Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-cnmwb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-22T13:37:39.176Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Magnanimity, or Classical Virtue

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 November 2009

Ryan Patrick Hanley
Affiliation:
Marquette University, Wisconsin
Get access

Summary

THE PROBLEMS OF PRUDENCE AND THE THERAPY OF MAGNANIMITY

Let us restate the problem to this point. Commerce seems to depend on vanity, yet vanity induces restlessness, anxiety, duplicity, and inauthenticity. Prudence offers a palliative remedy that ameliorates these vices by redirecting, and thus mitigating, the love of esteem inseparable from commerce. Yet such a remedy engenders new ills of its own – particularly individualism and mediocrity, the consequences of prudence's reanimation of the love of acquisition – and hence Smith's dialectical approach to the study of prudence, and indeed to the study of ethical virtue more generally. Smith's balanced account of prudence testifies to his recognition that positing a practical solution to a moral or political problem often induces new problems which in turn require redress. In the case at hand, the reification of self-love encouraged by prudence intensifies the natural propensity to self-preference that it was in fact intended to ameliorate. As a consequence, Smith must now confront a new set of challenges – challenges that are both original to the corruption induced by commercial society and exacerbated by prudence. Chief among these are the ills of self-preference, or individualism, and mediocrity, or an indifference to excellence and nobility. Remedying these two ills is the task of his account of magnanimity.

Stating the problem in these terms is likely to prompt at least two objections, one skeptical of this description of the problem, another skeptical of the solution.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Livingston, Donald, Philosophical Melancholy and Delirium: Hume's Pathology of Philosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), 49–50 and 141–42Google Scholar
Keys, Mary, Aquinas, Aristotle, and the Promise of the Common Good (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 143–72CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lear, Gabriel Richardson, Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004), 168–74Google Scholar
Harkin, , “Natives and Nostalgia: The Problem of the ‘North American Savage’ in Smith's Historiography,” Scottish Studies Review 3 (2001): 21–32Google Scholar
Dent, N. J. H. and O'Hagan, Timothy, “Rousseau on ‘Amour-Propre’,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1999): 93Google Scholar
Schliesser, , “The Obituary of a Vain Philosopher: Adam Smith's Reflections on Hume's Life,” Hume Studies 29 (2003): 327–62Google Scholar
Waterman, A. M. C., “Economics as Theology: Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations,” Southern Economic Journal 68 (2002): 907–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, , “The Hidden Theology of Adam Smith,” European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 8 (2001): 1–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alvey, , “The Secret, Natural Theological Foundation of Adam Smith's Work,” Journal of Markets and Morality 7 (2004): 335–61Google Scholar
Seigel, Jerrold, The Idea of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 144–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Welsh, Alexander, What is Honor? A Question of Moral Imperatives (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2008), 173, 176, 179Google Scholar
Reeder, John, ed., On Moral Sentiments: Contemporary Responses to Adam Smith (Bristol: Thoemmes Press, 1997), 66
Cropsey, , Political Philosophy and the Issues of Politics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977), 87Google Scholar
Aristotle on the Greatness of Greatness of Soul,” History of Political Thought 23 (2002): 1–20
Buchanan, James, “Equality, Hierarchy, and Global Justice,” Social Philosophy and Policy 23 (2006): 255–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, , “The Justice of Natural Liberty,” Journal of Legal Studies 5 (1976): 1–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sympathy and Approbation in Hume and Smith: A Solution to the Other Rational Species Problem,” Economics and Philosophy 20 (2004): esp. 337–39, 346–48
Boltanski, Luc, Distant Suffering: Morality, Media and Politics, trans. Burchell, Graham (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 35–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pitts, Jennifer, A Turn to Empire: The Rise of Imperial Liberalism in Britain and France (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005), 43–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shklar, , Men and Citizens: A Study of Rousseau's Social Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 187–88Google Scholar
Policies Designed for Self-Interested Citizens May Undermine ‘The Moral Sentiments’: Evidence from Economic Experiments,” Science 320 (2008): 1605–9CrossRef
Bowles, et al., eds., Moral Sentiments and Material Interests: The Foundations of Cooperation in Economic Life (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005), esp. 3–4, 31–33
Mansfield, Harvey, Manliness (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2006)Google Scholar
Pangle, , “The Classical and Modern Liberal Understandings of Honor,” in The Noblest Minds: Fame, Honor, and the American Founding, ed. McNamara, (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999), 211Google Scholar
Language, Literature, and Imagination,” Adam Smith Review 4 (2008): 221–30CrossRef
Hayek, F. A., “Adam Smith's Message in Today's Language,” in New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978), 267–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Milton, “Adam Smith's Relevance for 1976,” in Adam Smith and the Wealth of Nations, ed. Glahe, Fred R. (Boulder: Colorado Associated University Press, 1978), 7–20Google Scholar
History of England, ed. Todd, William (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1983), vol. 2, p. 272
Adam Smith's Theoretical Endorsement of Deception,” Adam Smith Review 2 (2006)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×