Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-21T05:00:34.299Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The role of belief in the case for austerity policies

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2023

Sheila C Dow*
Affiliation:
University of Stirling, UK
*
Sheila C Dow, Division of Economics, Stirling Management School, University of Stirling, Stirling FK9 4LA, UK. Email: s.c.dow@stir.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Mainstream economists give the misleading impression that their argument for austerity is purely technical and indeed the most ‘scientific’. The argument developed here is that their reasoning is not, any more than that of their heterodox critics, independent of ideology, power and ethics. The widespread belief in austerity policies as scientifically justified has prevented arguments against austerity gaining more traction; issues of ideology, power and ethics need to be brought to the fore as part of the arguments on both sides. In other words, awareness of the epistemological issues arising from an open-system ontology is critical to understanding the crisis and the policy response, and therefore to challenging that understanding and encouraging a radical policy shift. The critique of austerity policies would therefore be strengthened by a critique of the mainstream’s rhetorical (mis)representation of economic theorising.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s) 2015

Introduction

As the global financial crisis of 2007–2009 became an economic crisis, early fiscal stimulus soon gave way to a dominant policy response of fiscal austerity. The aim of this article is to explore the mechanisms by which belief in austerity policies have widely become unchallenged conventional wisdom, despite evidence and experience of their adverse effects.

Austerity policy has taken the form of significant reductions in government expenditure, primarily on public services. The aim has been to improve the fiscal position, which had worsened as a result of support for the financial system during the crisis. The mainstream economic reasoning behind this policy is an extension of the reasoning behind the limits put on budgetary deficits in Europe by the Maastricht Treaty; it is taken as a universal principle, based on positivist methodology, that budgetary deficits should be strictly limited. Footnote 1 However, a broad coalition of economists under the banner of Keynesianism have produced theoretical reasons, along with supportive historical evidence, why austerity policies in current circumstances (though not universally) would be self-defeating, damaging the prospects for recovery and actually worsening the fiscal position. While ‘Keynesian’ arguments against austerity have been put forward by some who share with mainstream economics a positivist methodology, we confine our attention here to heterodox (including Post Keynesian) arguments which employ a non-positivist methodology, based on an open-system epistemology (see Reference DavidsonDavidson, 2012, on this distinction). Footnote 2

The purpose of this article is specifically to consider why belief that austerity policy was necessary became conventional wisdom within society. It would seem straightforward to compare the theoretical arguments on both sides and to assess them in the light of the evidence. Yet, the difference of opinion among economists persists, while the mainstream view has proved more generally persuasive. Why have Keynesians so far been unable to shake the prevailing belief in austerity policies? Two forces have been of fundamental importance in driving support for austerity: an ideological commitment to reducing the size of the state on the one hand and vested interests among those with financial power on the other (see, for example, Reference CallinicosCallinicos, 2012). But the conventional support for austerity has extended well beyond those who share that ideology and even more so beyond the minority with financial power. The mechanisms for the exercise of power by those promoting austerity policies require investigation.

The aim here is to understand why the Keynesian critique has not gained more traction in society at large. This question is approached by considering the nature of knowledge in terms of belief, and the role of ideology, power and ethics, alongside reason and evidence, in the building up of knowledge about an open-system reality. A particular focus will be placed on the rhetorical power of mainstream economic policy, presented as the outcome of a technical scientific process distinct from ideology, power and ethics. This article arrives at a conclusion that broadens the range of argument against austerity to include a critique of this mainstream scientism. This critique has been well developed more generally with respect to mainstream economics; the argument here applies it particularly to the debate over austerity.

The mainstream view of economics as a science

It is well established now that mainstream economics evolved by emulating physics (Reference MirowskiMirowski, 1989). The aim was to develop theories which were both internally logically consistent and testable against empirical evidence. According to logical positivism, such an aim marks out science from non-science. Indeed prior to the emergence of logical positivism in the 1930s, the marginalist methodological approach had started the shift of economics away from the class-based framework of classical political economy towards a focus on the supposedly universal optimising behaviour of individuals within competitive markets. Marginalism required and thus promoted the increasing use of formal mathematics to such an extent that the deductivist formal mathematical method for analysing choice has come to define the discipline as far as mainstream economists are concerned. The scientific nature of economics is seen as being completed by empirical testing.

Explicit references to methodology are in fact rare in mainstream economics, such that methodological stance has often to be inferred from practice. But mainstream introductory textbooks do provide illustrative statements about the nature of economics and its methodology. Reference Mankiw and TaylorMankiw and Taylor (2006) and Reference Parkin, Powell and MatthewsParkin et al. (2012) make typical statements, introducing students to economics by specifying the subject matter in terms of rational choice under scarcity. They then briefly set out economic methodology (what Reference Mankiw and TaylorMankiw and Taylor, 2006, call ‘the economist’s way of thinking’ (p. 19)). Theory is equated with mathematical models which they assert to be simplifications of reality, tested against evidence: that is, they make a clear statement of logical positivist methodology. Here, we have a particular understanding of economics, and its methodology presented as the definitive understanding for all of economics. But it involves huge methodological presumptions. If there are (unacknowledged) alternatives, the implication is that they must be less scientific.

