Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-68ccn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-12T09:45:03.643Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Data making as a paradigm-directed activity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2009

John A. Vasquez
Affiliation:
Vanderbilt University, Tennessee
Get access

Summary

The proposition

Kuhn's analysis

Kuhn (1970a: ch. 3) explicitly states that fact gathering (i.e., data making) in normal science is guided by the dominant paradigm in the field; such guidance is necessary because the world consists of numerous phenomena, and phenomena only take on meaning to the extent that they are conceptualized. Conceptualization, as pointed out earlier, is a function of theory construction or paradigm articulation. Facts, then, presuppose a paradigm that sifts through the welter of phenomena to focus on what is important. In the pre-paradigm stage of science, fact gathering tends to be random because there is no single paradigm to distinguish the chaff from the wheat (Kuhn 1970a: 16–17). In normal science, however, fact gathering becomes highly directed, not only because the paradigm focuses on certain phenomena, but because fact gathering usually “consumes much time, equipment, and money” (Kuhn 1970a: 25). Consequently, the gathering of facts becomes a highly selective activity.

According to Kuhn (1970a: 25–27), three types of facts are gathered. The first consists of those that the paradigm has shown to be of great importance for revealing the nature of things. The second, which is a smaller set, consists of those facts that, although they are not intrinsically important, can be used to test certain predictions from paradigm theory. Finally, the third class of facts, which Kuhn considers most important, consists of those facts that were not originally central to the paradigm but subsequently become important because of paradigm articulation.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Power of Power Politics
From Classical Realism to Neotraditionalism
, pp. 77 - 103
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×