Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-qs9v7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T03:30:11.533Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Toward a mechanistic Evo Devo

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 June 2009

Manfred D. Laubichler
Affiliation:
Arizona State University
Jane Maienschein
Affiliation:
Arizona State University
Get access

Summary

I have acquired the conviction that our biological theories must remain inadequate so long as we confine ourselves to the study of cells and persons and leave the psychologists, sociologists, and metaphysicians to deal with complex organisms.

W. M. Wheeler (1911)

INTRODUCTION: TWO DISTINCTIONS

Manfred Laubichler's contribution to this volume contains a subtle argument to the conclusion that in evolutionary developmental biology (Evo Devo), form and function are both best understood as kinds of causes at different scales that can be brought together in mechanistic explanations of phenotypic evolution. This argument is evocative not only because it leans heavily on mechanistic explanation – about which much more below – but also because there have been long periods during which form was not understood to have a causal aspect. When the phenotype is a passive by-product of evolution, the form does not do much work.

Evo Devo, of course, is partly built around denying the correctness of one-sided explanatory strategies, and thus, if Laubichler is correct, finds itself brushing up against another familiar distinction. When Ernst Mayr (1961) made his cut between proximate and ultimate causation, he recognized two sorts of causes in biology, but minced no words about which he took to be the more important. It is possible, of course, to agree with Mayr's distinction and disagree with him about which kind of causes matter most, just as it is possible to reject the nature–nurture dichotomy and still wonder whether nature or nurture is more important.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bechtel, W. and Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: a mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36, 421–41.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bechtel, W. and Hamilton, A. (2007). Natural, behavioral, social sciences and the humanities: reductionism and the unity of the sciences. In Kuipers, T. (ed.), General Philosophy of Science: Focal Issues. Amsterdam: North Holland, pp. 377–430.Google Scholar
Bechtel, W. and Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering Complexity: Decomposition and Localization as Strategies in Scientific Research. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Darwin, C. R. (1871). The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex. New York: D. Appleton and Company.Google Scholar
Davidson, E. H. and Erwin, D. H. (2006). Gene regulatory networks and the evolution of animal body plans. Science 311, 796–800.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science 69, S342–S353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haber, M. and Hamilton, A. (2005). Coherence, consistency, and cohesion: clade selection in Okasha and beyond. Philosophy of Science 72, 1026–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, A. and Haber, M. (2006). Clades are reproducers. Biological Theory 1, 381–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, A., Smith, N. R., and Haber, M. H. (in press). Social insects and the individuality thesis: cohesion and the colony as a selectable individual. In Gadau, J. and Fewell, J. (eds.), Organization of Insect Societies: From Genome to Sociocomplexity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetic evolution of social behavior. I and II. Journal of Theoretical Biology 7, 1–16, 17–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, W. D. (1967). Extraordinary sex ratios. Science 156, 477–88.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kern Reeve, H. and Hölldobler, B. (2007). The emergence of a superorganism through intergroup competition. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 23, 9736–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewontin, R. C. (2000). The dream of the human genome. In Lewontin, R. C., It Ain't Necessarily So: The Dream of the Human Genome Project and Other Illusions. New York: Basic Books, pp. 135–76.Google Scholar
Machamer, P. K., Darden, L., and Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. (1964). Group selection and kin selection. Nature 201, 145–7.Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. (1974). Group selection. Quarterly Review of Biology 51, 277–83.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1961). Cause and effect in biology. Science 134, 1501–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Michener, C. D. (1974). The Social Behavior of the Bees. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Minelli, A. (2003). The Development of Animal Form: Ontogeny, Morphology, and Evolution. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Page, R. E., Scheiner, R., Erber, J., and Amdam, G. (2006). The development and evolution of division of labor and foraging behavior in a social insect (Apis mellifera L.). Current Topics in Developmental Biology 74, 253–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raff, R. and Sly, B. (2000). Modularity and dissociation in the evolution of gene expression territories in development. Evolution & Development 2, 102–13.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wagner, G. P. (1996). Homologues, natural kinds and the evolution of modularity. American Zoologist 36, 36–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wheeler, W. M. (1911). The ant-colony as an organism. Journal of Morphology 22, 307–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation and Natural Selection. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, D. S. and Sober, E. (1989). Reviving the Superorganism. Journal of Theoretical Biology 136, 337–56.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wimsatt, W. C. (1974). Complexity and organization. Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (1972), 67–86.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W. C. (1976). Reductive explanation: a functional account. Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (1974), 671–710.Google Scholar
Wynne-Edwards, V. C. (1962). Animal Dispersion in Relation to Social Behaviour. New York: Hafner.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×