Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-qs9v7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-15T11:26:13.258Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Self-disturbance in schizophrenia: hyperreflexivity and diminished self-affection

from Part III - Disturbances of the self: the case of schizophrenia

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 December 2009

Louis A. Sass
Affiliation:
Rutgers University, Piscataway, NJ, USA
Tilo Kircher
Affiliation:
Eberhard-Karls-Universität Tübingen, Germany
Anthony David
Affiliation:
Institute of Psychiatry, London
Get access

Summary

Abstract

The present chapter offers a unifying but nonreductive interpretation of schizophrenia, one that attempts to show how the diverse signs and symptoms of this illness may all be rooted in certain fundamental alterations in the acts of consciousness that constitute both self and world. Schizophrenia, I argue, can best be understood as a two-faceted disturbance of self-experience. Phenomena that would normally be inhabited – and in this sense experienced as part of the self – come instead to be taken as objects of focal or objectifying awareness (hyperreflexivity). Intimately connected with this development is a profound weakening of the sense of existing as a subject of awareness, as a presence for oneself and before the world (diminished self-affection). Both facets imply a key disturbance of ipseity, i.e. of the basic sense of existing as a vital and self-coinciding subject of experience or first-person perspective on the world. (Ipse is Latin for self or itself.)

To explain the nature of this self-disturbance, I borrow the philosopher Merleau-Ponty's concept of the intentional arc along with Michael Polanyi's notion of an experiential continuum stretching between the object of awareness and what has a more tacit form of existence. I also distinguish between compensatory, consequential and more basic forms of hyperreflexivity. I consider the positive, negative and disorganized syndromes or types of schizophrenic symptom; and attempt, in each case, to illuminate the role of shared disturbances of consciousness and the sense of self.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

American Psychiatric Association. (1994). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-IV). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Press
Andreasen, N. (1979). Thought, language, and communication disorders: I. Archives of General Psychiatry, 36, 1315–21Google Scholar
Andreasen, N. (1984). The Broken Brain: The Biological Revolution in Psychiatry. New York: Harper and Row
Andreasen, N. (1999). A unitary model of schizophrenia: Bleuler's ‘fragmented phrene’ as schizencephaly. Archives of General Psychiatry, 56, 781–7Google Scholar
Angyal, A. (1936). The experience of the body-self in schizophrenia. Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry, 35, 1029–53Google Scholar
Angyal, A. (1964). Disturbances of thinking in schizophrenia. In Language and Thought in Schizophrenia, ed. J. S. Kasanin, pp. 115–23. New York: Norton
Arieti, S. (1978). Volition and value: a study based on catatonic schizophrenia. In On Schizophrenia, Phobias, Depression, Psychotherapy, and the Farther Shores of Psychiatry, ed. S. Arieti, pp. 109–20. New York: Brunner/Mazel
Armbruster, B. & Klosterkoetter, J. (1986). Basic versus negative symptoms. In Biological Psychiatry 1985, ed. C. Shagass, R. C. Josiassen, W. H. Bridger et al. pp. 1148–50. New York: Elsevier
Armstrong, D. M. (1993). A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge
Artaud, A. (1965). Antonin Artaud Anthology, ed. J. Hirschman. San Francisco, CA: City Lights Books
Artaud, A. (1976). Antonin Artaud: Selected Writings, ed. S. Sontag, translated by H. Weaver. New York: Farrar, Straus, & Giroux
Berenbaum, H., & Oltmanns, T. F. (1992). Emotional experience and expression in schizophrenia and depression. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 101, 37–44Google Scholar
Bernet, R., Kern, I. & Marbach, E. (1993). An Introduction to Husserlian Phenomenology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press
Berrios, G E. (1985). Positive and negative symptoms and Jackson. Archives of General Psychiatry, 42, 95–7Google Scholar
