsbald akzeptiert und in seiner Antwort fortgespielt.’

22. On anti-realism, see esp. Silk (Reference Silk2000), 212–17, Ruffell (Reference Ruffell2011). Stings: καὶ κέντρ(α) ἔχουϲιν, 420, with Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad loc.: ‘“They've actually got stingers!” …contrast 225–9, where Bdelycleon's description of the chorus’ weapons is most easily taken as metaphorical’, citing Denniston (Reference Denniston and Dover1950), 320, for the connotations of καί. Philokleon's dual, or tripartite, generational status is also paralleled in Compton-Engle's (Reference Compton–Engle2015) analysis, 128f., of ‘the duality between human chorus member and animal costume…in Wasps, where both the human and the animal qualities of the wasp chorus are kept operative throughout the play.’ The Dog's speech (with interruptions): 907–30.

23. Bowie (Reference Bowie1993), 95.

24. Hutchinson (Reference Hutchinson2011), 67.

25. On the issue of Philokleon's cure, see esp. Sidwell (Reference Sidwell1990), Ruffell (Reference Ruffell2018). On the interrelatedness of juror and old man: Bowie (Reference Bowie1993), 81.

26. Starkie (Reference Starkie1897) ad loc. Cf. Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein1983) ad loc.

27. Cf. Biles (Reference Biles2016), 134: ‘Philocleon's violence and verbal abuse of innocent victims in the streets emphasizes his renouncement of the law courts. This point is impressed on us at the scene's outset when the old man brushes off legal threats and even scoffs at symbols of the courtroom he had idolized so recently’.

28. For the nuances of αἰβοῖ here and elsewhere in Aristophanes, see Levine (Reference Levine, Lateiner and Spatharas2016), esp. 94: ‘The old man used to love lawsuits, but in his current frame of mind the idea of them is disgusting. This expletive shows how completely the old man has changed from loving lawsuits to detesting them.’

29. MacDowell (Reference MacDowell1971) ad loc.

30. Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad loc. catch the double sense but see the reference to Philokleon's status as primary: ‘The point is not just that Philocleon is no longer one himself, but that no legal aid is available to protect his victims.’

31. Slater (Reference Slater1996), 42, notes further how βάλλε κημούϲ (‘to hell with voting urns’, 1339) contrasts with Philokleon's erotic graffiti in praise of voting urns at 99.

32. On Philokleon as recreative-discontinuous character: Silk (Reference Silk2000), 246–55.

33. Rusten (Reference Rusten1977), 160.

34. Vaio (Reference Vaio1971), 344 n.41: ‘Wine releases new energy and permits the re-enactment of some youthful tricks, but the bitter reality is visible to all, and much of Philocleon's boasting must be interpreted as humorous because incongruous with the real state of affairs.’ Cf. Rothwell (Reference Rothwell2019), 11: ‘it may be that Philocleon is a self-deluded alazon when it comes to his own potency, because it is entirely possible that the audience could see the old man's limp, dangling phallus.’

35. Sonia Pertsinidis (per litt.) notes the contrast with Theophrastos’ ὀψιμαθήϲ (‘late-learner’, Char. 27), where the humour and absurdity arise from the old man's failed attempts to act like a youth, most relevantly in his komastic assault on a hetaira's door (27.9). Notably, there it is the old man who is beaten up and who then summons his rival to court.

36. Crichton (Reference Crichton1993), 68.

37. On the slave–master reversal here, see Segal (Reference Segal1987), 113f., Moore (Reference Moore2011), 113, Richlin (Reference Richlin2017), 210f.

39. The examples are intended to convey the sense of what Aristophanes could have written, but of course some recasting of word order or diction would be required to render the phrases metrical.

40. Kaimio et al. (Reference Kaimio1990), 61: ‘[Philokleon] makes fun of the lessons of civilized conversation given to him by his son…and tells the story of the victorious old pancratiast while punching his son to the ground’.

41. Slater (Reference Slater1996), 42: ‘Striking his adult son is startling even by Greek standards, but there is an added frisson in that Philocleon has portrayed himself as the son: he has become in effect another Pheidippides…, a πατραλοίαϲ beating his own father.’

42. I follow Wilson (Reference Wilson2007) in printing Dobree's conjecture τεττάρων for the MS τέτταρας and translating ἐπιθήκη accordingly. However, retaining the paradosis and translating ‘four loaves in addition’ (with MacDowell [Reference MacDowell1971] and Biles and Olson [Reference Biles and Olson2015]) would not affect the argument.