But this view of scientific method has long been discredited in the philosophy of science literature. All three recent accounts of the methodology literature attest to this and therefore devote more attention to the ways in which the field has moved on (see Reference Boumans and DavisBoumans and Davis, 2010; Reference DowDow, 2002; Reference HandsHands, 2001). All three accounts explain how logical positivism suffers from the Duhem–Quine problem, which refers to the difficulty of identifying what exactly has been falsified by contrary evidence. Finding evidence consistent with a theory does not prove it to be correct. Reference PopperPopper (1963) had argued that scientists should instead test very narrow propositions and reject them if contradicted by the evidence. But Reference BlaugBlaug (1980) demonstrated that, where economists test theories, they persist in relying on confirmatory evidence. Thus, even among those who share a positivist approach to economics, differences of opinion on austerity policies have not been resolved.

Because of the difficulty in arriving at definitive conclusions on the basis of empirical evidence, the higher ground of mainstream economics has been held by pure theorists whose theories produce definitive conclusions, regarded only as testable in principle. Thus, while there has been an increasing challenge from evidence arising from applied fields like behavioural economics, the aim of the challengers is stated as being to build a better formal framework (Reference DowDow, 2013). Reference ShillerShiller (2013) reiterates the compatibility between formalist theorising and experimental evidence, within a logical positivist view of science as demarcated from non-science (‘charlatanism’). But the view, that for economics to be a science theory must be tested empirically, has continued to pose a challenge for mainstream economics. Such a challenge is endemic to logical positivism.

According to this ‘scientific’ (indeed scientistic Footnote 3 ) approach to economics, theory appraisal and policy prescription are matters of logic and evidence; there is no place for belief as far as economists are concerned. Were economists’ beliefs to be analysed, they would be constrained to converge on the correct model, identified on logical positivist grounds. Beliefs do feature in agents’ expectations in mainstream models, reflecting the subjectivity of expectations and the learning required to adjust expectations in the light of evidence. Agents’ beliefs are particularly important with respect to the behaviour of state agencies; central banks are enjoined to behave in a consistent way which enhances credibility and thus the correctness of beliefs. But beliefs are constrained eventually to settle on the final equilibrium values which are identified by technical analysis, based on deductivist logic tested against empirical evidence.

Not only has philosophy of science moved on, so have the physical sciences. Reference BuchananBuchanan (2013) argues that the physical sciences have shifted their focus from pure theory to attempting to understand real disequilibrium systems with positive feedback mechanisms; the nature of the subject matter is determining the type of theory that is being developed and the type of mathematics used. He contrasts this development with the continuing dominance of mainstream economics, whose deductivist equilibrium theoretical system bears little relation to the real subject matter. Reference ShillerShiller (2013) too draws attention to developments in the physical sciences in the direction of becoming more applied, using this tendency as evidence of economics’ continuing scientific status. Yet he does not challenge the identification of mainstream theory with mathematical models: ‘The challenge has been to combine its mathematical insights with the kinds of adjustments that are needed to make its models fit the economy’s irreducibly human element’. This is not the fundamental shift from axiomatic deductivist equilibrium theory to the study of disequilibrium positive feedback processes we find occurring in the physical sciences, but rather a shifting balance in the continually uneasy relations between theory and evidence which characterise mainstream economic methodology.

It is the economist’s task, according to Reference LucasLucas (1980), to build ever-better analogue models, where models are again equated with theories. Since formal models are closed systems, this means that mainstream theories too are closed systems. Although the crisis provided overwhelming evidence that the economic system was not closed to unexpected structural shifts, this evidence has not been taken by the mainstream as a challenge to the closed-system approach. Much of the discourse responding to the challenge posed by the crisis was conducted, not in terms of rethinking the reliance on formal models, but in terms of finding a better technical model (Reference LawsonLawson, 2009).

But, in spite of all these problems with the unworkability of logical positivism and the fact that physics has moved on to systems very different from economics, arguments in favour of austerity policies are still presented as technical propositions (see Reference Ball and MankiwBall and Mankiw, 1996, for a typical statement). The underlying argument for austerity is indeed a technical result of the assumptions and structure of mainstream models, but these in turn are built on a range of metaphysical and methodological assumptions. Arguments either for or against austerity are not purely technical.

