Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-wxhwt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-11T12:23:51.873Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Gene marking, recombinant DNA technology, and gene transfer: toward true gene therapy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 March 2010

Get access

Summary

Are human genetic processes sufficiently plastic to permit the development of intraindividual flexibility? Before addressing this question it is useful to consider how thoroughly human genetic endowment ensures systematic interindividual differences. Our genetic endowment provides a basis of the uniqueness of each human life and provides substance to the claim that all humans have a unique heredity–environment interactive history (Hirsch, 1970; Lerner, 1976, 1978, 1979; McClearn, 1981). Estimates of the number of gene pairs in humans typically range between 10,000 and 100,000 (Bodmer & Cavalli-Sfarza, 1976; Stern, 1973), and if one considers how much genotypic variability can be produced by the reshuffling process of meiosis occurring with 100,000 gene pairs, then the potential for variability is so enormous that “it is next to impossible that there have ever been two individuals with the same combination of genes” (McClearn, 1981, p. 19).

Indeed, Hirsch (1970) conservatively estimates that there are over 7 × 1017 (70 trillion) potential human genotypes. Bodmer and Cavalli-Sforza (1976) estimate that each human has the capacity to generate any one of 103000 different eggs or sperm; by comparison, their estimate of the number of sperm of all men who have ever lived is only 1024. Thus, considering

103000 possible eggs being generated by an individual woman and 103000 possible sperm being generated by an individual man, the likelihood of anyone ever – in the past, present, or future – having the same genotype as anyone else (excepting multiple identical births, of course) becomes dismissably small

(McClearn, 1981, p. 19).
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×