43. Bowie (Reference Bowie1993), 86f. It is worth noting, though Bowie does not draw attention to it, that forms of ἀνήρ are also used in that earlier scene to emphasize the status of the ‘combatants’: the slaves as ‘hoplite men’ keeping watch at the ‘passes’ (ἄνδρεϲ ὁπλῖται, 360), Philokleon acting ‘like a man’ when he decides to gnaw through the net (ταῦτα μὲν πρὸϲ ἀνδρόϲ, 369), the chorus demanding that Xanthias let ‘the man’ go on pain of violent attack (τὸν ἄνδρ᾽, 428).

44. Cf. Roisman (Reference Roisman2005), 11: ‘From the age of thirty on, free adult males stood at the pinnacle of the social and political hierarchy of Athens; younger adults ranked lower, as did older men.’

45. D.L. 1.33: πρῶτον μὲν ὅτι ἄνθρωποϲ ἐγενόμην καὶ οὐ θηρίον, εἶτα ὅτι ἀνὴρ καὶ οὐ γυνή, τρίτον ὅτι Ἕλλην καὶ οὐ βάρβαροϲ. (‘First, that I was born a human being and not a beast, then that I was born as man and not a woman, and third that I was born a Greek and not a barbarian.’)

46. Cawthorn (Reference Cawthorn2008), 96: ‘The ephebe has only recently separated from the feminine (in both the form of the maternal and the feminine within, since the child, pais, is considered feminine in this culture).’ Beaumont (Reference Beaumont and Derevenski2000), 47: ‘By the time he attained his twentieth year, the young male was certainly in biological terms, and in many civic and legal respects, regarded as a man. Nevertheless, in certain civic aspects and in social terms, he was not deemed to have passed completely through the dangerous liminal developmental stage of youth until he was 30.’

47. Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad loc. and cf. Macdowell (1972) ad loc., Willi (Reference Willi2003), 189, all comparing Ec. 155–8.

48. Wilson (Reference Wilson2007) prints Richards’ conjecture γενομένηϲ for the MS θυγατέροϲ, but the rarity of the form is insufficient grounds for emendation and γενομένηϲ is colourless. Nevertheless, the following argument still stands if γενομένηϲ is printed.

49. Kloss (Reference Kloss2001), 108f., identifies the incongruity (‘unpassend’) of Myrtia's form of self-introduction but stresses its association with social class (‘Myrtia darf sich ihrer unbedeutenden Herkunft rühmen’) rather than civic status. This is certainly part of the picture but by no means all.

50. Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein2009c), 44–6.

51. Husband: Austin and Olson (Reference Austin and Olson2004) ad loc. Father: Zeitlin (Reference Zeitlin and Foley1981), 187, Silk (Reference Silk2000), 284, Kanavou (Reference Kanavou2011), 148. Willi (Reference Willi2003), 170, and Sidwell (Reference Sidwell2009), 274, allow for either possibility.

52. Austin and Olson (Reference Austin and Olson2004) ad loc. Pace Willi (Reference Willi2003), 170, ‘[t]he complete naming pattern for a woman consists of her first name, her husband's (or father's) name in the genitive, and the deme to which she belongs through her husband (or father): for instance, Κρίτυλλά γ᾿ Ἀντιθέου Γαργηττόθεν’, this is not a representative example but the only instance where an Aristophanic woman includes the deme; all others have only the husband's or father's name.

53. Lenz (Reference Lenz2014) ad loc.: ‘Mit der Nennung beider Eltern gibt sie zu verstehen, dass sie Vollbürgerin ist und Rechte geltend machen kann.’ Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein1983) ad loc.: ‘Myrtia names both her parents to prove that she is a citizen, not lightly to be insulted or injured.’

54. e.g. Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad 1408: ‘why he in particular accompanies Myrtia in preparation for serving as her witness in court is unclear.’

55. On P.Oxy. 5131, see esp. Finglass (Reference Finglass2014) and (Reference Finglass, Kyriakou and Rengakos2016).

56. Taaffe (Reference Taafe1993), 37. Cf. Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein1983) ad 1413: ‘the point is that with such a complexion he might be thought to be a woman, in which case he would not be allowed to give evidence in court of the serving of the summons’.

57. Denniston (Reference Denniston and Dover1950), 207: ‘Particularly in the case of σύ (especially in questions), the emphasis is often ironical, contemptuous, or indignant in tone.’

58. Pertsinidis (Reference Pertsinidis2009), 213: ‘Bdelykleon explicitly advises Philokleon to tell fables in order to amuse and pacify any potential complainant’.