Yet, the assumption of rational expectations (or some variant of them) portrays agents as arriving at the same technical conclusions as economists. Indeed, the argument for austerity has increasingly been expressed in terms of the assumption that financial markets have accepted the technical result that deficits crowd out private sector expenditure and reduce growth, such that they will factor it into the pricing of assets, including government debt, constraining the government to accept an austerity stance. This thinking was embedded in the Maastricht rules, limiting the size of deficits and public sector debt relative to gross domestic product (GDP) in order for fiscal policy not to interfere with the priority of controlling inflation through independent monetary policy. The force of the pro-austerity reasoning appeared to be strengthened by the research findings of Reference Reinhart and RogoffReinhart and Rogoff (2010), whose historical evidence of budgetary positions and growth rates appeared to confirm the technical results. Reason and evidence are assumed to be sufficient for generating and accepting the austerity conclusion. Beliefs are seen only to enter into the policy arena once politicians input their political preferences (Reference ColanderColander, 2002). The presumption is that the theoretical structure is purely technical, yielding definitive ‘scientific’ results.

Yet, even physical scientists talk in terms of belief, as in belief in global warming. This is a clear indication that there is too much uncertainty surrounding climate change to be able to demonstrate definitively that global warming is occurring. The physical world, like the social world, is an evolving, complex, open system. Footnote 4 Reason and evidence support the belief in global warming, but others find support for alternative beliefs. While promoters of global warming regard their critics as wrong-headed, nevertheless the matter is treated as one of belief, requiring persuasion to change from one belief to another. Pure deductive reasoning, built on premises which all agree to be true, is not enough; any deductive chain is vulnerable to premises not being reliably true. Pure inductive reasoning, extrapolating from past observations, is not enough; there is no guarantee that past structures and relationships will continue as before. Even in the physical sciences, then, arguments require belief – that premises hold true, or that structures and/or relationships will continue to hold – even when this cannot be demonstrated definitively. Knowledge is in general uncertain.

Knowledge and belief

The inadequacies of logical positivism and the centrality of belief for knowledge were established at the beginning of modern economics in the 18th century. Reference Hume, Selby-Bigge and NedditchHume ([1739–1740] 1978) grappled with Cartesian deductivism and also specified the problem of induction, concluding that knowledge rests on belief. As far as deductivism was concerned, no system based on pure reason could legitimately be applied to real circumstances. As far as empirical testing on the basis of evidence from the past was concerned, there could be no basis for assuming that the same causal mechanisms would operate, or operate in the same way, in the future. Reason and evidence were necessary for knowledge, but not sufficient: they relied in turn on belief.

This belief applies at a variety of levels, starting with a conventional belief in existence and in the nature of the real world but also incorporating belief that some theoretical propositions are reliable, on which to build other propositions. Hume, like Smith, adopted a Newtonian approach, whereby knowledge is built up through a process of abduction. Any resulting theory must be regarded as provisional since its premises may not apply to other times and places than those from which evidence is drawn. Even as explanation rather than prediction, a theory is provisional given the reliance on belief at various stages of reasoning. Knowledge is more reliable the more it draws on experience and on reason – the philosopher (scientist) is someone drawn to applying more reason than others, and thus to challenging conventional beliefs. But knowledge is always subject to some degree of uncertainty.

Reference KeynesKeynes (1921) pursued Hume’s agenda by exploring how we establish grounds for belief under the normal condition of uncertainty, where uncertainty eludes the quantification which allows mainstream theorists to generate what purport to be demonstrable propositions. Keynes understood establishing grounds for belief as being an objective process, drawing on evidence and reason; anyone in the same circumstances, environment and psychological state would arrive at the same belief. But circumstances, environment and psychological state differ, such that, not only does the evidence brought to bear differ, but so do the conventional beliefs and intuition employed and also what Keynes called ‘animal spirits’. Beliefs therefore differ. Beliefs can be justified up to a point by reason and evidence. Thus, the more different types of evidence support any belief, the greater the evidential weight. But what is admissible as evidence depends on judgement as to its relevance which depends on the underlying theoretical perspective and ultimately on belief (Reference Dow, Dow and HillardDow, [1995] 2012).

Critics of austerity policies have marshalled a compelling range of arguments challenging both the deductive and empirical elements of the case for austerity. For example, Reference Chick and PettiforChick and Pettifor (2010) provide empirical evidence from a range of historical episodes in the UK which contradicts the mainstream arguments for austerity. They show in general that fiscal expansion has been associated with falling public sector debt, higher growth and lower interest rates. A key argument is that austerity cannot achieve its object of reducing public sector debt because of automatic stabilisers: austerity causes revenues to fall and expenditure to increase. Increasing expenditures on the other hand, in underemployment conditions, have a multiplier effect on incomes and thus on revenues, while reducing reliance on unemployment benefits and spending on social services. Similarly, Reference Herndon, Ash and PollinHerndon et al. (2014) provide a detailed critique of the evidence on the relationship between deficits and growth behind the Reference Reinhart and RogoffReinhart and Rogoff (2010) thesis. These are just two examples of what would appear to be powerful direct challenges to the arguments for austerity on the same ground of reason and evidence. So why does the argument for austerity still persist?

