Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dsjbd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T00:22:07.276Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why all Welfare States (Including Laissez-Faire Ones) Are Unreasonable*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 January 2009

Gerald F. Gaus
Affiliation:
Philosophy and Political Science, University of Minnesota, Duluth

Extract

Liberal political theory is all too familiar with the divide between classical and welfare-state liberals. Classical liberals, as we all know, insist on the importance of small government, negative liberty, and private property. Welfare-state liberals, on the other hand, although they too stress civil rights, tend to be sympathetic to “positive liberty,” are for a much more expansive government, and are often ambivalent about private property. Although I do not go so far as to entirely deny the usefulness of this familiar distinction, I think in many ways it is misleading. In an important sense, most free-market liberals are also “welfare-state” liberals. I say this because the overwhelming number of liberals, of both the pro-market and the pro-government variety, entertain a welfarist conception of political economy. On this dominant welfarist view, the ultimate justification of the politico-economic order is that it promotes human welfare. Traditional “welfare-state liberals” such as Robert E. Goodin manifestly adopt this welfarist conception. But it is certainly not only interventionists such as Goodin who insist that advancing welfare is the overriding goal of normative political economy. J. R. McCulloch, one of the great nineteenth-century laissez-faire political economists, was adamant that “freedom is not, as some appear to think, the end of government: the advancement of public prosperity and happiness is its end.” To be sure, McCulloch would have disagreed with Goodin about the optimal welfare-maximizing economic policy: the welfarist ideal, he and his fellow classical political economists believed, would best be advanced by provision of a legal and institutional framework — most importantly, the laws of property, contract, and the criminal code — that allows individuals to pursue their own interests in the market and, by so doing, promote public welfare. In general, what might be called the “classical-liberal welfare state” claims to advance welfare by providing the framework for individuals to seek wealth for themselves, while welfarists such as Goodin insist that a market order is seriously flawed as a mechanism for advancing human welfare and, in addition, that government has the competency to “correct market failures” in the provision of welfare.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For analyses focusing on this divide, see Shils, Edward, “The Antinomies of Liberalism,” in The Relevance of Liberalism, ed. Staff of the Research Institute on International Change (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1978), pp. 135200Google Scholar; and Lomasky, Loren E., Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), ch. 5Google Scholar. See also my “Liberalism,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (online at http://plato.stanford.edu).

2 Goodin, Robert E., Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), ch. 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3 McCulloch, J. R., Principles of Political Economy, 5th ed. (Edinburgh: Charles Black, 1864), pp. 187–88.Google Scholar

4 For an elaboration, see my “Public and Private Interests in Liberal Political Economy, Old and New,” in Public and Private in Social Life, ed. Benn, S. I. and Gaus, G. F. (New York: St. Martin's, 1983), pp. 199203.Google Scholar

5 Goodin, Robert E., Reasons for Welfare (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988), pp. 1112Google Scholar. President Franklin Delano Roosevelt recognized more clearly than most the broader ideal of the welfare state: “If, as our constitution tells us, our Federal Government was established among other things, ‘to provide for the general welfare,’ then it is our plain duty to provide for that security upon which welfare depends.” Quoted in Gutmann, Amy, “Introduction,” in Democracy and the Welfare State, ed. Gutmann, Amy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988), p. 3.Google Scholar

6 Regarding the term “government house,” Goodin writes: “This is after all a term usually applied, usually derisively, to the closing chapters in [Henry] Sidgwick's Methods of Ethics, where he recommends that enlightened (implicitly, colonial) rulers govern according to utilitarian principles that are not necessarily … accessible to those subject to their rule” (Goodin, , Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy, pp. 6162).Google Scholar

7 Ibid., pp. 10–11.

8 Oakeshott, Michael, On Human Conduct (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), p. 156.Google Scholar

9 Ibid., p. 159.

10 von Hayek, Friedrich A., The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988), p. 31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

11 I vary the spelling from the traditional “Rechtsstaat” to indicate my slightly deviant use of the term. As I understand it, the traditional notion of the Rechtsstaat is consistent with rules of law that are justified as ways to achieve welfare. On the traditional view of the Rechtsstaat, see Kelsen, Hans, The Pure Theory of Law, trans. Knight, Max (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967), pp. 312–13Google Scholar. The variation in spelling was suggested to me by von Hayek, Friedrich A., The Road to Serfdom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1944), p. 88, n. 2.Google Scholar

12 Hayek, , The Road to Serfdom, ch. 6.Google Scholar

13 In the terminology of ethics, the Liberal Rechtstaat is a deontological view of the state.

14 Perry, Ralph Barton, Realms of Value (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1954), p. 107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15 Throughout I will be supposing that legislators, when deliberating about legislation, are taking up a genuinely public perspective, rather than using their public position to advance their private ends.