59. Cf. Jedrkiewicz (Reference Jedrkiewicz2006), 82: ‘Ad uso di questi interlocutori furibondi, il vecchio riesce ad usare i geloia esopici e sibaritici in modo perfettamente rovesciato: invece di ammansire, esaspera ancor di più.’ Biles (Reference Biles2016), 135: ‘Philocleon throughout the later scenes demonstrates his mastery of the verbal strategies of the intellectual elite…with the difference that he deploys them according to his own rules, in blatant disregard for all social conventions and fears of repercussions.’ Halliwell (Reference Halliwell, Rosen and Foley2020), 126: ‘Bdelykleon…is someone who wants to avoid or defuse conflict. But this only cues his reprobate father to borrow and parody his son's impulse to appeasement for his own sarcastic purposes.’ Similarly Zanetto (Reference Zanetto, Cavarzere, Aloni and Barchiesi2001), 68f. Contra Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad 1258–61: ‘Philocleon's own clumsy attempt to put Bdelycleon's advice into practice (1393–1414, 1427–41), only exacerbates his troubles.’ Sonia Pertsinidis (per litt.) suggests that the close connection of fable to iambos may contribute to Philokleon's aggressive deployment of them. Cf. Zanetto (Reference Zanetto, Cavarzere, Aloni and Barchiesi2001), 68–70, on iambos and Aesopic tales in this scene and, on the connection more broadly, Hawkins (Reference Hawkins2014), 89–93.

60. Van Dijk (Reference van Dijk1997), 190f.

61. Animals and the Aesopic in Wasps: Whitman (Reference Whitman1964), 162–5, Rothwell (Reference Rothwell1995), Kloss (Reference Kloss2001), 106–15, Jedrkiewicz (Reference Jedrkiewicz2006), Pertsinidis (Reference Pertsinidis2009), Schirru (Reference Schirru2009), 56–70, Hall (Reference Hall2013), 289–94, Payne (Reference Payne and Walsh2016), Miles (Reference Miles, Fögen and Thomas2017).

62. The appendix of animal-related jokes and references in the play at Miles (Reference Miles, Fögen and Thomas2017), 226–9, is a useful resource, to which I am indebted.

64. Reckford (Reference Reckford1987), 276.

65. Van Dijk (Reference van Dijk1997), 191: ‘Aesop's réplique finale clearly applies to the bread seller, not to the bitch.’

66. Franco (Reference Franco and Fox2014), 159.

67. Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad loc. are correct that ὕβρεωϲ is ‘placed emphatically at the head of the line to emphasize the gravity of the matter’, but its incongruity is emphasized alongside its gravity and the surprise, verging on para prosdokian, intensified by the enjambment.

68. On the connection of youth and hybris, see Dover (Reference Dover1974), 103, MacDowell (Reference MacDowell1976), 15, Fisher (Reference Fisher1992), esp. 97–9 (citing this fragment at 97), and index s.v. ‘youth’, Cairns (Reference Cairns1996), 24f., 31. Note esp. Fisher (Reference Fisher1992), 97: ‘The terms specifically formed to denote behaviour characteristic of youth, neanikos and neanikeuesthai, are often found in association with hybris, indicating such violent, thoughtless and reckless behaviour that harms and insults others’. On the motif in tragedy, see Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein, Markantonatos and Zimmermann2012), Shipton (Reference Shipton2018), 47–9, 54f.

69. Austin and Olson (Reference Austin and Olson2004) ad loc., italics original.

70. With Biles-Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad loc.: ‘“vigorously”…but also anticipating the rejuvenating effect Philocleon's immersion in the symposium has on him’.

71. MacDowell (Reference MacDowell1976), 15.

72. D. 54.1, 2, 11, 13, 24, 37, in addition to fourteen instances of ὑβρίζω and one of ὑβριϲτήϲ. The thirty-seven instances and ninety-four of its cognates in D. 21 are catalogued and discussed in Rowe (Reference Rowe1993).

73. Similarly, Konon's cronies, although ‘grey-haired’ (ἐπιπόλιον), bandy ‘young-men's talk’ (νεανικά) about perjuring themselves over acts of ὕβριϲ (D. 54.34f.).

74. The seriousness of the charge and its penalties is the other trigger for Bdelykleon's reaction, as commentators note.

75. On ὕβριϲ in Aristophanes, see Thiercy (Reference Thiercy2007).

76. On the ϲωφροϲύνη of old age: Pl. Leg. 691e, Arist. Rh. 1390b, and cf. E. fr. 619. On ϲωφροσύνη in the play as a whole, and in particular Philokleon's lack of it, see Kanavou (Reference Kanavou2016).

