Article contents
Optimal Deterrence*
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 13 January 2009
Extract
1. Introduction
The policy of deterrence, at least to avert nuclear war between the superpowers, has been a controversial one. The main controversy arises from the threat of each side to visit destruction on the other in response to an initial attack. This threat would seem irrational if carrying it out would lead to a nuclear holocaust – the worst outcome for both sides. Instead, it would seem better for the side attacked to suffer some destruction rather than to retaliate in kind and, in the process of devastating the other side, seal its own doom in an all-out nuclear exchange.
Yet, the superpowers persist in their adherence to deterrence, by which we mean a policy of threatening to retaliate to an attack by the other side in order to deter such an attack in the first place. To be sure, nuclear doctrine for implementing deterrence has evolved over the years, with such appellations as “massive retaliation,” “flexible response,” “mutual assured destruction” (MAD), and “counterforce” giving some flavor of the changes in United States strategic thinking.
All such doctrines, however, entail some kind of response to a Soviet nuclear attack. They are operationalized in terms of preselected targets to be hit, depending on the perceived nature and magnitude of the attack. Thus, whether U.S. strategic policy at any time stresses a retaliatory attack on cities and industrial centers (countervalue) or on weapons systems and armed forces (counterforce), the certainty of a response of some kind to an attack is not the issue.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1985
References
1 Brams, Steven J., Superpower Games: Applying Game Theory to Superpower Conflict (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1985)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, chaps. 1 and 2.
2 Brams, Steven J. and Wittman, Donald, “Nonmyopic Equilibria in 2 × 2 Games,” Conflict Management and Peace Science, vol.6 (Fall 1981), pp.39–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kilgour, D. Marc, “Equilibria for Far-sighted Players,” Theory and Decision, vol.16 (March 1984), pp. 135–157CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Zagare, Frank C., “Limited-Move Equilibria in 2 × 2 Games,” Theory and Decision, vol.16 (January 1984), pp.1–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
3 Brams, Steven J. and Hessel, Marek P., “Threat Power in Sequential Games,” International Studies Quarterly, vol.28 (March 1984), pp. 15–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
4 ibid.; the original distinction between compellent and deterrent threats is due to Schelling, Thomas C., Arms and Influence (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1966).Google Scholar
5 The validity of the symmetry condition in the context of Soviet-American conflict is supported by the following statement of an authority on Soviet defense policy: “The answers [to the problems posed by nuclear war and nuclear weapons] the Soviet leaders have arrived at are not very different from those given by Western governments … The Soviet Union has not been able to escape from the threat of nuclear annihilation. Its leaders and its people share our predicament.” Holloway, David, The Soviet Union and the Arms Race (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983), p.182.Google Scholar
6 For debate on this point, see Frank C. Zagare, “Toward a Reformulation of the Theory of Mutual Deterrence,” International Studies Quarterly, vol. 29 (June 1985); Brams and Hessel, “Threat Power in Sequential Games”; and Brams, Superpower Games, Chap.l.
7 Selten, Reinhard, “Reexamination of the Perfectness Concept for Equilibrium Points in Extensive Games,” International Journal of Game Theory, vol.4 (1975), pp.25–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar; see also Shubik, Martin, Game Theory in the Social Sciences: Concepts and Solutions (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1982), pp.265–270.Google Scholar
8 Schelling, Thomas C., The Strategy of Conflict (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1960), chap.9.Google Scholar
9 In a more complete dynamic analysis, we show that there is a trajectory or path from either of the Preemption Equilibria to the Deterrence Equilibrium that the player who is preempted can trigger by threatening to move – widi a probability above a, particular threshold – to the mutually worst outcome. Although this player incurs a temporary cost in making this threat, the rational response of the preemptor is to move to the Deterrence Equilibrium, whose dynamic stability would then preclude a rational move away from it. See Brams, Steven J. and Kilgour, D. Marc, “The Path to Stable Deterrence,” Dynamic Models of International Relations, Urs, Luterbacher and Michael, D. Ward, eds., (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 1985).Google Scholar A game analogous to the Deterrence Game, but based on Prisoners' Dilemma rather than Chicken, permits the players to move from the Pareto-inferior “Escalation Equilibrium” to the Pareto-superior “Deescalation Equilibrium,” that is costless to the player who initiates a move from the Escalation to the Deescalation Equilibrium. See Brams, Steven J. and Kilgour, D. Marc, “Rational Deescalation” (mimeographed, 1985).Google Scholar
10 Brams, Superpower Games, chap.l.
11 Bracken, Paul, The Command and Control of Nuclear Weapons (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983).Google Scholar Gauthier claims that such precommitments are not necessary to deter aggression, but threats which are not credible are empty, and empty threats invite attack. His calculus of deterrence, we believe, is sensible only when his retaliator's threats will assuredly be implemented because of precommitments. See Gauthier, David, “Deterrence, Maximization, and Rationality,” Ethics, vol.94 (April 1984), pp.474–495.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
12 Brams, Superpower Games, pp.45–46.
- 12
- Cited by