16 For a fuller treatment, see my essay “The Conflict of Values and Principles,” in Conflicting Values, ed. Magnell, Thomas (Amsterdam: Rodopi, forthcoming).Google Scholar

17 In addition to ibid., see my essay “The Rational, the Reasonable, and Justification,” Journal of Political Philosophy, vol. 3, no. 3 (09 1995), pp. 235–38Google Scholar; and Hampton, Jean, “The Failure of Expected-Utility Theory as a Theory of Reason,” Economics and Philosophy, vol. 10, no. 2 (10 1994), p. 198ff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

18 Brennan, Geoffrey and Lomasky, Loren, Democracy and Decision: The Pure Theory of Electoral Preference (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 9 (note omitted).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 Schmidtz, David, Rational Choice and Moral Agency (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995), p. 7Google Scholar. As with Schmidtz, , “I use ‘end’ and ‘goal’ … interchangeably”Google Scholar (ibid., p. 7n.). I have slightly altered Schmidtz's notation.

20 Kirzner, Israel M., The Meaning of Market Process: Essays in the Development of Modern Austrian Economics (London: Routledge, 1992), p. 208CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Wicksteed, Philip H., The Common Sense of Political Economy, ed. Robbins, Lionel (London: George Routledge and Sons, 1946), vol. 1, pp. 170–83.Google Scholar

21 If the goal is understood in terms of specific goods, “lumpiness” can also be a problem; it may well be that we only have use for goal G in certain “lumpy” increments, and an extra amount that does not get us to the next increment is of no use.

22 Although I have defended one elsewhere; see my Value and Justification: The Foundations of Liberal Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), Part 1.Google Scholar

23 See Hausman, Daniel M., The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), p. 32CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Cf. Ludwig von Mises's claim that “there is no question of any such thing as a law of increasing marginal utility” (i.e., marginal utility never increases over the range of possible quantities). von Mises, Ludwig, Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, 3d ed. (Chicago: Contemporary Books, 1966), p. 125.Google Scholar

24 See Freud, Sigmund, “The Disposition to Obsessional Neurosis,” in On Psychopathology, ed. Richards, Angela (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1979), pp. 134–44Google Scholar. Cf. Green, Thomas Hill, “On the Different Senses of ‘Freedom’ as Applied to the Will and to the Moral Progress of Man,” in his Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation and Other Writings, ed. Harris, Paul and Morrow, John (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 228.Google Scholar

25 Brennan, and Lomasky, , Democracy and Decision (supra note 18), p. 9Google Scholar. This is distinct from F2. According to decreasing marginal reasons, if we hold constant the cost of obtaining G, our reason to secure it decreases as we obtain higher levels; according F4, holding constant the level of G, our reasons for pursuing it decrease as the cost of obtaining it rises.

26 For the present, these can be treated as synonymous, though in fact the idea of a utility function is usually interpreted in a way that is more demanding than a system of trade-off rates. See Benn, Stanley, A Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), ch. 3CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also my Value and Justification (supra note 22), p. 182.Google Scholar

27 Sir Robert Giffen pointed out that when the price of bread rises, the very poor may purchase more of it; the increase in the price of bread has a significant effect on the real incomes of poor people, causing them to substitute bread for more expensive foods they can no longer afford, thus increasing the total amount of bread they consume. Status goods also can be considered as exceptions to downward-sloping demand — if they do not cost a great deal, they do not serve their purpose of showing that you can afford them. I am grateful to Julian Lament for pointing these exceptions out to me.

28 See, e.g., Becker, Gary, The Economic Approach to Human Behavior (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976), p. 3.Google Scholar

29 Simon, Herbert A., Reason in Human Affairs (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1983), pp. 78.Google Scholar

30 For the contrast between economic and sociological approaches, see Vanberg, Viktor J., Rules and Choice in Economics (London: Routledge, 1994), ch. 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See Talcott Parsons's “classification of the sciences of action” in Parsons, , The Social System (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1951), p. 545ffGoogle Scholar. For analyses of rule rationality with a focus on law, see Gottlieb, Gidon, The Logic of Choice (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1968)Google Scholar; and Schauer, Frederick, Playing by the Rules (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991).Google Scholar

31 Hart, H. L. A., The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961), p. 121Google Scholar. I shall not consider permissive rules here.