77. On Philokleon's Sybarite tales, see van Dijk (Reference van Dijk1997), 191–4, Kloss (Reference Kloss2001), 111–14, Pertsinidis (Reference Pertsinidis2009), 214f., Schirru (Reference Schirru2009), 156–65.

78. Kaimio et al. (Reference Kaimio1990), 61: ‘he…tells the story of the victorious old pancratiast while punching his son to the ground…and a Sybaritan story of the breaking of a vase…when smashing the man calling him to court’.

79. Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad loc. assign 1433 to the accuser, so that ‘what he means is “This too is hybris”’, with no reference to Philokleon's other actions, of which he has no knowledge. Though this would lack the pointedness of having Bdelykleon's evoking his father's consistently νεανικόϲ behaviour despite his symbolic aging across the three iambic scenes, it nevertheless stresses the continuity of his youthful status despite his apparent senescence within this final scene.

80. Definition from Biles and Olson (Reference Biles and Olson2015) ad 133–5.

81. Collard and Cropp (Reference Collard and Cropp2009), 61.

82. There is some uncertainty as to whether Athenaios (to whom we owe this fragment) has altered the rest of the quotation to make the speaker claim that ‘dying at the same time as fucking’ (ἀποθανεῖν βινοῦνθ᾿ ἅμα, 13.27) is or is not the sweetest thing, but this does not affect the general import of the opening imperative.

83. Auger (Reference Auger, Auger and Peigney2008), 513: ‘Conformément au schéma rituel, l'initié meurt métaphoriquement à son ancienne vie pour renaître dans la nouvelle.’ Without the initiatory associations, Reckford (Reference Reckford1977), 297: ‘[H]e has lost his identity. It is a kind of death.’ Jedrkiewicz (Reference Jedrkiewicz2006), 70, argues for two paratragic ‘morti in scena’, at 752–7 and 997.

84. Cf. Crane (Reference Crane and Dobrov1997), 223: ‘[Bdelycleon] is left in the same position that he occupied at the opening of the play, as his father's jailer, desperately holding Philocleon within the limits of the oikos.’

85. Hutchinson (Reference Hutchinson2011), 67: ‘he physically carries him against his will, as if he were a child.’

86. On Philokleon's use of the story: Rothwell (Reference Rothwell1995), 253, van Dijk (Reference van Dijk1997), 194–7, Kloss (Reference Kloss2001), 113, Jedrkiewicz (Reference Jedrkiewicz2006), 82, Pertsinidis (Reference Pertsinidis2009), 215f., Schirru (Reference Schirru2009), 95–9, Hall (Reference Hall2013), 292f.

87. Hall (Reference Hall2013), 293: ‘There are therefore no fewer than three parallel stories of subversion of superior authority going on here—Philocleon is challenging his upwardly mobile son, as Aesop challenged the Delphians, and the dung-beetle challenged both the eagle and Zeus’, though she omits that Aesop (and Philokleon) are both also the hare, the victim of the eagle's initial violent injustice.

88. Esp. Jedrkiewicz (Reference Jedrkiewicz2006), 82: ‘si riafferma come narratore σκαιός in senso letterale, ossia dal repertorio scatologico: lo scarabeo ottiene giustizia bombardando di escrementi Zeus.’

89. Van Dijk (Reference van Dijk1997), 196f., quoting from 197, with original emphasis.

90. Schirru (Reference Schirru2009), 98f., does situate the parallelism with Aesop's death within ‘una serie di segni “premonitori”’of Philokleon's paratragic ‘death’ throughout the play, but sees the latter not as symbolic, but as one of the ‘esagerazioni del vecchio’ and ‘il “triste fato” dell'eroe comico’ as ‘parodia di quello di tanti protagonisti del teatro tragico.’

91. Cf. Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein2009b), 198: ‘That sequence ends with Philokleon being carried off-stage, kicking and screaming, by his son—but it is the son who then vanishes from the play’.

92. Alluding to Bowie (Reference Bowie1993), 93.

93. Payne's suggestion (Reference Payne and Walsh2016), 141, that ‘this dance-off turns out to be not agonistic after all, but an enactment of the integration of new and old that P[hilo]Cleon embodies in his own person’ is humane and attractive, but while it is true that Philokleon and the sons of Karkinos do seem to dance together, both in the orkhestra and in procession offstage, there is still a strong sense of a victory being achieved, albeit a benign, inclusive one that incorporates rather than excludes one's opponents.