Blankenburg, W. (1969). Ansätze zu einer Pschopathologie des ‘common sense’. Confinia Psychiatrica, 12, 144–63. [First steps toward a psychopathology of ‘common sense’, English translation in Philosophy, Psychiatry, Psychology, 8, 303–15.(2001).]Google Scholar
Blankenburg, W. (1991). La Perte de l'Evidence Naturelle: Une Contribution a la Psychopathologie des Schizophrenies Pauci-Symptomatiques. Translated by J.-M. Azorin & Y. Totoyan. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Originally published in 1971: Der Verlust der Naturlichen Selbstverstandlichkeit: Ein Beitrag zur Psychopathologie Symptomarmer Schizophrenien. Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enke Verlag
Bleuler, E. (1950). Dementia Praecox, or The Group of Schizophrenias. Translated by J. Zinkin. New York: International Universities Press
Bleuler, M. (1978). The Schizophrenic Disorders. Translated by S. M. Clemens. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
Bouricius, J K. (1989). Negative symptoms and emotions in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 15, 201–7Google Scholar
Breier, A., & Strauss, J S. (1983). Self-control in psychotic disorders. Archives of General Psychiatry, 40, 1141–5Google Scholar
Cahill, C. & Frith, C D (1996a). A cognitive basis for the signs and symptoms of schizophrenia. In Schizophrenia: A Neuropsychological Perspective, ed. C. Pantelis, H. E. Nelson & T. R. E. Barnes, pp. 373–95. New York: John Wiley
Cahill, C. & Frith, C. D. (1996b). False perceptions or false beliefs? Hallucinations and delusions in schizophrenia. In Method in Madness: Case Studies in Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, ed. P. W. Halligan & J. C. Marshall, pp. 267–91. Howe, East Sussex, UK: Erlbaum
Clark, M. J. (1981). The rejection of psychological approaches to mental disorder in late nineteenth-century British psychiatry. In Madhouses, Mad-Doctors, and Madmen: The Social History of Psychiatry in the Victorian Era, ed. A. Scull, pp. 271–312. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press
Costello, C G. (1992). Research on symptoms versus research on syndromes: arguments in favour of allocating more research time to the study of symptoms. British Journal of Psychiatry, 160, 304–8Google Scholar
Cutting, J. (1985). The Psychology of Schizophrenia. Edinburgh: Churchill Livingstone
Cutting, J. (1990). The Right Cerebral Hemisphere and Psychiatric Disorders. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Cutting, J., & Murphy, D. (1988). Schizophrenic thought disorder: a psychological and organic interpretation. British Journal of Psychiatry, 152, 310–19Google Scholar
Cutting, J., & Murphy, D. (1990). Impaired ability of schizophrenics, relative to manics or depressives, to appreciate social knowledge about their culture. British Journal of Psychiatry, 157, 355–8Google Scholar
Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes' Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Avon Books
Damasio, A. R. (1999). The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. New York: Harcourt Brace
Dillon, M. (1997). Merleau-Ponty's Ontology, 2nd edn. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press
Ey, H. (1973). Traité des Hallucinations. Paris: Masson
Fenton, W. S., & McGlashan, T. (1991). Natural history of schizophrenia subtypes: II. Positive and negative symptoms and long-term course. Archives of General Psychiatry, 48, 978–86Google Scholar
Frith, C D. (1979). Consciousness, information processing, and schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 134, 225–35Google Scholar
Frith, C D. (1987). The positive and negative symptoms of schizophrenia reflect impairments in perception and initiation of action. Psychological Medicine, 17, 631–48Google Scholar
Frith, C. (1992). The Cognitive Neuropsychology of Schizophrenia. Hove, UK: Lawrence Erlbaum
Frith, C. D., & Done, D J. (1989). Experiences of alien control in schizophrenia reflect a disorder in central monitoring of action. Psychological Medicine, 19, 359–63Google Scholar
Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S.-J., & Wolpert, D M (2000). Explaining the symptoms of schizophrenia: abnormalities in the awareness of action. Brain Research Reviews, 31, 357–63Google Scholar
Gallagher, S. (1997). Mutual enlightenment: recent phenomenology in cognitive science. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 4, 195–214Google Scholar
