Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-rkxrd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T04:48:57.638Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Epistemology without Knowledge and without Belief

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Jaakko Hintikka
Affiliation:
Boston University
Get access

Summary

Knowledge and Decision-Making

Epistemology seems to enjoy an unexpectedly glamorous reputation in these days. A few years ago, William Safire wrote a popular novel called The Sleeper Spy. It depicts a distinctly post-Cold War world in which it is no longer easy to tell the good guys—including the good spies—from the bad ones. To emphasize this sea change, Safire tells us that his Russian protagonist has not been trained in the military or in the police, as he would have been in the old days, but as an epistemologist.

But is this with-it image deserved? Would the theory of knowledge that contemporary academic epistemologists cultivate be of any help to a sleeper spy? This question prompts a critical survey of the state of the art or, rather, the state of the theory of knowledge. I submit that the up-to-date image is not accurate and that most of the current epistemological literature deals with unproductive and antiquated questions. This failure is reflected in the concepts that are employed by contemporary epistemologists.

What are those concepts? It is usually thought and said that the most central concepts of epistemology are knowledge and belief. The prominence of these two notions is reflected in the existing literature on epistemology. A large chunk of it consists in discussions of how the concept of knowledge is to be defined or is not to be defined. Are those discussions on the target?

Type
Chapter
Information
Socratic Epistemology
Explorations of Knowledge-Seeking by Questioning
, pp. 11 - 37
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Austin, John, 1961(a) (original 1946), “Other Minds,” in Philosophical Papers, Clarendon Press, Oxford, especially pp. 67–68.Google Scholar
Austin, John, 1961(b), “Performative Utterances,” in Philosophical Papers, Clarendon Press, Oxford, ch. 10, especially p. 220.Google Scholar
Bonjour, Laurence, 2002, Epistemology: Classical Problems and Contemporary Responses, Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, Maryland.Google Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan, 1992, Essay on Belief and Acceptance, Clarendon Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
Cohen, Stewart, 1998, “Contextual Solutions to Epistemological Problems,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 76, pp. 289–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collingwood, R. G., 1940, An Essay on Metaphysics, Clarendon Press, Oxford, especially ch. I, sec. 5.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald, 1996, “The Folly of Trying to Define Truth,” Journal of Philosophy, vol. 93, pp. 263–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeRose, Keith, 1995, “Solving the Skeptical Problem,” Philosophical Review, vol. 104, pp. 1–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, John, 1992, Bayes or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory, MIT Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob, 1984 (original 1918–19), “Thoughts,” in Collected Papers, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.Google Scholar
Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 1975 (original 1960), Truth and Method, Continuum, New York, especially the section “Logic of Questions and Answers,” pp. 333–341.Google Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, forthcoming, “Wittgenstein on knowledge and skepticism.”
Hintikka, Jaakko, 2004, “A fallacious fallacy?Synthese vol. 140, pp. 25–35. And as Chapter 9 in this volume.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, 2003 (a), “A Distinction Too Few or Too Many: A Vindication of the Analytic vs. Synthetic Distinction,” in Constructivism and Practice: Toward a Historical Epistemology, Gould, Carol C., editor, Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, Maryland, 47–74.Google Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, 2003(b), “A Second-Generation Epistemic Logic and Its General Significance,” in Hendricks, Vincent F. et al., editors, Knowledge Contributors, Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht, pp. 33–56. And as Chapter 3 in this volume.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, 2002, “Post-Tarskian Truth,” Synthese, vol. 126, pp. 17–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, 1999, Inquiry as Inquiry: A Logic of Scientific Discovery, Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, 1998, “What Is Abduction? The Fundamental Problem of Contemporary Epistemology,” Transactions of the Charles Peirce Society, vol. 34, pp. 503–533. A revised version, “Abduction—Inference, Conjecture, or an Answer to a Question,” appears as Chapter 2 in this volume.Google Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, 1974, Knowledge and the Known, Reidel, Dordrecht.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, and Halonen, Ilpo, 1995, “Semantics and Pragmatics for Why-Questions,” Journal of Philosophy, vol. 92, pp. 636–657.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Husserl, Edmund, 1983 (original 1913), Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology. First Book, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., and Tversky, A., editors, 1982, Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, 1787, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, second edition (see preface, p. xiii).
McCarthy, John 1990, “Circumscription—a Form of Non-Monotonic Reasoning,” Artificial Intelligence, vol. 13, pp. 27–39 and 171–172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montague, Richard, 1974, Formal Philosophy, Yale University Press, New Haven.Google Scholar
Piatelli-Palmarini, Massimo, 1994, Inevitable Illusions, John Wiley & Sons, NewYork.Google Scholar
Plato, 1924, Meno, Plato: with an English Translation, Loeb Classical Library, vol. IV, Harvard University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Ramsey, Frank, 1978 (original 1929), “Knowledge,” in Foundations: Essays in Philosophy, Logic, Mathematics, and Economics, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, pp. 126–127.Google Scholar
Safire, William, 1995, The Sleeper Spy, Random House, New York.Google Scholar
Shope, Robert K., 1983, The Analysis of Knowing: A Decade of Research, Princeton University Press, Princeton.Google Scholar
Tarski, Alfred, 1956 (original 1935), “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages,” in Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp. 152–278.Google Scholar
Williams, Michael, 2001, Problems of Knowledge: A Critical Introduction to Epistemology, Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×