32 See Parsons, , The Social System (supra note 30), p. 207ff.Google Scholar; Vanberg, , Rules and Choice in Economics (supra note 30), p. 14Google Scholar. See also Kagan, Jerome, The Nature of the Child (New York: Basic Books, 1984), ch. 4.Google Scholar

33 Schauer, , Playing by the Rules (supra note 30), ch. 2Google Scholar; Vanberg, , Rules and Choice in Economics, p. 16ff.Google Scholar

34 Schauer, , Playing by the Rules, pp. 54ff., 72, 77, 113Google Scholar; Benn, , A Theory of Freedom (supra note 26), p. 24.Google Scholar

35 This, of course, is Hart's famous example in The Concept of Law (supra note 31), p. 123ff.Google Scholar

36 This is a familiar claim in a huge body of utilitarian literature. As Goodin puts it: “The best way to coordinate our actions with those of others, and thereby maximize the utility from each of our actions as well as from all of our actions collectively, is to promulgate rules (themselves chosen with an eye to maximizing utility, of course) and to adhere to them.” Goodin, , Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (supra note 2), p. 18.Google Scholar

37 Mill, John Stuart, A System of Logic (London: Longman's, 1947), Book VI, ch. xii, section 3.Google Scholar

38 Ibid., Book VI, ch. xii, section 2. I consider Mill's view in depth in my essay “Mill's Theory of Moral Rules,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 58 (09 1980), pp. 265–78.Google Scholar

39 Schauer, , Playing by the Rules (supra note 30), ch. 3.Google Scholar

40 See, e.g., Hardin, Russell, “My University's Yacht: Morality and the Rule of Law,” in NOMOS XXXVI: The Rule of Law, ed. Shapiro, Ian (New York: New York University Press, 1994), pp. 219–22.Google Scholar

41 Schauer, , Playing by the Rules, p. 72.Google Scholar

42 Mill, John Stuart, Utilitarianism (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1957), pp. 6162.Google Scholar

43 Ibid., p. 26.

44 Benn, , A Theory of Freedom (supra note 26), p. 8.Google Scholar

45 See Gaus, , Value and Justification (supra note 22), pp. 175–85Google Scholar; Benn, , A Theory of Freedom, pp. 4750Google Scholar; and Griffin, James, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 8992.Google Scholar

46 Benn, , A Theory of Freedom, ch. 3Google Scholar. I consider Benn's analysis in more depth in “The Conflict of Values and Principles” (supra note 16).

47 See Zimring, Franklin E. and Hawkins, Gordon, The Search for Rational Drug Control (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), ch. 6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

48 Note that a person with consistent trade-off rates can rationally choose “inconsistently,” sometimes opting for R and sometimes for G. See Benn, , A Theory of Freedom, p. 50ff.Google Scholar

49 See Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 61Google Scholar. A “lexical” order “is an order which requires us to satisfy the first principle in the ordering before we can move on to the second, the second before we consider the third, and so on. A principle does not come into play until those previous to it are either fully met or do not apply. A serial [or lexical] ordering avoids, then, having to balance principles at all: those earlier in the ordering have an absolute weight, so to speak, with respect to later ones, and hold without exception” (ibid., p. 43). In Rawls's theory of justice, the principle of liberty is lexically prior to the principle dealing with economic justice. Rawls acknowledges that “in general, a lexical order cannot be strictly correct” (ibid., p. 45). As Elizabeth Anderson points out, both Robert Nozick and Ronald Dworkin can be interpreted as offering lexical rankings. See Anderson, , Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), p. 67.Google Scholar

50 Barry, Brian, The Liberal Theory of Justice (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973), p. 60.Google Scholar

51 See Benn, , A Theory of Freedom, pp. 5659.Google Scholar

52 Berlin, Isaiah, The Hedgehog and the Fox (London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson, 1953)Google Scholar. This understanding of fanaticism allows us to interpret R. M. Hare's famous fanatic as a special case: his fanatic cares only about one thing (say, his commitment to Nazism) and so ignores other relevant considerations, e.g., his own interests. See Hare, , Freedom and Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952), ch. 9Google Scholar. See also Lomasky, , Persons, Rights, and the Moral Community (supra note 1), pp. 7983.Google Scholar

53 Keeney, Ralph L. and Raiffa, Howard, Decisions with Multiple Objectives: Preferences and Value Trade-Offs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

54 See Goodin, Robert E., Political Theory and Public Policy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), pp. 738Google Scholar. Goodin argues that “incrementalism” does not obviate the need for such insight into the causes of social phenomena.