While apparently misguided (even delusional) beliefs can persist, it is also possible for them to change in the light of evidence, particularly when it has a direct effect on experience. Thus, for example, it was the initial experience of defaults which punctured the belief that financial markets had reliably priced risk and protected themselves against default, setting off the crisis. Mainstream theorists too have responded to the experience of the crisis by adapting theory to incorporate a range of constraints on the free operation of markets and on rational optimising behaviour. But, although it would seem that pointing out false logic and contrary evidence should change attitudes to austerity policies, this has been true only to a limited extent. Belief in austerity policies is necessarily based on more than reason and evidence; these are filtered through the underlying structure of beliefs.

At the level of belief in the nature of the economy, the arguments for austerity are all predicated on economic structure being unchanged. But the crisis and its real consequences provide ample evidence of the scope for the structure of social systems and behaviour within them to change in a non-deterministic way, that is, for the subject matter to be an open system. Thus, an important aspect of the Reference Chick and PettiforChick and Pettifor (2010) argument is the reference to changes in the policy-making architecture (particularly with respect to monetary policy) in the periods under study. Rather than separable deductive reasoning tested against evidence, their argument involves abduction, whereby observed structural changes alter the interpretation of the data and the reasoned argument.

And yet the mainstream persists in adopting a closed-system approach which implies a closed-system subject matter (Reference LawsonLawson, 1997). It is this approach which allows conclusions to be treated as reliable when they rest on deductive argument applied to an unchanging structure or on extrapolation from empirical evidence. Mainstream arguments in favour of austerity are only ‘technical’, independent of belief, within such a system. Yet, the system itself rests on the belief that the social system can be treated as if it were closed. The disparity between an open-system reality and closed-system theory lies behind the difficulties with empirical testing, notably the problem of induction. The statistical version is that tests can only refer to the past and cannot address uncertainty with respect to the future. Hume’s more fundamental problem is that causal mechanisms and their interrelations are too complex for us to fully understand them, far less predict their outcomes.

But closed-system theories yield definitive conclusions. While these conclusions cannot be related directly to evidence, the resulting certainty can be more persuasive to non-economists than the provisional conclusions of open-system theory. This is particularly the case with equilibrium theory where any dynamism en route to the final equilibrium occurs in mechanical time, that is, it does not correspond to historical time. As Reference Chick, Dow and HillardChick (1995: 33–34) points out, the closed system puts the focus on a fictional long run, while knowledge about a real historical long period is fundamentally uncertain. She quotes Reference RokeachRokeach (1960) as follows: ‘Knowledge about the remote future is impossible to refute and, hence, one can be safely preoccupied with it … For this reason, a narrow, future-oriented time perspective is … seen to be a defining characteristic of closed systems’ (p. 64).

Because reason therefore has limited scope, efforts to change others’ beliefs are a matter of persuasion rather than pure reason. As Reference KeynesKeynes ([1934] 1973, emphasis in original) put it,

In economics you cannot convict your opponent of error, you can only convince him of it. And, even if you are right, you cannot convince him, if there is a defect in your powers of persuasion and exposition or if his head is already so filled with contrary notions that he cannot catch the clues to your thought that you are trying to throw at him. (p. 470)

Reason and evidence are sufficient for argument according to mainstream economics, at least as far as the official discourse goes. (Reference McCloskeyMcCloskey, 1986, demonstrates that the unofficial rhetoric of the coffee room is – necessarily according to our argument – more pluralistic.) But reason and evidence are not even in principle sufficient from a Keynesian perspective. Thus, for example, while Joan Robinson demonstrated a logical inconsistency in mainstream theory in the Capital Controversies (an exercise in pure reason), the principle of factor substitution was not rejected; pure reason was insufficiently persuasive. On the other hand, the Monetarist/Keynesian debates about the relative slopes of the IS and LM curves remained unresolved in spite of extensive empirical work; empirical testing was insufficiently persuasive.

Argument rather needs to address the complex structure of knowledge, encompassing also the nature and role of beliefs within that structure. In Kuhnian terms, beliefs underpin the worldview of any paradigm; in critical realist terms, beliefs about the nature of reality (ontology) determine epistemology. But since theory develops by abduction, involving a going-back-and-forward between experience and theory, beliefs continue to penetrate all subsequent reasoning, including the interpretation of evidence. We have focused so far on belief in the epistemological sense. Indeed, much of the critiques of austerity draw on the large literature which spells out the foundation of orthodoxy, like heterodoxy, in beliefs as to what constitutes reliable knowledge. There is no basis in modern philosophy of science for mainstream economists to claim that their research is more scientific than that of heterodox economists because of their reliance on formal deductive mathematical reasoning and their appeal to what are presented as independent facts. The grounding in undemonstrable beliefs is there, unacknowledged or not.

