Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-2l2gl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-05T07:13:12.506Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Making Consciousness Safe for Neuroscience

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2010

Andrew Brook
Affiliation:
Professor of Philosophy and Director, Institute of Cognitive Science, Carleton University
Andrew Brook
Affiliation:
Carleton University, Ottawa
Kathleen Akins
Affiliation:
Simon Fraser University, British Columbia
Get access

Summary

Work on consciousness by neurophilosophers often leaves a certain group of other philosophers frustrated. The latter group of philosophers, which includes people such as Thomas Nagel, Frank Jackson, Colin McGinn, Ned Block, and David Chalmers, believe that consciousness is something quite different from the brain circuitry or other processes that are active in cognition. They feel frustrated because work on consciousness by neurophilosophers usually ignores this view, yet proceeds from an assumption that it is wrong. This work tends to assume, simply assume, that neuroscience not only will identify neural correlates of consciousness (which virtually all parties to the current consciousness debate now accept), but also (perhaps with the assistance of cognitive science) will eventually tell us what consciousness is. That is to say, it assumes that consciousness simply is a neural/cognitive process of some kind. Even more, it assumes that consciousness is a neural/cognitive process similar in kind to the processes that underlie (other aspects of) cognition and representation. That is to say, it assumes that consciousness is an aspect of general cognition.

Consciousness has appeared to be weird and wonderful to many people for a very long time. Daniel Dennett captured the feeling very nicely many years ago: ‘Consciousness appears to be the last bastion of occult properties, epiphenomena, immeasurable subjective states – in short, the one area of mind best left to the philosophers. Let them make fools of themselves trying to corral the quicksilver of “phenomenology” into a respectable theory’ (1978a, p. 149).

Type
Chapter
Information
Cognition and the Brain
The Philosophy and Neuroscience Movement
, pp. 397 - 422
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baars, B. 1988. A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Brook, A. 1975. Imagination, possibility, and personal identity. American Philosophical Quarterly 12, 185–198Google Scholar
Brook, A., and Raymont, P. 2005. Unity of Consciousness. Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.eduGoogle Scholar
Brook, A., and Raymont, P. forthcoming. A Unified Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Brook, A., and Stainton, R. 2000. Knowledge and Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Calvin, Wm. 2003. Review of Zeman (2003). New York Times Book Review, Sept. 28, 2003
Chalmers, D. 1995. Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2, 200–219Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1995. The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 2002. Catching consciousness in a recurrent net. In Brook, Andrew and Ross, Don, eds., Daniel Dennett. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 64–80Google Scholar
Churchland, P. S. 1983. Consciousness: The transmutation of a concept. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 65, 80–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crick, F. 1994. The Astonishing Hypothesis. New York: Scribner'sGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. 1978a. Toward a cognitive theory of consciousness. In his Brainstorms. Montgomery, VT: Bradford Books, pp. 149–173
Dennett, D. 1978b. Why you can't make a computer that feels pain. In his Brainstorms. Montgomery, VT: Bradford Books, pp. 190–232
Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. Boston: Little, BrownGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. 1998. Real consciousness. In his Brainchildren. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 131–140
Dennett, D. 2000. With a little help from my friends. In Ross, D., Brook, A., and Thompson, D., eds., Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 327–388Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 2001. Are we explaining consciousness yet? Cognition 79, 221–237CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Flanagan, O. 1991. Consciousness Reexamined. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Flanagan, O., and Polger, T. 1995. Zombies and the function of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2, 313–321Google Scholar
Jackendoff, R. 1987. Consciousness and the Computational Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/A Bradford BookGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F. 1986. What Mary didn't know. Journal of Philosophy 83, 5, 291–295CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, J. 1983. Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 654, 354–361CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, J. 1690. Essay Concerning Human Understanding. London: BassetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mack, A. (2001). Inattentional blindness: Reply to commentaries. http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/v7/psyche-7-16-mack.htm
Mack, A., and Rock, I. 1998. Inattentional Blindness. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
McGinn, C. 1991. The problem of consciousness: Essays towards a resolution. Oxford: Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. 1974. What it is like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83, 435–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Penrose, R. 1999. The Emperor's New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Perry, J. 1979. The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs 13, 3–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, J. 2001. Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Polger, T. 2000. Zombies explained. In Ross, D., Brook, A., and Thompson, D., eds., Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 259–286Google Scholar
Posner, M. 1994. Attention: The mechanism of consciousness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science USA 91, 7398–7403CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975. The meaning of ‘meaning’. Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215–272CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenthal, D. 1991. The Nature of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. 1980. Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 417–458CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1968. Self-reference and self-awareness. Journal of Philosophy 65, 555–567CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 1995. Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Tye, M. 2003. Qualia. plato.stanford.edu/entries/qualia
Wittgenstein, L. 1953. Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Zeman, A. 2003. Consciousness: A User's Guide. New Haven, CT: Yale University PressGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×