Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-n9wrp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T13:25:00.059Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

12 - Construction of Preferences by Constraint Satisfaction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Dan Simon
Affiliation:
Professor of Law, University of Southern California
Daniel C. Krawczyk
Affiliation:
Postdoctoral Fellow, University of California, Berkeley
Keith J. Holyoak
Affiliation:
Professor of Psychology, University of California, Los Angeles
Sarah Lichtenstein
Affiliation:
Decision Research. Oregon
Paul Slovic
Affiliation:
Decision Research, Oregon
Get access

Summary

A central tenet of classical theories of rational choice is that people harbor a stable, well-defined, and discernable order of preferences, and have computational skills that enable them to choose the courses of action that maximize their preferences. A paradigmatic example of a classical theory is multiattribute decision theory, which prescribes that the utility of a choice is equivalent to the sum of its preferences, that is, the sum of the weighted values of its attributes (Edwards & Newman, 1982; Keeney & Raiffa, 1976).

Research has challenged the axiom of preference invariance. Rather than being stable, well- defined, and discernable, preferences have been shown to be constructed (Markman, Zhang, & Moreau, 2000; Slovic, 1995); to some degree, they are labile, reversible, and obscure (for a review, see Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1992). Preference invariance is violated under different descriptions of essentially the same options (Tversky & Kahneman, 1986), when different modes of elicitation are invoked (Lichtenstein & Slovic, 1971), and when options are presented in different contexts (Shafir, Simonson, & Tversky, 1993). Various process theories claim that preferences are reconstructed to create dominance and thus bring the decision task to a point of commitment (Janis & Mann, 1977; Montgomery, 1983; Svenson, 1992; for a review, see Brownstein, 2003). These process theories are inconsistent with cognitive dissonance theory, which posits that changes in preferences are exclusively a postcommitment phenomenon (see Festinger, 1964, p. 153; also Simon & Holyoak, 2002).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×