Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-xq9c7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-26T13:14:08.956Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Criticism of connectionist theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 December 2009

Naomi Goldblum
Affiliation:
Bar-Ilan University, Israel
Get access

Summary

Until now I've been presenting the connectionist viewpoint of the way our minds work as if it were generally accepted. This is because, as I noted at the outset, it would have been far too annoying to repeat “according to the connectionists” in every paragraph. But actually this approach has come in for its share of criticism. Well, then, what sorts of criticisms are these? And how do connectionists respond to them?

The representationalists' criticism

Probably the most important criticism comes from a group of philosophers of science who espouse a theory known as “representationalism.” This theory is one of the “classical” theories I mentioned in the Introduction, and two of its most prominent advocates are Jerry Fodor and Zenon Pylyshyn. As an alternative theory of mental processes, it too is complicated and cannot be explained in a few sentences any more than connectionism can. What I will try to do, then, is to point out some of the ways in which representationalism differs from connectionism, so that you can get some idea of what is at stake in the debate between the two camps.

One of the important differences between the two theories is the one that gives them their names. Representationalists claim that every object we see, every sound we hear, every word we learn, is stored in our mind as a separate, point-like representation of that thing. Just as the word cat represents cats, they say, there is a concept CAT inside our mind that represents, somehow, the essence of “cathood.”

Type
Chapter
Information
The Brain-Shaped Mind
What the Brain Can Tell Us About the Mind
, pp. 116 - 128
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×