94. On the Dionysiac in the exodos: Vaio (Reference Vaio1971), 351, Reckford (Reference Reckford1977), 302, MacCary (Reference MacCary1979), 141f., Konstan (Reference Konstan1985), 44, Menu (Reference Menu and Moreau1992), 177f., Slater (Reference Slater1996), 44–9, Sommerstein (Reference Sommerstein2009b), 198–202, Biles (Reference Biles2016), 135f., Farmer (Reference Farmer2017), 147–53.

95. Hutchinson (Reference Hutchinson2011), 67. Cf. Lenz (Reference Lenz1980), 39, Auger (Reference Auger, Auger and Peigney2008), 501, Wright (Reference Wright2013), 222, Farmer (Reference Farmer2017), 148.

96. Cf. Biles (Reference Biles2016), 136: ‘As a proponent of the play's poetics, Philocleon simultaneously—and paradoxically—embodies the traditional in his fondness for old poets and experimentalism in the novel forms of comic entertainment that nonetheless result from his predilections.’

97. Silk (Reference Silk2000), 428.

98. Henderson (Reference Henderson1991), 82: ‘beyond the wild, reeling dance of life with which Philocleon ends the play, await a hangover, court appearances, and fines for damages.’

99. Telò (Reference Telò2016), 109. Cf. Pirotta (2016), 47: ‘Aristophanes seems to deal with Athens's hopeless political situation in the Wasps…it is quite obvious that this final scene of the Wasps cannot be read as a happy ending’.

100. Halliwell (Reference Halliwell, Rosen and Foley2020), 128. Cf. Nelson (Reference Nelson2016), 173f.: ‘the qualities that make him attractive are exactly the ones that would be condemned anywhere except on the comic stage.’

101. Radical democracy: Hubbard (Reference Hubbard, Falkner and De Luce1989), 91; representative democracy: Olson (Reference Olson1996); comedy over tragedy: Wright (Reference Wright2013), Farmer (Reference Farmer2017), 117–53; comedy over epic and tragedy: Papathanasopoulou (Reference Papathanasopoulou2019); Kratinos: Biles (Reference Biles2011), 134–66; Aristophanes over Kratinos and Eupolis: Sidwell (Reference Sidwell1995), (Reference Sidwell2009), 69–75, 178–99. In general, Morosi (Reference Morosi, Fries and Kanellakis2020), 115: ‘Philocleon…is fighting an unnatural war against linear time and would do anything to avoid the succession…however… Philocleon's irrational fight will end in triumph.’