It is challenging enough to get this argument across to fellow economists. But for persuading public opinion more generally to challenge the mainstream results, these epistemological arguments may have limited traction. What may have more purchase is the argument that, among these beliefs, all economic reasoning involves moral judgements, as Hume had contended (Reference KayatekinKayatekin, 2014). Thus, for example, arguments for austerity prioritise efficiency over distributional concerns. But the moral judgements are even more deep-rooted. Where it is assumed that workers are paid the value of their marginal product (VMP), this is taken as a technical result without moral content. Yet, the suggestion that government should support the market in paying CEOs of banks and low-paid workers, their market value entails a moral judgement in favour of forces for a particular distribution of income. The moral content is more evident in alternative approaches which understand pay levels to be politically and socially determined. But this is taken by mainstream economics to be an indication of poor science – reasoning invaded by ideology.

What is widely ignored is that this is in the nature of a social science and that mainstream economics incorporates ideology. Reference StrettonStretton (1969) sets out the argument that all theorising inevitably incorporates values, in the selection of the focus for theory and the selection of causal forces identified. The belief that the market produces a morally acceptable distribution of income has of course been widely challenged as a result of austerity policies. Yet, the presentation of mainstream arguments for austerity as a technical result has been persuasive that moral arguments about income distribution are separable from the content of mainstream economic theory. But Stretton points out that the mainstream methodological stricture to select for generality itself involves a value judgement. Rhetorically, the misguided conventional view that mainstream economics is the only scientific approach further diverts attention from any discussion among economists of belief on the grounds that any such discussion would not be ‘scientific’. It also diverts the moral argument in public discourse away from mainstream economics. Stretton points out the immorality of concealing the values embedded in theorising which has the consequence of stifling debate over these values.

The fact is that some beliefs hold more sway over the policy process than others. In the next section, we consider the process of persuasion which ensures that some beliefs become conventional in spite of the fact that critics of austerity policies regard the basis of these beliefs in reason and evidence as very weak.

Rhetoric, power and belief

If conventional beliefs spread through persuasion, then we need to consider further why the rhetoric of austerity has been so successful. We consider three elements in this process of persuasion: the content of the rhetoric, the means by which it is communicated and the relative power of those attempting to persuade.

It was noted at the start that the primary forces behind austerity policies were ideological (the aim of reducing the role of the state) and self-serving (the aim to protect capitalist economic interests). These forces are associated with socio-economic power and thus the capacity to influence what is regarded as reliable knowledge. There is a range of mechanisms for exercising that power. For academic economists, it is the editorial policies of leading mainstream journals, research funding and the hiring process in universities. These mechanisms operate by ‘peer review’, where the peers predominantly promote mainstream economics as the most ‘scientific’ approach to economics. That governments actively promote this kind of peer review reflects their tacit acceptance of the mainstream closed-system view of knowledge. Since governments have the power to challenge such a view, the fact that they don’t implies that it is not in their interests to do so. Even where political interests would not appear to be best served by mainstream economics, as is the case particularly for left-wing politics, the power of financial markets over governments can be seen as an effective constraint. Globalisation and financialisation have increased the power over governments of financial markets and their trading in sovereign debt.

For the general public, the mechanisms are different, relying heavily on power exercised over various communications media. A growing body of work in discourse analysis is building up a picture of communication strategies in persuasion with respect to government policies. Reference PigeonPigeon (2008) provides a rich account of how the Canadian government used a variety of communication strategies to great effect to produce conventional belief in the wisdom of inflation targeting and fiscal austerity. Reference MercilleMercille (2014) concentrates on the role of the mass media in Ireland in promoting a conventional neo-liberal view in support of fiscal consolidation policies. Reference Herndon, Ash and PollinHerndon et al. (2014) discuss how the Reference Reinhart and RogoffReinhart and Rogoff (2010) evidence had been used in the policy discourse. The language used itself can be very effective in persuading the general public to accept ‘expert’ opinion. Reference GaborGabor (2010) emphasises the importance in Romania of the presentation of macroeconomic policy in technical, apparently non-political, terms, allowing the government to pursue a neo-liberal agenda. Her work is path-breaking in demonstrating the power of presenting political economy arguments as neutral technical results, an argument on which this article has attempted to build.