55 Shackle, G. L. S., Epistemics and Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), p. 19.Google Scholar

56 “In actuality, the human being never has more than a fragmentary knowledge of the conditions surrounding his action, nor more than a slight insight into the regularities and laws that would permit him to induce further consequences from a knowledge of present circumstances.” Simon, Herbert A., Administrative Behavior: A Study of Decision-Making Processes in Administrative Organization, 3d ed. (New York: Free Press, 1976), p. 81.Google Scholar

57 See Goodin, , Political Theory and Public Policy (supra note 54), ch. 9.Google Scholar

58 See, e.g., Paris, J. B., The Uncertain Reasoner's Companion (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994).Google Scholar

59 For a summary, see Kleindorfer, Paul R., Kunreuther, Howard C., and Schoemaker, Paul J. H., Decision Sciences: An Integrative Perspective (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 87100CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See also Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, ed. Kahneman, Daniel, Slovic, Paul, and Tversky, Amos (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

60 Kirzner, , The Meaning of Market Process (supra note 20), chs. 9, 10Google Scholar. For the classic essay on this topic, see von Hayek, Friedrich A., “The Use of Knowledge in Society,” in Austrian Economics, ed. Ebeling, Richard M. (Hillsdale, MI: Hillsdale College Press, 1991), ch. 14.Google Scholar

61 See Peacock, Alan, Public Choice Analysis in an Historical Framework (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 7479Google Scholar. See also Wolf, Charles Jr., Markets or Governments: Choosing between Imperfect Alternatives, 2d ed. (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1994), pp. 6879Google Scholar; and Simon, , Administrative Behavior (supra note 56), ch. 10.Google Scholar

62 Evidence indicates, for example, that state investment in education tends to supplant rather than supplement private investment. See Becker, , The Economic Approach to Human Behavior (supra note 28), p. 267n.Google Scholar

63 Goodin, , Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (supra note 2), p. 63Google Scholar, emphasis added. See Rhoads, Steven, The Economist's View of the World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), p. 57.Google Scholar

64 Peltzman, Sam, “The Effects of Automobile Safety Regulations,” Journal of Political Economy, vol. 83 (08 1975), pp. 677726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

65 Houston, David J., Richardson, Lilliard E. Jr., and Neely, Grant W., “Legislating Traffic Safety: A Pooled Time Series Analysis,” Social Science Quarterly, vol. 76 (06 1995), pp. 330–31.Google Scholar

66 Harvey, A. C. and Durbin, J., “The Effects of Seat Belt Legislation on British Road Deaths,” Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Series A, vol. 149 (1986), pp. 187210CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ryan, David L. and Bridgeman, Guy A., “Judging the Roles of Legislation, Education, and Offsetting Behaviour in Seat Belt Use: A Survey and New Evidence from Alberta,” Canadian Public Policy, vol. 18 (1992), pp. 2746.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

67 Garbacz, Christopher, “Estimating Seat Belt Effectiveness with Seat Belt Usage Data from the Centers for Disease Control,” Economics Letters, vol. 34 (1990), pp. 8388CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Garbacz, Christopher, “Do Front-Seat Belt Laws Put Rear-Seat Passengers at Risk?Population Research and Policy Review, vol. 11 (1992), pp. 157–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

68 Rhoads, , The Economist's View of the World (supra note 63), p. 57.Google Scholar

69 Garbacz, , “Do Front-Seat Belt Laws Put Rear-Seat Passengers at Risk?”Google Scholar

70 Harvey, and Durbin, , “The Effects of Seat Belt Legislation on British Road Deaths” (supra note 66).Google Scholar

71 Rhoads, , The Economist's View of the World, p. 57.Google Scholar

72 Irwin, Alan, “Technical Expertise and Risk Conflict: An Institutional Study of the British Compulsory Seat Belt Debate,” Policy Sciences, vol. 20 (1987), pp. 339–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ryan, and Bridgeman, , “Judging the Roles of Legislation, Education, and Offsetting Behaviour in Seat Belt Use” (supra note 66), p. 32Google Scholar. For an exception, see Bhattacharyya, M. N. and Layton, Allan P., “Effectiveness of Seat Belt Legislation on the Queensland Road Toll,” Journal of the American Statistical Association, vol. 74 (09 1974), pp. 596603.Google Scholar

73 Rhoads, , The Economist's View of the World (supra note 63), p. 239, n. 65.Google Scholar

74 The Cyclists Touring Club and the British Cycling Federation opposed renewal of mandatory seat belt legislation in the United Kingdom in 1986. See Irwin, , “Technical Expertise and Risk Conflict,” p. 359.Google Scholar