Gallagher, S. (2000). Philosophical concepts of the self: implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Science, 4, 1–35Google Scholar
Gallagher, S. & Meltzoff, A. (1996). The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau-Ponty and recent developmental studies. Philosophical Psychology, 9, 211–33Google Scholar
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin
Gibson, E. J. (1993). Ontogenesis of the perceived self. In The Perceived Self, ed. U. Neisser, pp. 25–42. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
Goldman-Rakic, P. (1994). Working memory dysfunction in schizophrenia. Journal of Neuropsychiatry and Clinical Neurosciences, 6, 348–57Google Scholar
Gottesman, I. (1991). Schizophrenia Genesis: The Origins of Madness. New York: W. H. Freeman
Gray, J. A., Feldon, J., Rawlins, J. N., Hemsley, D. R., & Smith, A. D. (1991). The neuropsychology of schizophrenia. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14, 1–20Google Scholar
Grene, M. (1968). Tacit knowing and the pre-reflective cogito. In Intellect and Hope: Essays in the Thought of Michael Polanyi, ed. T. A. Langford & W. H. Poteat, pp. 19–57. Durham, NC: Duke University Press
Gross, G. (1986). The Bonn scale for the assessment of basic symptoms. In Biological Psychiatry 1985, ed. C. Shagass, R. C. Josiassen, W. H. Bridger et al. pp. 1142–4. New York: Elsevier
Hafner, H., Maurer, K., Loeffler, W., et al. (1998). The ABC schizophrenia study: a preliminary overview of the results. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology, 33, 380–6Google Scholar
Handest, P. (2002). The Prodromes of schizophrenia. Doctoral dissertation. In Danish with English summary. Copenhagen: medical faculty, University of Copenhagen
Hemsley, D. R. (1987). An experimental psychological model for schizophrenia. In Search for the Causes of Schizophrenia, vol. 1, ed. H. Hafner, W. F. Gattaz, & W. Janzarik, pp. 179–88. New York: Springer
Hemsley, D. R. (1998). The disruption of the ‘sense of self’ in schizophrenia: potential links with disturbances of information processing. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 71, 115–24Google Scholar
Henry, M. (1973). The Essence of Manifestation. Translated by G. Etzkorn. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. Original in 1963: L'Essence de la Manifestation. Paris: PUF
Hoenig, J. (1983). The concept of schizophrenia: Kraepelin–Bleuler–Schneider. British Journal of Psychiatry, 142, 547–56Google Scholar
Hoffman, R. (1986). Verbal hallucinations and language production processes in schizophrenia. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 9, 503–48Google Scholar
Hoffman, R., Kirstein, L., Stopek, S., & Cichetti, D. (1982). Apprehending schizophrenic discourse: a structural analysis of the listener's task. Brain and Language, 15, 207–33Google Scholar
Holzman, P. S., Shenton, M. E., & Solovay, M R. (1986). Quality of thought disorder in differential diagnosis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 12, 360–72Google Scholar
Huber, G. (1986). Negative or basic symptoms in schizophrenia and affective illness. In Biological Psychiatry 1985, ed. C. Shagass, R. C. Josiassen, W. H. Bridger et al., pp. 1136–41. New York: Elsevier
Hunt, H T. (1985). Cognition and states of consciousness. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 60, 239–82Google Scholar
Hunt, H. T. (1995). On the Nature of Consciousness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
Hurlbut, R. T. (1990). Sampling Normal and Schizophrenic Inner Experience. New York: Plenum
Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, vol. 2. Translated by R. Rojcewicz & A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer
James, W. (1981). The Principles of Psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Jaspers, K. (1963). General Psychopathology. Translated by J. Hoenig & M. W. Hamilton. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Johnson, R. (1978). The Anatomy of Hallucinations. Chicago: Nelson Hall
Johnstone, E. C., & Frith, C D. (1996). Validation of three dimensions of schizophrenic symptoms in a large unselected sample of patients. Psychological Medicine, 26, 669–79Google Scholar
Kim, Y., Takemoto, K., Mayahara, K., Sumida, K., & Shiba, S. (1994). An analysis of the subjective experience of schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 35, 430–6Google Scholar