Reference Smith and WightmanSmith ([1795] 1980) had emphasised the role of rhetoric in persuasion, given the impossibility in general of fully demonstrating a proposition by reason or evidence. Metaphor performs a powerful role in the communication of theories (Reference McCloskeyMcCloskey, 1986), but also in their origination and development (Reference LawsonLawson, 2003). Indeed, Reference Smith and WightmanSmith ([1795] 1980) had likened theories themselves to imaginary machines. In economics, metaphors such as ‘the market’ have been very powerful in guiding thought. With respect to fiscal policy, the most powerful metaphor employed by politicians (though not generally by economists) has involved likening a national budget to a household budget; fiscal austerity is presented as normal prudence. Such a device is persuasive, as Reference Smith and BryceSmith ([1762–1763] 1983) suggested, because it builds on personal experience (unlike proper macroeconomic arguments). Households are then susceptible to the argument that, once debt reaches a particular level at a particular interest rate, debt servicing will make it increasingly difficult to control the budget. A budgetary surplus is therefore seen to be required to reduce both the debt and the debt service burden; it is perceived that the way to achieve this is to implement austerity policies.

While this may seem like a purely technical argument, it rests on the belief that a government is like a household. But, even setting aside the confusion in the public discourse between current and capital deficits, and the different capacities of governments and households to finance a deficit, a current deficit at the national level is not like a current deficit at the household level. When a household is earning from employment less than it is spending on current consumption, there is no mechanism to avoid ever-increasing debt other than to cut back on spending. A government’s earnings are primarily from taxation, which depends on the employment and spending of the population. Cutting back on government spending therefore reduces tax revenue and requires increased spending on social services, making the budgetary situation worse. It is not just government capital spending which can improve long-run fiscal prospects, as can investment in human capital by households. The point is that government current spending can have multiplier effects on incomes and thus on the fiscal position; there is no such equivalent for households. The fallacy is to use a microeconomic metaphor, tapping into the public’s personal experience, for a macroeconomic problem.

A further rhetorical device is to make the recipients of austerity feel responsible for their plight. It is a clear implication of mainstream economics that (barring market imperfections) workers are paid low wages because of the low value of what they produce, or are capable of producing. Similarly, unemployment is portrayed as an unwillingness to search adequately, move location, acquire appropriate skills, or accept the lower wage appropriate to that worker’s VMP. Vulnerable household borrowers, further, are portrayed as having been greedy and profligate, when in fact banks had had a duty of care not to make loans without a reasonable expectation that they could be serviced. Of course, this can be explained to some extent by banks’ buying into the expectation of continued asset price rises purveyed by ‘technical’ economics and finance experts, such that they had not appreciated the risks for them or their clients.

Psychology clearly plays an important role in rhetoric, as in cognition more generally. Reference Smith and BryceSmith ([1762–1763] 1983) pointed to the importance of bearing in mind the beliefs and prior knowledge of the audience. This explains the effectiveness of the household metaphor. Smith also stressed the importance for successful rhetoric of appealing to what the audience would find psychologically satisfying (given that knowledge is sought to calm any sense of discomfort at unexplained events; see further Reference Smith and WightmanSmith [1795] 1980). He was fully aware of the aesthetic attractions of abstract argument, however, misleading it may be:

It gives us a pleasure to see the phenomena which we reckoned the most unaccountable as deduced from some principle (commonly a well-known one) and all united in one chain … We need not be surprised then that the Cartesian Philosophy … tho it does not perhaps contain a word of truth, … should nevertheless have been so universally received by all the Learned in Europe at that time. The Great Superiority of the method over that of Aristotle … made them greedily receive a work which we justly esteem one of the most entertaining Romances that has ever been wrote. (Reference Smith and BryceSmith, [1762–1763] 1983: 146)

Furthermore, Smith distinguished between the natural and social sciences in terms of how far, on the strength of their own specialist expertise, they could sustain their theories in the face of contrary arguments. He maintained that the natural sciences were protected from much public scrutiny because their theories are far removed from normal experience:

Natural philosophers, in their independency upon the public opinion, approach nearly to mathematicians, and, in their judgments concerning the merit of their own discoveries and observations, enjoy some degree of the same security and tranquillity. (Reference Smith, Raphael and MacfieSmith, [1759] 1976: III.2.20)

But as far as moral philosophy, and thus the social sciences, was concerned, he predicted that they would be held in check by the fact that the public understood the subject matter:

A system of natural philosophy may appear very plausible, and be for a long time very generally received in the world, and yet have no foundation in nature, nor any sort of resemblance to the truth … But it is otherwise with systems of moral philosophy and an author who pretends to account for the origin of our moral sentiments, cannot deceive us so grossly, nor depart so very far from all resemblance to the truth. (Reference Smith, Raphael and MacfieSmith, [1759] 1976: VII.ii.4.14)

The device of mimicking the natural sciences and mathematics has allowed mainstream economics a degree of immunity from critique which Smith had not thought possible for economics. A key element of that device has been to present economic results as independent from moral sentiments.