References

Auger, D. (2008), ‘Corps perdu et retrouvé dans les Guêpes d'Aristophane’, in Auger, D. and Peigney, J. (eds), Φιλευριπίδης = Phileuripidès: mélanges offerts à François Jouan (Nanterre), 503–28.Google Scholar
Auger, D. (2017), ‘Les dénouements dans le théâtre d'Aristophane’, in Faure-Ribreau, M. (ed.), Plaute et Aristophane: Confrontations (Paris), 183200.Google Scholar
Austin, C., and Olson, S.D. (eds) (2004), Aristophanes: Thesmophoriazusae (Oxford).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bakola, E., Prauscello, L., and Telò, M. (eds) (2013), Greek Comedy and the Discourse of Genres (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaumont, L. (2000), ‘The Social Status and Artistic Presentation of “Adolescence” in Fifth-Century Athens’, in Derevenski, J.S. (ed.), Children and Material Culture (London), 3950.Google Scholar
Biles, Z.P. (2011), Aristophanes and the Poetics of Competition (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biles, Z.P. (2016), ‘Thucydides’ Cleon and the Poetics of Politics in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, CPh 111, 117–38.Google Scholar
Biles, Z.P., and Olson, S.D. (eds) (2015), Aristophanes: Wasps (Oxford).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boulic, N. (2009), ‘“On m'appelle Outis”: une impuissance dérangeante chez Homère et Aristophane’, Gaia 12, 153–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowie, A.M. (1987), ‘Ritual Stereotype and Comic Reversal: Aristophanes’ Wasps’, BICS 34, 112–25.Google Scholar
Bowie, A.M. (1993), Aristophanes. Myth, Ritual, and Comedy (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byl, S. (1977), ‘Le vieillard dans les comédies d'Aristophane’, AC 46, 5273.Google Scholar
Cairns, D.L. (1996), ‘Hybris, Dishonour, and Thinking Big’, JHS 116, 132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cawthorn, K. (2008), Becoming Female: The Male Body in Greek Tragedy (London).Google Scholar
Collard, C., and Cropp, M. (eds) (2009), Euripides: Fragments: Oedipus-Chrysippus. Other Fragments (Cambridge, MA).Google Scholar
Compton–Engle, G. (2015), Costume in the Comedies of Aristophanes (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, G. (1997), ‘Oikos and Agora: Mapping the Polis in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, in Dobrov, G. (ed.), The City as Comedy: Society and Representation in Athenian Drama (Chapel Hill), 198229.Google Scholar
Crichton, A. (1993), ‘“The Old Are in a Second Childhood”: Age Reversal and Jury Service in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, BICS 38, 5980.Google Scholar
Davidson, J. (2006), ‘Revolutions in Human Time. Age-Class in Athens and the Greekness of Greek Revolutions’, in Goldhill, S. and Osborne, R. (eds), Rethinking Revolutions through Ancient Greece (Cambridge), 2967.Google Scholar
Denniston, J.D. (1950), The Greek Particles, second edition, rev. Dover, K.J. (Oxford).Google Scholar
Dover, K.J. (1974), Greek Popular Morality in the Time of Plato and Aristotle (Oxford).Google Scholar
Farmer, M.C. (2017), Tragedy on the Comic Stage (Oxford).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finglass, P. (2014), ‘A New Fragment of Euripides’ Ino’, ZPE 189, 6582.Google Scholar
Finglass, P. (2016), ‘Mistaken Identity in Euripides’ Ino’, in Kyriakou, P. and Rengakos, A. (eds), Wisdom and Folly in Euripides (Berlin and Boston), 299315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, N.R.E. (1992), Hybris: A Study in the Values of Honour and Shame in Ancient Greece (Warminster).Google Scholar
Franco, C. (2014), Shameless: The Canine and the Feminine in Ancient Greece, tr. Fox, M. (Berkeley) [orig. publ. 2003].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garland, R. (1990), The Greek Way of Life: From Conception to Old Age (London).Google Scholar
Gelzer, T. (1976), ‘Some Aspects of Aristophanes’ Dramatic Art in the Birds’, BICS 23, 114.Google Scholar
Grava, S. (1999), ‘I mercanti in scena. Scene episodiche negli Acarnesi di Aristofane’, Patavium 13, 1746.Google Scholar
Hall, E. (2013), ‘The Aesopic in Aristophanes’, in Bakola et al. (2013), 277–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halliwell, S. (2020), ‘Politics in the Street: Some Citizen Encounters in Aristophanes’, in Rosen, R.M. and Foley, H.P. (eds), Aristophanes and Politics: New Studies (Leiden), 113–36.Google Scholar
Hawkins, T. (2014), Iambic Poetics in the Roman Empire (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henderson, J. (1991), The Maculate Muse: Obscene Language in Attic Comedy, second edition (Oxford) [orig. publ. 1975].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hubbard, T.K. (1989), ‘Old Men in the Youthful Plays of Aristophanes’, in Falkner, T.M. and De Luce, J. (eds), Old Age in Greek and Latin Literature (Albany), 90113.Google Scholar