75 Ibid., pp. 359–60.

76 Ibid., p. 360.

77 Slovic, Paul, “Beyond Numbers: A Broader Perspective on Risk Perception and Risk Communication,” in Acceptable Evidence, ed. Mayo, Deborah G. and Hollander, Rachelle D. (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), pp. 4865.Google Scholar

78 Ibid., pp. 57–59.

79 Griffin, , Well-Being (supra note 45), pp. 121–24.Google Scholar

80 See Goodin, , Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (supra note 2), p. 17Google Scholar; Hardin, Russell, Morality within the Limits of Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988).Google Scholar

81 von Hayek, Friedrich A., The Mirage of Social Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976), p. 20.Google Scholar

82 For a recent defense of this “satisficing” conception of reason, see Schmidtz, , Rational Choice and Moral Agency (supra note 19), Part IGoogle Scholar. For a brief discussion, see my review of Schmidtz's book in the American Political Science Review, vol. 90, no. 1 (03 1996), pp. 179–80Google Scholar. The basic idea, of course, derives from Simon, , Administrative Behavior (supra note 56).Google Scholar

83 Keeney, and Raiffa, , Decisions with Multiple Objectives (supra note 53), p. 1.Google Scholar

84 Ibid., p. 20.

85 Goodin, , Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (supra note 2), p. 10 (footnotes omitted).Google Scholar

86 Weber, Max, “Politics as a Vocation,” in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. Gerth, H. H. and Mills, C. Wright (New York: Oxford University Press, 1946), p. 120.Google Scholar

87 Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos, “On the Psychology of Prediction,” in Judgment under Uncertainty (supra note 59), p. 66.Google Scholar

89 Weber, , “Politics as a Vocation” (supra note 86), p. 127Google Scholar. See also Larmore, Charles, Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), pp. 144–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

90 For a foreign policy case, see Benn, S. I., “Deterrence or Appeasement? or, On Trying to Be Rational about Nuclear War,” Journal of Applied Philosophy, vol. 1 (1984), pp. 519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

91 See my Value and Justification, ch. 8 (supra note 22) and Justificatory Liberalism: An Essay on Epistemology and Political Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), ch. 10.Google Scholar

92 See my Justificatory Liberalism, Parts II and III.

93 See ibid., pp. 209–11.

94 See Gauthier, David, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), ch. 4.Google Scholar

95 See Kirzner, , The Meaning of Market Process (supra note 20), pp. 2425Google Scholar. See also Simon, , Reason in Human Affairs (supra note 29), pp. 1923.Google Scholar

96 I am indebted here to Julian Lament, whose forthcoming work on this topic promises to clear up a variety of confusions about efficiency judgments of real-world economies.

97 I believe my views here are consistent with the “middle ground” of Austrian economics as well as the radical views of G. L. S. Shackle. For a defense of the middle ground, see Kirzner, , The Meaning of Market Process (supra note 20), ch. 1Google Scholar. For Shackle, see his Epistemics and Economics (supra note 55), and his Decision, Order, and Time in Human Affairs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969)Google Scholar. See also Hutchinson, Terence W., “Philosophical Issues that Divide Liberals: Omniscience or Omni-nescience about the Future?” in Subjectivism, Intelligibility, and Economic Understanding, ed. Kirzner, Israel M. (New York: New York University Press, 1986), ch. 10.Google Scholar

98 See my “A Contractual Justification of Redistributive Capitalism,” in NOMOS XXXI: Markets and Justice, ed. Chapman, John W. and Pennock, J. Roland (New York: New York University Press, 1989), pp. 89121.Google Scholar

99 “The principal justification for public policy lies in the frequent and numerous shortcomings of market outcomes.” Wolf, , Markets or Governments (supra note 61), p. 17Google Scholar. Wolf, however, is far more aware than most that “the policy implications of market imperfections may be ambiguous” (p. 27).

100 Kirzner, , The Meaning of Market Process (supra note 20), p. 58.Google Scholar

101 McCulloch, , Principles of Political Economy (supra note 3), p. 228Google Scholar; Say, Jean Baptiste, A Treatise on Political Economy (New York: A. M. Kelley, 1964), p. 181.Google Scholar

102 McCulloch, , Principles of Political Economy, pp. 129, 226–30Google Scholar. See also Robbins, Lionel, The Theory of Economic Policy in English Classical Political Economy (London: Macmillan, 1961), pp. 8893.Google Scholar

103 Ricardo, David, On the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, ed. Sraffa, Piero (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1951), pp. 356–57Google Scholar; O'Brien, D. P., The Classical Economists (Oxford: Clarendon, 1975), pp. 274–75.Google Scholar

104 Hayek, , The Road to Serfdom (supra note 11), p. 43.Google Scholar