Klosterkötter, J. (1992). The meaning of basic symptoms for the development of schizophrenic psychoses. Neurology, Psychiatry, and Brain Research, 1, 30–41Google Scholar
Klosterkötter, J., Gross, G., Huber, G., et al. (1997). Evaluation of the ‘Bonn Scale for the Assessment of Basic Symptoms’ (BSABS) as an instrument for the assessment of schizophrenia proneness. Neurology, Psychiatry, and Brain Research, 5, 137–50Google Scholar
Koehler, K., & Sauer, H. (1984). Huber's basic symptoms: another approach to negative psychopathology in schizophrenia. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 25, 174–82Google Scholar
Kring, A. M., & Neale, J. (1996). Do schizophrenic patients show a disjunctive relationship among expressive, experiential, and psychophysiological components of emotion? Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 105, 249–57Google Scholar
Kring, A. M., Kerr, S. L., Smith, D. A., et al. (1993). Flat affect in schizophrenia does not reflect diminished subjective experience of emotion. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 102, 507–17Google Scholar
Lang, J. (1938). The other side of hallucinations. American Journal of Psychiatry, 94, 1089–97Google Scholar
Liddle, P F. (1987). The symptoms of chronic schizophrenia: a re-examination of the positive–negative dichotomy. British Journal of Psychiatry, 151, 145–51Google Scholar
Liddle, P. F., Carpenter, W. T. & Crow, T. (1994). Syndromes of schizophrenia: classic literature. British Journal of Psychiatry, 165, 721–7Google Scholar
Maj, M. (1998). Critique of the DSM-IV operational diagnostic crireria for schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 172, 458–60Google Scholar
Marneros, A., Andreasen, N. C. & Tsuang, M. T. (eds) (1991). Negative versus Positive Schizophrenia. Berlin: Springer-Verlag
McClamrock, R. (1995). Existential Cognition: Computational Minds in the World. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
McGhie, A., & Chapman, J. (1961). Disorders of attention and perception in early schizophrenia. British Journal of Medical Psychology, 34, 103–15Google Scholar
McGlashan, T H. (1982). Aphanasis: the phenomenon of pseudo-depression in schizophrenia. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 8, 118–34Google Scholar
McGlashan, T. H., & Fenton, W S. (1992). The positive–negative distinction in schizophrenia: review of natural history indicators. Archives of General Psychiatry, 49, 63–72Google Scholar
McKenna, P. J. (1994). Schizophrenia and Related Syndromes. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press
Mellor, C S. (1970). First rank symptoms of schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry, 117, 15–23Google Scholar
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945). Phenomenologie de la Perception. Paris: Gallimard
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). The Phenomenology of Perception. Translated by C. Smith. New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Mlakar, J., Jensterle, J., & Frith, C D. (1994). Central monitoring deficiency and schizophrenic symptoms. Psychological Medicine, 24, 557–64Google Scholar
Mojtabai, R., & Rieder, R O. (1998). Limitations of the symptom-oriented approach to psychiatric research. British Journal of Psychiatry, 173, 198–202Google Scholar
Naudin, J., Banovic, I., Schwartz, M. A., et al. (2000). Définir l'hallucination acoustico-verbale comme trouble de la conscience de soi. Evolution Psychiatrique, 65, 311–24Google Scholar
Ostwald, p. & Zavarin, V. (1980). Studies of language and schizophrenia in the USSR. In Applied Psycholinguistics and Mental Health, ed. R. W. Rieber, pp. 69–92. New York: Plenum
Parnas, J., & Bovet, P. (1991). Autism in schizophrenia revisited. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 32, 7–21Google Scholar
Parnas, J. & Sass, L. (2001). Self, solipsism, and schizophrenic delusions. Philosophy, Psychiatry, Psychology, 8, 101–20Google Scholar
Persons, J. (1986). The advantages of studying psychological phenomena rather than psychiatric diagnoses. American Psychologist, 41, 1252–60Google Scholar
Petitot, J., Varela, F. J., Pachoud, B. & Roy, J.-M. (eds) (1999). Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
Polanyi, M. (1964). Personal Knowledge. New York: Harper Torchbooks
Polanyi, M. (1967). The Tacit Dimension. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books
