Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T09:24:34.912Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Preserve psychoanalysis from too much neuroscience

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

H. Jones*
Affiliation:
Maudsley Hospital, Denmark Hill, London SE5 8AZ, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Columns
Copyright
Copyright © 2003 The Royal College of Psychiatrists 

Professor Hobson (Reference Hobson2003) argues admirably for the continued relevance of psychoanalysis in a mainstream psychiatric journal. But is his suggested rapprochement between psychoanalysis and contemporary neuroscience really desirable?

Contemporary neuroscience as illustrated by his example of ‘mirror neurons’ typically assumes an ‘empiricist’ worldview. In brief, imitation is assumed to be an acquired process in which information is abstracted from experience using associative learning. The current focus is on the anatomical location of the associative learning responsible for imitation (Reference Rizzolatti, Fogassi and GalleseRizzolatti et al, 2001).

In contrast, psychoanalysis derives from an older, rationalist philosophical tradition. It assumes the existence of both innate beliefs, such as persecutory anxiety, and distinct mental mechanisms, such as introjection or Klein's paranoid–schizoid position, that do not rely on associative learning.

These two philosophies have been in tension for centuries. One option is to make psychoanalysis more empiricist by down-playing the innateness and divergent mental mechanisms of classical theory. This is seen in attempts to incorporate ‘theory of mind’ deficits into a psychodynamic understanding of mental states (Reference FonagyFonagy, 1991).

But will associative learning form the secure basis for understanding the mind that empiricism proposed? Practical attempts to develop this philosophy, such as neural networks, are not actually very good at accounting for how we manage to form and fix true beliefs. Rationalist accounts of higher brain functions such as language do exist (Reference ChomskyChomsky, 1959). Given such uncertainty rationalism continues to merit the foothold within psychiatric practice that psychoanalysis provides. Too much mutual understanding between psychoanalysis and contemporary neuroscience might not be good for psychiatry.

Footnotes

EDITED BY STANLEY ZAMMIT

Declaration of interest

H.J. has previously received unrestricted educational grants from Eli Lilly and Astra-Zeneca.

References

Chomsky, N. (1959) A review of Skinner's verbal behaviour. Language, 35, 1. Reprinted (1980) in Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 1 (ed. N. Block). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University press.Google Scholar
Fonagy, P. (1991) Thinking about thinking: some clinical and theoretical considerations in the treatment of a borderline patient. International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 72, 639656.Google Scholar
Hobson, R. I. (2003) Between ourselves: psychodynamics and the interpersonal domain. British Journal of Psychiatry, 182, 193195.Google Scholar
Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, I. & Gallese, V. (2001) Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the understanding of imitation and action. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 661669.Google Scholar
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.