Conclusion

While the importance of putting forward arguments against austerity has been used by some post-Keynesians as an argument against a focus on methodology (see, for example, Reference Lavoie, Lee and LavoieLavoie, 2012), the conclusion drawn here is that methodological, and indeed epistemological, differences from the mainstream are at the core of the reception of post-Keynesian ideas. The mainstream are rhetorically convincing because their results are presented as scientific, such that debate is diverted to what are seen as the separable areas of ideology, power and ethics. The critique of austerity policies would therefore be strengthened by a critique of this rhetorical (mis)representation of economic theorising. Such a critique could refer to the mainstream epistemological belief that the social world is such as to generate technical, law-like conclusions. But it could also refer to belief in the particular moral judgements embedded in their theories about the nature and consequences of individual behaviour and market forces.

The point is a general one, applicable to any policy advice. Reference Von HayekVon Hayek ([1974] 1989) in his Nobel lecture address criticised the notion of the economic expert with a ‘pretence of knowledge’. The post-Keynesian arguments against austerity reflect a belief that markets are not generally beneficial and rely on support from the state, something which Hayek did not share. His policy stance was based on the opposite belief. But, although the direction his ideas took differed markedly from that of Keynes and the post-Keynesians, he like Keynes had been profoundly influenced by Hume’s epistemology. For him too, the limits to knowledge meant the limited applicability of formal mathematical argument, the need for other methods, and the inability to demonstrate economic propositions to be true.

The point is that mainstream economics, just like heterodox economics, bases its policy advice on a structure of beliefs, so that austerity policies need to be understood and critically addressed with that in mind. This point can be made from the standpoint of any set of beliefs. But, as things stand, there is an asymmetry between arguments against austerity which openly combine beliefs and technical analysis on the one hand, and arguments for austerity put forward as if they arose from a purely technical analysis on the other. Post-Keynesians have reason and evidence aplenty in support of their critique of austerity policies for current conditions. But they are being denied due attention by the false perception that they are less ‘scientific’ than the mainstream. It is important to bring the debate onto a level playing field where all accept the inevitable role of belief in their theories and arguments, given the open-system nature of the subject matter, and are prepared to be explicit about this. Ideology matters. But we need to understand ontology, epistemology and methodology in order to analyse the effect of powerful interests on public understanding.

Acknowledgement

This paper has benefited from comments following a presentation of an earlier version (entitled ‘Belief in Austerity Policies’) to the Annual Conference of the PKSG at SOAS, May 2014, and from Geoff Harcourt, John Woods and two anonymous referees.

Funding

Research for this article received no funding support.

Footnotes

1. The aberration of fiscal stimulus in the immediate onset of crisis is generally justified, if at all, as a temporary expedient requiring speedy reversal.

2. There is a large literature challenging austerity policies from a heterodox perspective, of which just a few examples are Reference SawyerSawyer (2012), Reference BoyerBoyer (2012), Reference Palley and HornPalley and Horn (eds) (2013) and Reference BlythBlyth (2013). These arguments are put in historical context by Reference KonzelmannKonzelmann’s (2014) account of the socio–political–economic environment within which ideas about austerity policies have evolved.

3. Scientism is the belief that scientific method, as understood to be practised by the physical sciences, has universal validity.