Polanyi, M. (1968). Sense-giving and sense-reading. In Intellect and Hope: Essays in the Thought of Michael Polanyi, ed. T. A. Langford & W. H. Poteat, pp. 402–31. Durham, NC: Duke University Press
Ricoeur, P. (1992). Oneself as Another, translated by K. Blamey. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
Rosenthal, D. M. (1997). A theory of consciousness. In The Nature of Consciousness, ed. N. Block, O. Flanagan & G. Guzeldere, pp. 729–53. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Rumke, H. C. (1990 [1941]). The nuclear symptom of schizophrenia and the praecox feeling. History of Psychiatry, 1, 331–41Google Scholar
Sass, L. (1992). Madness and Modernism: Insanity in the Light of Modern Art, Literature, and Thought. New York: Basic Books (Harvard University Press peperback, 1994)
Sass, L. (1994). The Paradoxes of Delusion: Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the Schizophrenic Mind. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
Sass, L. (1996). ‘The catastrophes of heaven’: modernism, primitivism, and the madness of Antonin Artaud. Modernism/Modernity, 3, 73–92Google Scholar
Sass, L. (2000). Schizophrenia, self-experience, and the so-called ‘negative symptoms.’ In Exploring the Self: Philosophical and Psychopathological Perspectives on Self-experience, ed. D. Zahavi, pp. 149–82. Amsterdam: John Benjamins
Sass, L., & Parnas, J. (2001). Phenomenology of self disturbances in schizophrenia: some research findings and directions. Philosophy, Psychiatry, Psychology, 8, 347–56Google Scholar
Sass, L. & Parnas, J. (in press). Explaining schizophrenia: the relevance of phenomenology. In The Philosophical Understanding of Schizophrenia, ed. M. C. Chung, K. W. M. Fulford & G. Graham. Oxford: Oxford University Press
Schwartz, S. (1982). Is there a schizophrenic language? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 5, 579–88Google Scholar
Selten, J. P. (1995). The Subjective Experience of Negative Symptoms. Doctoral dissertation. Rijksuniversiteit Groningen, The Netherlands
Selten, J.-P., van den Bosch, R. J. & Sijben, A. E. S. (1998). The subjective experience of negative symptoms. In Insight and Psychosis, ed. X. F. Amador & A. S. David, pp. 78–90. New York: Oxford University Press
Selten, J.-P., Wiersma, D., & Bosch, R J. (2000). Discrepancy between subjective and objective ratings for negative symptoms. Journal of Psychiatric Research, 34, 11–13Google Scholar
Sokolov, A. N. (1972). Inner Speech and Thought. New York: Plenum
Solovay, M. R., Shenton, M. E., & Holzman, P S. (1987). Comparative studies of thought disorder: mania and schizophrenia. Archives of General Psychiatry, 44, 13–20Google Scholar
Sommers, A A. (1985). Negative symptoms: conceptual and methodological problems. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 11, 364–79Google Scholar
Spitzer, M. (1997). A cognitive neuroscience view of schizophrenic thought disorder. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 23, 29–50Google Scholar
Stanghellini, G., & Monti, M R. (1993). Influencing and being influenced: the other side of ‘bizarre delusions.’ Psychopathology, 26, 165–9Google Scholar
Storring, G. (1987). Perplexity. In The Clinical Roots of the Schizophrenia Concept, ed. J. Cutting & M. Shepherd, pp. 79–82. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press
Tatossian, A. (1997). La Phenomenologie des psychoses. Paris: L'Art du Comprendre.
Tausk, V. (1933 [1919]). On the origin of the ‘influencing machine’ in schizophrenia. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 2, 519–56Google Scholar
Tissot, T. (1984). Fonction Symbolique et Psychopathologie. Paris: Masson
van den Bosch, R. (1994). Context and cognition in schizophrenia. In Advances in the Neurobiology of Schizophrenia, ed. J. A. den Boer, H. G. M. Westenberg & H. M. van Praag. pp. 343–66. Chichester, UK: Wiley. Available at http://www.psy.med.rug.nl/0014
Bosch, R. J., Rombouts, R. P., & Asma, M. J. O. (1993). Subjective cognitive dysfunction in schizophrenic and depressed patients. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 34, 130–6Google Scholar
Vygotsky, L. (1962). Thought and Language. Translated by E. Hanfmann & G. Vakar. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Zahavi, D. (1999). Michel Henry and the phenomenology of the invisible. Continental Philosophy Review, 32, 223–40Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×