Hutchinson, G.O. (2011), ‘House Politics and City Politics in Aristophanes’, CQ 61, 4870.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jedrkiewicz, S. (2006), ‘Bestie, gesti e logos. Una lettura delle Vespe di Aristofane’, QUCC 82, 6191.Google Scholar
Kaimio, M., et al. (1990), ‘Comic Violence in Aristophanes’, Arctos 40, 4772.Google Scholar
Kanavou, N. (2011), Aristophanes’ Comedy of Names: A Study of Speaking Names in Aristophanes (Berlin).Google Scholar
Kanavou, N. (2016), ‘Sōphrosynē and Justice in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, G&R 63, 175–91.Google Scholar
Kloss, G. (2001), Erscheinungsformen komischen Sprechens bei Aristophanes (Berlin and New York).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Konstan, D. (1985), ‘The Politics of Aristophanes’ Wasps’, TAPA 115, 2746.Google Scholar
Konstan, D. (2014), ‘Turns and Returns in Plautus’ Casina’, in Perysinakis, N. and Karakasis, E. (eds), Plautine Trends, Studies in Plautine Comedy and its Reception (Berlin), 311.Google Scholar
Lenz, L. (1980), ‘Komik und Kritik in Aristophanes’ Wespen’, Hermes 108, 1544.Google Scholar
Lenz, L. (ed.) (2014), Aristophanes: Wespen (Berlin).Google Scholar
Levine, D.B. (2016), ‘Disgust and Delight: The Polysemous Exclamation αἰβοῖ in Attic Comedy’, in Lateiner, D. and Spatharas, D. (eds), The Ancient Emotion of Disgust (Oxford), 87102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacCary, W.T. (1979), ‘Philokleon Ithyphallos: Dance, Costume, and Character in the Wasps’, TAPA 109, 137–47.Google Scholar
MacDowell, D.M. (ed.) (1971), Aristophanes: Wasps (Oxford).Google Scholar
MacDowell, D.M. (1976), ‘Hybris in Athens’, G&R 23, 1431.Google Scholar
McGlew, J. (2004), ‘“Speak on my Behalf”: Persuasion and Purification in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, Arethusa 37, 1136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marshall, C.W. (2014), ‘Dramatic Technique and Athenian Comedy’, in Revermann, M. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Greek Comedy (Cambridge), 131–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menu, M. (1992), ‘Philocléon: une initiation de la vieillesse dans les comédies d'Aristophane’, in Moreau, A. (ed.), L'initiation (Montpellier), 165–84.Google Scholar
Miles, S. (2017), ‘Cultured Animals and Wild Humans? Talking with the Animals in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, in Fögen, T. and Thomas, E. (eds), Interactions between Animals and Humans in Graeco-Roman Antiquity (Berlin), 205–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, T.J. (2011), Music in Roman Comedy (Cambridge).Google Scholar
Morosi, F. (2020), ‘Fathers and Sons in Clouds and Wasps’, in Fries, A. and Kanellakis, D. (eds), Ancient Greek Comedy: Genre—Texts—Reception (Berlin), 111–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, S. (2016), Aristophanes and His Tragic Muse: Comedy, Tragedy and the Polis in 5th Century Athens (Leiden).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olson, S.D. (1996), ‘Politics and Poetry in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, TAPA 126, 129–50.Google Scholar
Orfanos, C. (1999), ‘Philocleon palimpais, in Cusset, C. and Hammout, M. (eds), Politique, société, et comédie (Toulouse), 97110.Google Scholar
Papathanasopoulou, N. (2019), ‘Tragic and Epic Visions of the oikos in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, CW 112, 253–78.Google Scholar
Payne, M. (2016), ‘Teknomajikality and the Humanimal in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, in Walsh, P. (ed.), Brill's Companion to the Reception of Aristophanes (Leiden), 129–47.Google Scholar
Pellegrino, M. (2017), ‘The Sycophant in Episodic Scenes of Aristophanic Comedy’, Polis 34, 405–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pertsinidis, S. (2009), ‘The Fabulist Aristophanes’, Fabula 50, 208–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pirrotta, S. (2016), ‘Triumph of Hilarity? Some Reflections on the Structure and Function of the Final Scenes in Aristophanic Comedy’, TiC 8, 3354.Google Scholar
Purves, A. (1997), ‘Empowerment for the Athenian Citizen: Philocleon as Actor and Spectator in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, in Zimmermann, B. (ed.), Griechisch-römische Komödie und Tragödie (Stuttgart), 522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reckford, K.J. (1977), ‘Catharsis and Dream-Interpretation in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, TAPA 107, 283312.Google Scholar
Reckford, K.J. (1987), Aristophanes’ Old-and-New Comedy. Volume I: Six Essays in Perspective (Chapel Hill).Google Scholar
Richlin, A. (2017), Slave Theater in the Roman Republic: Plautus and Popular Comedy (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roisman, J. (2005), The Rhetoric of Manhood: Masculinity in the Attic Orators (Berkeley).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rothwell, K.S. (1995), ‘Aristophanes’ Wasps and the Sociopolitics of Aesop's Fables’, CJ 90, 233–54.Google Scholar
