Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-fv566 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T05:19:44.738Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Ancient Greek science and psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 September 2015

John D. Greenwood
Affiliation:
City University of New York
Get access

Summary

The origins of psychological knowledge may be said to be as old as humankind. From as early as recorded time, men and women have speculated about the nature of psychological states and processes and their relationship to human behavior. Theoretical reflections on sensation, memory, and dreaming, for example, are to be found in many ancient works, such as the Hindu sacred texts known as the Vedas (which precede the first millennium BCE) and the Assyrian “dream books” (from around the fifth millennium BCE).

Many early cultures, such as the Egyptian and Babylonian, tried to understand human psychology and behavior in terms of the activity of some immaterial “spirit” or “soul,” usually intimately associated with breath and the action of the heart and lungs. The Greek term psyche, from which the term psychology is derived, is etymologically tied to words signifying breath (pneuma) or wind. There is nothing especially remarkable about this, for at a basic level of observation, it is obvious that whatever enables the human organism to act in a purposive fashion is intimately associated with the action of the heart and lungs. When activity in these organs ceases, so also does the activity of the human organism.

Many early theories that postulated immaterial spirits or souls also maintained that such entities could enjoy a life after death in some spiritual realm. However, not all early theories were committed to the notion of an afterlife, and for those that were, it was often an impoverished and literally shady sort of thing. In Greek mythology, for example, the dead survived as shadows of their former selves, which could only be temporarily revived via blood sacrifice.

Beliefs in immaterial spirits or souls are often characterized as animistic and are associated with so-called primitive cultures today. However, we should guard against the condescending assumption that all earlier cultures explained mind and behavior in terms of immaterial spirits or souls and that humans came to a proper understanding of these matters only with the development of psychological science, as such assumptions can seriously prejudice our approach to the history of psychology. Although many ancient thinkers did embrace theories about immaterial spirits or souls, their psychological understanding was far more sophisticated – and materialistic – than is usually acknowledged.

Type
Chapter
Information
A Conceptual History of Psychology
Exploring the Tangled Web
, pp. 20 - 40
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Angell, J. R. (1907). The province of functional psychology. Psychological Review, 14, 61–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, J. (1979). The Presocratic Philosophers: Volume 2. Empedocles to Democritus. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1987). Early Greek Philosophy. New York, NY: Penguin.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (Ed.) (1995). The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. (Vols. 1–2.) Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. (1996). The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Euclid. (1977). Euclid's Elements. (Desmore, D., Ed.; Heath, T. H., Trans.) Ann Arbor, MI: Green Lion Press. (Original work from second century BCE.)Google Scholar
Frank, J. D. (1973). Persuasion and Healing. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Green, C. D. (1998). The thoroughly modern Aristotle:was he really a functionalist? History of Psychology, 1, 8–20.Google Scholar
Hamlyn, D. (1968). Introduction. In Hamlyn, D. W. (Trans.), Aristotle's De Anima Books II and III (With Certain Passages from Book I). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hippocrates, . (1983). Art of healing. In Lloyd, G. E. R., Hippocratic Writings. New York, NY: Penguin. (Original work from third century BCE.)Google Scholar
Jager, M. and VanHoorn, W. (1972). Aristotle's opinion on perception in general. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 8, 321–327.3.0.CO;2-M>CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jones, W. H. S. (1923). Hippocrates. (Vol. 1.) New York, NY: Putnam.Google Scholar
Kirk, G. S., Raven, J. E., and Schofield, M. (1983). The Presocratic Philosophers: A Critical History with a Selection of Texts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1964). Experiment in early Greek philosophy and medicine. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, n.s., 10, 50–72.CrossRef
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1991). Methods and Problems in Greek Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lovejoy, A. O. (1936). The Great Chain of Being. Harvard, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. and Putnam, H. (1992). Changing Aristotle's mind. In Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle's De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Pivnicki, D. (1969). The beginnings of psychotherapy. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 5, 238–247.3.0.CO;2-7>CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Walker, C. E. (Ed.) (1991). Clinical Psychology: Historical and Research Foundations. New York, NY: Plenum.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkes, K. V.(1992). Psyche versus the mind. In Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (Eds.), Essays on Aristotle's De Anima. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×