Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-fwgfc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T04:21:31.388Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

10 - Causation and Conditional Probabilities

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 April 2010

Daniel M. Hausman
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin, Madison
Get access

Summary

In chapter 4 I made the operationalizing assumption that there are causal connections among events if and only if there are probabilistic dependencies in the background circumstances among the relevant properties or variables. If this assumption is a reasonable approximation, then the claims about causal asymmetry made in chapters 4–7 have implications concerning probability distributions, which deserve further scrutiny. This chapter begins this scrutiny by exploring David Papineau's theory relating causation to conditional probabilistic dependencies.

The Fork Asymmetry

Suppose event types a and b are probabilistically dependent on one another:

  1. 1. Pr(AB) > Pr(A)·Pr(B).

Suppose further that

  1. 2. a and b are not related as cause and effect.

Then, according to Hans Reichenbach, there exists an event type c satisfying the following conditions:

  1. 3. Pr(AC) > Pr(A)·Pr(C)

  2. 4. Pr(BC) > Pr(B)·Pr(C)

  3. 5. Pr(AB/C) = Pr(A/C)·Pr(B/C)

  4. 6. Pr(AB/~C) = Pr(A/~C)·Pr(B/~C)

  5. 7. Tokens of kind cprecede tokens of kinds a and b.

  6. 8. Tokens of kind c are common causes of tokens of kinds a and b.

The probabilistic dependence between a and b is explained by the existence of the common cause c. Reichenbach proves that if none of the probabilities is one or zero, then 3–6 entail 1. This proof is given in chapter 4*, pp. 76–7.

7 or 8 is called in the literature “the fork asymmetry”: the causal arrows point away from the event type that does the screening-off and toward the future. 7 might be called the temporal fork asymmetry, while 8 might be called the causal fork asymmetry. There can be events of kind c satisfying 3–6 that are common effects of a and b and that succeed them in time, but only when there are also common (preceding) causes.

Type
Chapter
Information
Causal Asymmetries , pp. 207 - 216
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×