4. Reference DavidsonDavidson’s (2012) concept of a non-ergodic system captures much of the meaning of an open system.

References

Ball, L, Mankiw, NG (1996) What do budget deficits do? NBER working paper no. 5263. Cambridge, MA: The National Bureau of Economic Research.Google Scholar
Blaug, M (1980) The Methodology of Economics, or How Economists Explain. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Blyth, M (2013) Austerity: The History of a Dangerous Idea. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Boumans, M, Davis, JB (2010) Economic Methodology: Understanding Economics as a Science. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Boyer, R (2012) The four fallacies of contemporary austerity policies: the lost Keynesian legacy. Cambridge Journal of Economics 36(1): 283312.Google Scholar
Buchanan, M (2013) Forecast: What Physics, Meteorology and the Natural Sciences Can Teach Us about Economics. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Callinicos, A (2012) Contradictions of austerity. Cambridge Journal of Economics 36(1): 6578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chick, V (1995) ‘Order out of chaos’ in economics. In: Dow, S, Hillard, J (eds) Keynes, Knowledge and Uncertainty. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, pp. 2542.Google Scholar
Chick, V, Pettifor, A (2010) The Economic Consequences of Mr Osborne. Fiscal Consolidation: Lessons from a Century of UK Macroeconomic Statistics. London: PRIME Publications.Google Scholar
Colander, D (2002) The lost art of economics. Journal of Economic Perspectives 6(3): 191198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, P (2012) Is economics a science? Should economics be rigorous? Real-world Economics Review 59. Available at: http://econ.bus.utk.edu/documents/davidsonpapers/realworld%20econrview(2).pdf (accessed 10 October 2014).Google Scholar
Dow, SC ([1995] 2012) Uncertainty about uncertainty. In: Dow, S, Hillard, J (eds) Keynes, Knowledge and Uncertainty. Aldershot: Edward Elgar, pp. 117–27 (Reprinted in Dow S Foundations for New Economic Thinking: A Collection of Essays. London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp.72–82).Google Scholar
Dow, SC (2002) Economic Methodology: An Inquiry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dow, SC (2013) ‘Mark Blaug on Formalism and Reality: the case of behavioural economics’, Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, 6(3): 2643. http://ejpe.org/pdf/6-3-art-2.pdf Google Scholar
Gabor, D (2010) Central Banking and Financialization. London: Palgrave.Google Scholar
Hands, DW (2001) Reflection without Rules: Economic Methodology and Contemporary Science Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herndon, T, Ash, M, Pollin, R (2014) Does high public debt consistently stifle economic growth? A critique of Reinhart and Rogoff. Cambridge Journal of Economics 38(2): 257279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D ([1739–1740] 1978) A Treatise of Human Nature (ed Selby-Bigge, KA, Nedditch, PH). 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Kayatekin, SA (2014) The relation of morality to political economy in Hume. Cambridge Journal of Economics 38(3): 605622.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keynes, JM (1921) A Treatise on Probability (Reprinted in Collected Writings, 1973). vol. VIII. London: Macmillan for the Royal Economic Society.Google Scholar
Keynes, JM ([1934] 1973) The General Theory and After. Part I: Preparation: Collected Writings. vol. XIII. London: Macmillan for the Royal Economic Society.Google Scholar
Konzelmann, SJ (2014) The political economics of austerity. Cambridge Journal of Economics 38(4): 701741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lavoie, M (2012) After the crisis: Perspectives for post-Keynesian economics. In: Lee, F, Lavoie, M (eds) In Defense of Post-Keynesian Economics and Heterodox Economics: Response to their Critics. London: Routledge, pp. 1841.Google Scholar
Lawson, T (1997) Economics and Reality. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lawson, T (2003) Reorienting Economics. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lawson, T (2009) The current economic crisis: its nature and the course of academic economics. Cambridge Journal of Economics 33(4): 759777.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lucas, RE Jr (1980) Methods and problems in business cycle theory. Journal of Money Credit and Banking 12: 696715.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, DN (1986) The Rhetoric of Economics. Brighton: Wheatsheaf.Google Scholar
Mankiw, RG, Taylor, MP (2006) Economics. London: Thomson.Google Scholar
Mercille, M (2014) The role of the media in fiscal consolidation programmes: The case of Ireland. Cambridge Journal of Economics 38(2): 281300.Google Scholar
Mirowski, P (1989) More Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics, Physics as Nature’s Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Palley, TI, Horn, GA (eds) (2013) Restoring Shared Prosperity: A Policy Agenda from Leading Keynesian Economists. Berlin: Hans Boeckler Foundation. Available: http://www.boeckler.de/pdf/p_restoring_shared_prosperity.pdf (accessed 29 December 2014).Google Scholar
Parkin, M, Powell, M, Matthews, K (2012) Economics (European edition). 8th ed. London: Pearson.Google Scholar
Pigeon, MA (2008) Conflict, consensus, convention: The depoliticization of Canada’s macroeconomic discourse. PhD Thesis, Carleton University, Ottawa, ON, Canada.Google Scholar
Popper, K (1963) Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Reinhart, CM, Rogoff, KS (2010) Growth in a time of debt. American Economic Review 100(2): 573578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rokeach, M (1960) The Open and Closed Mind: Investigations into the Nature of Belief Systems and Personality Systems. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Sawyer, M (2012) The tragedy of UK fiscal policy in the aftermath of the financial crisis. Cambridge Journal of Economics 36(1): 205222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shiller, R (2013) Is economics a science? The Guardian economics blog, 6 November. Available at: http://www.theguardian.com/business/economics-blog/2013/nov/06/is-economics-a-science-robert-shiller (accessed 10 June 2014).Google Scholar
Smith, A ([1759] 1976) The Theory of Moral Sentiments (Glasgow edition; ed Raphael, DD, Macfie, A). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, A ([1762–1763] 1983) Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres (ed Bryce, JC). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, A ([1795] 1980) The history of astronomy. In: Wightman, WLD (ed.) Essays on Philosophical Subjects. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 33105.Google Scholar
Stretton, P (1969) The Political Sciences: General Principles of Selection in Social Science and History. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Von Hayek, FA ([1974] 1989) The pretence of knowledge: Nobel memorial lecture. American Economic Review 79(6): 37.Google Scholar