Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-c9gpj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T01:41:45.442Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

16 - Experimentation and scientific realism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Get access

Summary

Experimental work provides the strongest evidence for scientific realism. This is not because we test hypotheses about entities. It is because entities that in principle cannot be ‘observed’ are regularly manipulated to produce a new phenomena and to investigate other aspects of nature. They are tools, instruments not for thinking but for doing. The philosopher's favourite theoretical entity is the electron. I shall illustrate how electrons have become experimental entities, or experimenter's entities. In the early stages of our discovery of an entity, we may test the hypothesis that it exists. Even that is not routine. When J.J. Thomson realized in 1897 that what he called ‘corpuscles’ were boiling off hot cathodes, almost the first thing he did was to measure the mass of these negatively charged particles. He made a crude estimate of e, the charge, and measured e/m. He got m about right, too. Millikan followed up some ideas already under discussion at Thomson's Cavendish Laboratory, and by 1908 had determined the charge of the electron, that is, the probable minimum unit of electric charge. Hence from the very beginning people were less testing the existence of electrons than interacting with them. The more we come to understand some of the causal powers of electrons, the more we can build devices that achieve well-understood effects in other parts of nature. By the time that we can use the electron to manipulate other parts of nature in a systematic way, the electron has ceased to be something hypothetical, something inferred.

Type
Chapter
Information
Representing and Intervening
Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science
, pp. 262 - 275
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1983

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×