Rothwell, K.S. (ed.) (2019), Aristophanes: Wasps (Oxford).Google Scholar
Rowe, G.O. (1993), ‘The Many Facets of Hybris in Demosthenes' Against Meidias’, AJP 114, 397406.Google Scholar
Ruffell, I. (2011), Politics and Anti-Realism in Athenian Old Comedy: The Art of the Impossible (Oxford).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruffell, I. (2018), ‘Stop Making Sense, The Politics of Aristophanic Madness’, ICS 43, 326–50.Google Scholar
Rusten, J.S. (1977), ‘Wasps 1360–1369: Philokleon's τωθασμός’, HSCP 81, 157–61.Google Scholar
Schirru, S. (2009), La Favola in Aristofane (Berlin).Google Scholar
Segal, E. (1987), Roman Laughter, second edition (Oxford) [orig. publ. 1968].Google Scholar
Shipton, M. (2018), The Politics of Youth in Greek Tragedy: Gangs of Athens (London).Google Scholar
Sidwell, K. (1990), ‘Was Philokleon cured? The νόσος Theme in Aristophanes’ Wasps’, C&M 41, 931.Google Scholar
Sidwell, K. (1995), ‘Poetic Rivalry and the Caricature of Comic Poets: Cratinus’ Pytine and Aristophanes’ Wasps’, BICS 66, 5680.Google Scholar
Sidwell, K. (2009), Aristophanes the Democrat: The Politics of Satirical Comedy during the Peloponnesian War (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Silk, M.S. (2000), Aristophanes and the Definition of Comedy (Oxford).Google Scholar
Slater, N.W. (1996), ‘Bringing up Father: Paideia and Ephebeia in the Wasps’, in Sommerstein and Atherton (1996), 27–52, reprinted in N.W. Slater (2002), Spectator Politics: Metatheatre and Performance in Aristophanes (Philadelphia), 86114.Google Scholar
Sommerstein, A.H. (1977), ‘Notes on Aristophanes Wasps’, CQ 27, 261–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommerstein, A.H. (ed.) (1983), Aristophanes: Wasps (Warminster).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommerstein, A.H. (2009a), Talking About Laughter and Other Studies in Greek Comedy (Oxford).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommerstein, A.H. (2009b), ‘Response to Slater, “Bringing up Father: Paideia and Ephebeia in the Wasps”’, in Sommerstein (2009a), 192–203 [orig. publ. 1996: Sommerstein and Atherton, 53–64].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommerstein, A.H. (2009c), ‘The Naming of Women in Greek and Roman Comedy’, in Sommerstein (2009a), 43–64 [orig. publ. 1980: Quaderni di Storia 11, 393–418].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommerstein, A.H. (2012), ‘Problem Kids: Young Males and Society from Electra to Bacchae, in Markantonatos, A. and Zimmermann, B. (eds), Crisis on Stage: Tragedy and Comedy in Late Fifth-Century Athens (Berlin), 343–57.Google Scholar
Sommerstein, A.H., and Atherton, C. (eds) (1996), Education in Greek Fiction (Bari).Google Scholar
Spatharas, D. (2008), ‘ταυ̑τ’ ἐγὼ μαρτὐρομαι: Bystanders as Witnesses in Aristophanes’, Mnemosyne 61, 177–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Starkie, W.J.M. (1897), Σφῆκες Ἀριστοφάνους: the Wasps of Aristophanes, with Introduction, Metrical Analysis, Critical Notes, and Commentary (London).Google Scholar
Taafe, L. (1993), Aristophanes and Women (New York).Google Scholar
Telò, M. (2016), Aristophanes and the Cloak of Comedy: Affect, Aesthetics, and the Canon (Chicago).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thiercy, P. (2007), ‘L’ὕβρις chez Aristophane’, Kentron 23, 179–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vaio, J. (1971), ‘Aristophanes’ Wasps. The Relevance of the Final Scenes’, GRBS 12, 335–51.Google Scholar
van Dijk, G.-J. (1997), Ainoi, logoi, mythoi: Fables in Archaic, Classical, and Hellenistic Greek Literature, with a Study of the Theory and Terminology of the Genre (Leiden).Google Scholar
van Leeuwen, J. (ed.) (1893), Aristophanis Vespae. Cum prolegomenis et commentariis (Leiden).Google Scholar
Whitman, C.H. (1964), Aristophanes and the Comic Hero (Cambridge MA).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willi, A. (2003), The Languages of Aristophanes: Aspects of Linguistic Variation in Classical Attic Greek (Oxford).Google Scholar
Wilson, N.G. (ed.) (2007), Aristophanis: Fabulae, Vol. 1: Acharnenses; Equites; Nubes; Vespae; Pax; Aves (Oxford).Google Scholar
Wright, M. (2013), ‘Comedy versus Tragedy in Wasps’, in Bakola et al. (2013), 205–25.Google Scholar
Zanetto, G. (2001), ‘Iambic Patterns in Aristophanic Comedy’, in Cavarzere, A., Aloni, A., and Barchiesi, A. (eds), Iambic Ideas: Essays on a Poetic Tradition from Archaic Greece to the Late Roman Empire (Lanham MA), 6576.Google Scholar
Zeitlin, F.I. (1981), ‘Travesties of Gender and Genre in Aristophanes’ Thesmophoriazousae’, in Foley, H.P. (ed.), Reflections of Women in Antiquity (New York), 169217.Google Scholar
Zimmermann, B. (2007), ‘Väter und Söhne: Generationenkonflikt in den Wolken und Wespen des Aristophanes’, in Baier, T. (ed.), Generationenkonflikte auf der Bühne: Perspektiven im antiken und mittelalterlichen Drama (Tübingen), 7381.Google Scholar