Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-wp2c8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-15T22:22:49.451Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Moral standards and the distinguishing mark of a man

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 April 2013

Bernard Williams
Affiliation:
University of Oxford and University of California, Berkeley
Get access

Summary

A PROTOTYPE of the nontranscendental type is to be found in the philosophy of Aristotle. According to Aristotle, there are certain characteristics, in particular, certain activities and powers, which are distinctive of man, and the life of the good man will exemplify to the fullest degree the development of those powers and activities. Or, more accurately, there is one distinctive feature of man – his ability to shape his actions and dispositions by reason – which will be manifested in the highest degree; other of his potentialities will, under the ordering power of reason, be realized in a balanced way and not each maximally. Practical reason is supposed to produce coherence, and reduce conflict, among the desires of the individual living (as man must live) in society. This aim of reducing conflict between desires, while not inordinately suppressing them, is part of what gives recognizable content to the claim that the aim of the sort of life outlined in Aristotle's system is happiness.

The importance of the harmonization of desires in Aristotle, and of practical reason in securing this, is illustrated in a backhanded way by his notable failure to deal with one problem of reconciliation which, in his own terms, must be important. The ‘reason’ that we have so far referred to is practical reason, which applies to particular actions and desires and which is the ground of what Aristotle (or rather his translators) call ‘virtues of character’ – that is to say, those dispositions to right action which involve motivations of pleasure and pain.

Type
Chapter
Information
Morality
An Introduction to Ethics
, pp. 55 - 62
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×